Skip to main content

A Pragmatic and Philosophical Examination of Everett’s Claims About Pirahã

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Formal Models in the Study of Language

Abstract

This paper discusses Everett’s (Curr Anthropol 46(4):621–646, 2005) claim that Pirahã lacks words for the existential and the universal quantifiers. Everett bases his argument on his analysis of the word báasio (the prima facie universal quantifier in Pirahã) in an example in which the word is used when the main part of an object or set is concerned rather than the whole. This, or so Everett claims, would be dishonest, given the norms of language use, if báasio meant all. According to him, this is enough to show that báasio cannot be the universal quantifier. However, Everett’s argument entirely neglects the possibility that in such a case báasio could be used non-literally (in an hyperbolic way), just as all can be in English. I conclude that Everett fails to show that báasio is not the universal quantifier in Pirahã.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Radical translation is illustrated by the following situation: a linguist (by which Quine meant a field linguist) is dropped in a tribe where the language spoken has never been described before and for which there is no interpreter. In other words, the linguist has to understand what he is told without any reliance on semantic equivalences between this language and a known language and without the means to ask questions. Basically, she finds herself without any resources apart from the speakers’ utterances and the situations in which they are produced. Interestingly, according to Everett (2008), this was precisely his situation when he first went to the Pirahãs.

  2. 2.

    He probably would not agree anymore than I do with meaning skepticism, even when limited in this way, though.

  3. 3.

    As we will see, he does not even discuss the existence of the other quantifiers, apparently thinking that the (supposed) non-existence of the universal quantifier naturally extends to the other quantifiers.

  4. 4.

    I should point out that, since then, various comments (see, e.g., Watumull et al. 2014) have pointed out that the hypothesis proposed by Hauser, Chomsky and Fitch did not imply that all languages would be recursive, merely that recursion was a central feature of language (vs. of languages). Whether this is right or not is immaterial to the present paper. But Everett’s claim was the operational factor in his overnight fame.

  5. 5.

    And with which I strongly disagree for reasons that are not without relevance to the present paper (Reboul forthcoming).

  6. 6.

    Also called pragmatic intrusion, in Levinson (2000).

  7. 7.

    Note that the fact that norms enjoining the speaker to use words only in their conventional meaning are implausible does not mean that in tropes or in loose use, conventional meaning does not have a role to play (for a discussion, centering on metaphor, see Reboul 2014).

  8. 8.

    Also known as linguistic relativism.

  9. 9.

    For a discussion of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis in the domain of color (concluding that it enjoys support only on a trivial reading), see Reboul (2015).

  10. 10.

    It should be noted that Whorf played a less than savory role in the birth of the Great Eskimo Hoax, having apparently failed to see that, if anything, it contradicts rather than supports linguistic relativity (the causal direction—from environment to culture—is the reverse of what it is in linguistic relativity).

  11. 11.

    As well as the poverty of the Pirahã culture, described by Everett as lacking creation myths and rituals, and as extremely restricted in technology.

  12. 12.

    The supposed syntactic "lacks" have been discussed (and largely dismissed) by Nevins et al. (2009a, b).

  13. 13.

    As said above, given that Everett’s description is imprecise, we cannot be sure.

  14. 14.

    It should be pointed out that it is not clear how weak effability could apply to quantities in a language such as Pirahā that (truly) lacks cardinals: how can you say that the boy has shot all his arrows when you have neither quantifiers nor cardinals?

  15. 15.

    Though that is debatable, see Reboul (2012).

References

  • Carston R (2002) Thoughts and utterances: the pragmatics of explicit communication. Blackwell, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Everett DL (2005) Cultural constraints on grammar and cognition in Pirahã. Curr Anthropol 46(4):621–646

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everett DL (2008) Don’t sleep, there are snakes: life and language in the Amazonian jungle. Random House LLC, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett DL (2012) Response to Reboul: between cognition, communication, and culture. Pragmat Cogn 20(2):392–407

    Google Scholar 

  • Glüer K, Wikforss A (2010) The normativity of meaning and content. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/meaning-normativity/. Accessed 2 Oct 2014

  • Hauser MD, Chomsky N, Fitch WT (2002) The faculty of language: what is it, who has it, and how did it evolve? Science 298(5598):1569–1579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn LR (2004) Implicature. In: Horn LR, Ward G (eds) The handbook of pragmatics. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 3–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson SC (2000) Presumptive meanings: the theory of generalized conversational implicature. MIT press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin L (1986) Eskimo words for snow: a case study in the genesis and decay of an anthropological example. Am Anthropol 88:418–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moeschler J (2007) Why are there no negative particulars? Horn’s conjecture revisited. Generative Grammar Geneva 5:1–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Nevins A, Pesetsky D, Rodrigues C (2009a) Pirahã exceptionality: a reassessment. Language 85(2):355–404

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nevins A, Pesetsky D, Rodrigues C (2009b) Evidence and argumentation: a reply to Everett. Language 85(3):671–681

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pullum GK (1989) The great Eskimo vocabulary hoax. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 7:275–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (2013) Word and object. The MIT press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Reboul A (2012) Language: between cognition, communication and culture. Pragmat Cogn 20(2):295–316

    Google Scholar 

  • Reboul A (2014) Live metaphors. In: Reboul A (ed) Mind, values and metaphysics: philosophical essays in honor of Kevin Mullligan, vol 2. Springer, Cham/Heidelberg/New York/London, pp 503–515

    Google Scholar 

  • Reboul A (2015) A new look on the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis on colours, based on neuroscientific data. In: Boguschevskaya V (ed) Thinking colours: perception, translation and representation. Cambridge Scholar Publishing, Cambridge, pp 2–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Reboul A (forthcoming) Can there be linguistic norms? In: Bayertz K, Roughley N (eds) The normative animal? On the anthropological significance of social, moral and linguistic norms. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Fintel K, Matthewson L (2008) Universals in semantics. Linguist Rev (1–2):39–201

    Google Scholar 

  • Watumull J, Hauser MD, Roberts I, Hornstein N (2014) On recursion. Front Psychol 4: Article 1017

    Google Scholar 

  • Wierzbicka A (2005) Peer comment. Curr Anthropol 46(4):641

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anne Reboul .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Reboul, A. (2017). A Pragmatic and Philosophical Examination of Everett’s Claims About Pirahã. In: Blochowiak, J., Grisot, C., Durrleman, S., Laenzlinger, C. (eds) Formal Models in the Study of Language. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-48832-5_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-48832-5_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-48831-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-48832-5

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics