Skip to main content

Beauty and the Sense of Life

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Artistic Visions and the Promise of Beauty
  • 555 Accesses

Abstract

The Hegelian notion of the end of art presupposes his totalizing account of world history. Hegel’s historical vision is inadequate because it fails to recognize that cultures have had different specific goals for art, and that they have not all aimed at the transparent realism that Hegel admires. His relegation of art to a less prominent role than hitherto also amounts to a demotion of beauty from its earlier spiritual role, through art, of guiding humanity to greater collective self-awareness. Hegel underemphasizes another spiritual function of beauty, its role in furthering our sense of life and enabling us to take joy in our own vitality. A recognition of this function of beauty is better able to reflect diverse cultural conceptions of beauty and spirituality than does Hegel’s account. It also suggests a partial explanation of the widespread phenomenon of turning to beauty in contexts of loss and mourning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We should note that Geist, rendered as “Spirit” in most translations of Hegel, means “mind” as well as “spirit.” The intellectual cast of Hegel’s Geist is thus completely in keeping with the denotations of the term he uses. In English, however, “spirit” and “mind” are not so clearly linked. “Mind” is sometimes used with the meaning of the “thinking” faculty devoid of affect (as if there were such a thing), while “spirit” tends to have affective connotations, even if they tend to be a bit rarified and “pure.” “Mind” can also be used to refer to the psyche, or soul, as a whole. This latter usage is closer to Hegel’s Geist than the former.

  2. 2.

    One might argue that David Hume comes much closer to Indian theory than Aristotle, with his notion of a peculiarly aesthetic emotion. (See Hume 1963). Hume does differentiate the emotion prompted by beautiful art from that occurring in other contexts; however, his aesthetic emotion is quite different from the Indian rasa, which occurs as a result of a transformed spiritual state in the audience member. Hume’s aesthetic emotion by contrast seems to be an everyday emotional state, albeit one that occurs in the particular context of enjoying an artwork. Nothing about it seems to involve or require the competent audience member’s achievement of an inner transformation as a consequence of experiencing aesthetic emotion.

  3. 3.

    Abhinava acknowledges (and is our major source of knowledge about) the aesthetic views of other important aesthetic theorists with whom he disagreed. Bhaṭṭa Lollaṭa, for example, claimed that rasa was only an intensified experience of a durable bhāva.

  4. 4.

    We should note, however, that Indian theorists did not all agree on the importance of dhvani. Bhaṭṭanāyaka, for example, endeavored to undermine the notion.

  5. 5.

    Armstrong is not alone in regarding the term “art” as problematic. See, for example, Shiner 2001. One certainly can use the term in an ethnocentric way, and we should be vigilant in trying to avoid insisting that one’s own culture sets the standard in this or any other type of human practice. Nevertheless, I think that widespread parallels among human practices justify use of generic terms in reference to them, so long as one acknowledges an array of differences in specific cultural attitudes and implementations. Ellen Dissanayake offers one interesting account of the common denominator of artistic practices, broadly understood. See Dissanayake 2000.

  6. 6.

    This suggests that when attempting to generalize beyond a given culture, philosophers should not insist on analytic precision since this will typically make their terms less serviceable.

  7. 7.

    For a thoughtful discussion of refined emotional responses, which may occur in connection with art, see Nico H. Frijda and Louise Sundararajan (2007).

  8. 8.

    Pater is actually talking about philosophy as well as art, but he seems particularly to have in mind a broad philosophical approach to life and what surrounds us:

    The service of philosophy, of speculative culture, towards the human spirit, is to rouse, to startle it to a life of constant and eager observation. Every moment some form grows perfect in hand or face; some tone on the hills or the sea is choicer than the rest; some mood of passion or insight or intellectual excitement is irresistibly real and attractive to us, for that moment only. Not the fruit of experience, but experience itself, is the end. A counted number of pulses only is given to us of a variegated, dramatic life. How may we see in them all that is to be seen in them by the finest senses? How shall we pass most swiftly from point to point, and be present always at the focus where the greatest number of vital forces unite in their purest energy? To burn always with this hard, gemlike flame, to maintain this ecstasy, is success in life.

    I am arguing that beauty, more directly than abstract speculation, provokes eager observation and awareness of vital forces united in the manner Pater describes, although the experience of beauty can be calm in a way that Pater’s term “quickened” does not capture.

  9. 9.

    While the sense of life is quickened by beauty, the pulse is not necessarily sped up, not, at least, for a sustained amount of time. Experiences of the beautiful include those in which it is steadied into a kind of repose.

  10. 10.

    At least not to the same high degree, though I grant that my description of typical features of this sense are shaped by my cultural background.

  11. 11.

    My thanks to Anjolie Ela Menon for pointing out to me the “unbeautiful” character of certain cultures’ funerary ceremonies.

  12. 12.

    This point that is somewhat akin to the reasoning of Abhinavagupta. See Abhinavagupta 1990, 1.5, 115.

References

  • Abhinavagupta. 1990. Locana. In The “Dhvanyāloka” of Ānandavardhana with the “ Locana” of Abhinavagupta. Trans. Daniel H. H. Ingalls, Jeffrey Moussaieff Masson, and M. V. Patwardhan, ed. Daniel H. H. Ingalls. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1941. De poetica (Poetics). In The basic works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, Trans. Ingram Bywater, 1453–1487. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, Robert Plant. 1971. The affecting presence: An essay in humanistic anthropology. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bharata-Muni (ascribed). 1969. The Nāṭyaśāstra, VI.31–33. Trans. Manomohan Ghosh, rev 2nd ed. Calcutta: Granthalaya.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danto, Arthur C. 1981. The transfiguration of the commonplace: A philosophy of art. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danto, Arthur C. 1987. Approaching the end of art. In The state of the art. New York: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danto, Arthur C. 2003. The abuse of beauty: Aesthetics and the concept of art, The Paul Carus lectures 21. Chicago and La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dissanayake, Ellen. 2000. Art and intimacy: How the arts began. Seattle: University of Washington Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, Nico H. 2006. The laws of emotion. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, Nico H., and Louis Sundararajan. 2007. Emotion refinement: A theory inspired by Chinese poetics. Perspectives on Psychological Science 2: 227–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goswamy, B.N. 1986. Rasa: Delight of the reason. In Essence of Indian art, 17–30. San Francisco: Asian Art Museum of San Francisco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 1975. Aesthetics: Lectures on fine art. Trans. T.M. Knox. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 1977. Phenomenology of spirit. Trans. A.V. Miller. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hsün Tzu. 1963. Basic writings. Trans. Burton Watson. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1963. Of the standard of taste. In Essays moral, political and literary, 231–255. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingalls, Daniel H. H. 1990. Introduction. In The Dhvanyāloka of Ānandavardhana with the Locana of Abhinavagupta. Trans. Daniel H. H. Ingalls, Jeffrey Moussaieff Masson, and M. V. Patwardhan, ed. Daniel H. H. Ingalls. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1987. Critique of judgment. Trans. Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keene, Donald. 1969. Japanese aesthetics. Philosophy East and West 19: 293–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masson, Jeffrey Moussaieff, and M.V. Patwardhan. 1970. Aesthetic rapture: The Rasadhyaya of the Natyasastra, vol. 2. Poona: Deccan College.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCracken, Janet. 2001. Taste and the household: The domestic esthetic. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCracken, Janet. 2005. Falsely, sanely, shallowly: Reflections on the special character of grief. International Journal of Applied Philosophy 19: 139–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1966. Thus spoke Zarathustra. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1968. Twilight of the Idols [together with the Anti-Christ]. Trans. R.J. Hollingdale. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pater, Walter. 1919. The renaissance. New York: Boni and Liveright.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarry, Elaine. 1999. On beauty and being just. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, Arthur. 1966. The world as will and representation, vol. 1. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiner, Larry. 2001. The invention of art: A cultural history. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kathleen M. Higgins .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Higgins, K.M. (2017). Beauty and the Sense of Life. In: Higgins, K., Maira, S., Sikka, S. (eds) Artistic Visions and the Promise of Beauty. Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures, vol 16. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-43893-1_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics