Skip to main content

Presuppositions as Cancellable Inferences

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Pragmemes and Theories of Language Use

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 9))

Abstract

The phenomenon of presupposition suspension can be analyzed in terms of explicatures and the corresponding non-presumptive interpretative reasoning underlying it. On the view presented in this paper, the polyphonic articulation of an utterance at different levels can be used to explain cases in which presuppositions are suspended. Presuppositional suspensions indicate that the presumptive reading does not hold and a different interpretation is needed. Utterances can display various types of polyphonic structures, accounting for the speaker’s and the hearer’s commitments. A speaker can be held directly responsible for what he says, but he is committed only indirectly to what he presupposes, i.e. what is uttered by a second voice (the second utterer or enunciator) representing what the common opinion accepts to be true. The reconstruction of the pragmatic structure of an utterance is guided by a complex type of reasoning, which can be represented as an argumentative abductive pattern, grounded on hierarchies of presumptions. By comparing the possible presumptions associated with the explicit meaning and the contextual information, the hearer can find a best possible explanation of the intended effect of the utterance.

Fabrizio Macagno would like to thank the Fundação para a Ciências e a Tecnologia for the research grants no. IF/00945/2013, PTDC/IVC-HFC/1817/2014, and PTDC/MHC-FIL/0521/2014.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As Jaszczolt (2010) claims, “Since the rise of radical pragmatics in the late 1970s, semantics has begun to grow to include not only the study of the meaning of the sentence, but also those aspects of meaning intended by the author (speaker, writer) of this sentence which transform sentence meaning into the speaker’s intended, explicit meaning or what is said.”

  2. 2.

    Carston believes that in general the logical form cannot be equated with a full proposition, but we may concede that in a number of cases a minimal proposition is projected by a logical form.

  3. 3.

    An explicature concerns the specific logical form of the proposition expressed by an utterance within a specific context. In this sense, an utterance takenout-of-context can be enriched only potentially with explicatures (Capone 2009). The potential explicature of (1): “Today it is raining” is “It is raining [HERE];” however, this explicature does not conflict with (1*):“Today it is raining, but not here.” (1*) is simply a different utterance, and is perfectly consistent with an interpretation in which there is no explicature and thus “but not here” does not cancel anything.

  4. 4.

    As an extreme case, I could think of someone who is compelled to smoke, without his having such an intention; however, since he does not have this intention, he cannot stop smoking: as soon as the cigarette is pulled out of his mouth, he is no longer smoking, which is different from stopping smoking a cigarette.

  5. 5.

    Retrieved from: http://sequentialcrush.blogspot.pt/2013/04/i-know-you-are-dying-to-know-truth.html

  6. 6.

    Adapted from: https://books.google.pt/books?id=4kq1qgBBsMIC&pg=PA179&lpg=PA179&dq=%22she+stopped++smoking%22+never+smoked&source=bl&ots=2C-he54RdO&sig=s4HGi1ShomltgFhY2ZZ7yRNK_MA&hl=it&sa=X&ei=zs8GVZf6E4HkUJi6g9AE&ved=0CEEQ6AEwBQ#v=onepage&q=%22she%20stopped%20%20smoking%22%20never%20smoked&f=false

  7. 7.

    “Je signalerai enfin une perspective particulièrement prometteuse qui s’ouvre dès qu’on considère le sens comme un représentation de l’énonciation, représentation consistant notamment à y faire entendre la voix de divers énonciateurs s’adressant à divers destinataires et à identifier ces rôles illocutionnaires avec des personnages qui peuvent être, entre autres, ceux de l’énonciation. Il s’agit de la construction, dans le discours, du locuteur et de l’allocutaire. Psycho- et socio-linguistes ont quelquefois noté […] que l’on peut, en parlant, constituer une image de soi et de la personne à qui l’on parle, image que l’interlocuteur tantôt accepte et tantôt rejette. Un des principaux moyens de cette constitution est justement la possibilité, inscrite selon nous dans la langue, c'est-à-dire dans la signification des mots et des phrases, de faire s’exprimer différentes voix, en donnant l’instruction de les identifier à des êtres de la réalité –et en spécifiant même certaines contraintes à observer dans cette identification” (Ducrot 1980: 56).

  8. 8.

    This non-presumptive reasoning can be also interpreted as a case of a parasitic use. The use is tolerated, despite the fact that it is ungrammatical. Yet Italians, in informal speech, do not perceive it as ungrammatical. Certainly there is ambivalence in usage and it is possible that in some contexts stronger meanings are accessed, while in other contexts (especially the least formal ones) the weaker meanings prevail. However, even on the TV programs and the news the weaker forms of “sapere” are attested. They are certainly used in a sense that is different from that of the English verb “to know.” Although the philosophical literature attests the use of “John knows that p but not p,” it only concedes that this is a parasitic, tolerated but ungrammatical usage.

  9. 9.

    The Italian clitics tend to implicate that a proposition embedded in “sapere” (but also in other verbs such as “sentire,” “capire,” “immaginare,” “dire”) is true or anyway accepted by the speaker (and shared with the hearer). These seem to us to be uncontroversial cases where a presupposition is conversationally implicated. Now, apart from the case of “sapere,” where the presupposition is entailed and implicated (in the sense that loose, parasitic or weaker uses of “sapere” are excluded, since factivity is strongly implied), the other verbs mentioned (in Italian) do not seem to entail the truth of the embedded proposition. Thus a definitive result has been achieved for Italian, where the notion of presupposition seems to intersect with the notion of conversational implicature. Here the further problem that clitics usually tend to promote strong factive readings through inferences that appear to be not cancellable is resolved thanks to Capone’s previous considerations on the cancellability of explicatures/implicatures, not to mention the fact that contextual variation can prove that we are faced with conversational implicatures (See Capone 2000 and Capone 2013b on verbs of propositional attitude combined with pronominal clitics).

  10. 10.

    As Kecskes (Forthcoming) says, “Commonalities, conventions, common beliefs, shared knowledge and the like all create a core common ground, a kind of collective salience on which intention and cooperation-based pragmatics is built. However, when this core common ground appears to be mostly missing or limited as is the case in intercultural communication interlocutors cannot take them for granted, rather they need to co-construct them, at least temporarily.”

  11. 11.

    We would like to thank Dorota Zielińska who suggested us examples 19 and 20. See Zielinska 2013.

References

  • Abbott, B. (2000). Presuppositions as nonassertions. Journal of Pragmatics, 32(10), 1419–1437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrusán, M. (2011). Predicting the presuppositions of soft triggers. Linguistics and Philosophy, 34(6), 491–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abusch, D. (2002). Lexical alternatives as a source of pragmatic presuppositions. Proceedings of SALT, 12, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allan, K. (2013). What is common ground? In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives in pragmatics, philosophy & psychology volume 2 (pp. 285–310). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, J., & Levinson, S. (1981). It-clefts, informativeness and logical form: Radical pragmatics (revised standard version). In P. Cole (Ed.), Radical pragmatics (pp. 1–62). New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakhtin, M. M. (1981). The dialogic imagination. (C. Emerson, M. Holquist, Trans.). Austin: University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakhtin, M. M. (1986). Speech genres and other late essays (V. W. McGee, Trans.). Austin: University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaver, D. (2010). Have you noticed that your belly button lint colour is related to the colour of your clothing. In Presuppositions and discourse: Essays offered to Hans Kamp (pp. 65–99). Philadelphia: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton-Roberts, N. (1989). On Horn’s dilemma: Presupposition and negation. Journal of Linguistics, 25, 95–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2000). Dilemmas and excogitations. An essay on modality, clitics and discourse. Messina: Armando Siciliano.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2001). Modal adverbs and discourse. Pisa: ETS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2005). Pragmemes. Journal of Pragmatics, 37, 1355–1371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2006). On Grice’s circle (a theory-internal problem in linguistic theories of the Gricean type). Journal of Pragmatics, 38, 645–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2009). Are explicatures cancellable? Toward a theory of the speaker’s intentionality. Intercultural Pragmatics, 6(1), 55–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2010a). On the social practice of indirect reports (further advances in the theory of pragmemes). Journal of Pragmatics, 42, 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2010b). Barack Obama’s South Carolina speech. Journal of Pragmatics, 42, 2964–2977.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2013a). Explicatures are NOT cancellable. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics, perspectives in pragmatics, philosophy & psychology (2nd ed., pp. 131–151). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2013b). The pragmatics of pronominal clitics and propositional attitudes. Intercultural Pragmatics, 10(3), 459–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1996). Metalinguistic negation and echoic use. Journal of Pragmatics, 25(3), 309–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts and utterances. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ducrot, O. (1966). Le roi de France est sage. Implication logique et Présupposition linguistique. Etudes de linguistique appliquée, 4, 39–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducrot, O. (1980). Les mots du discours. Paris: Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducrot, O. (1984). Le dire et le dit. Paris: Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, G. (1996). Pragmatics and natural meaning understanding. New York: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts (pp. 41–58). New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gundel, J., & Fretheim, T. (2004). Topic and focus. In The handbook of pragmatics (pp 175–196). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. (1970). Fallacies. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1992). Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics, 9(3), 183–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hockett, C. (1950). Peiping morphophonemics. Language, 26, 63–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Y. (2007). Pragmatics. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczolt, K. (2005). Default semantics: Foundations of a compositional theory of acts of communication. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczolt, K. (2010). Default semantics. In B. Heine & H. Narrog (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of linguistic analysis. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, J. J., & Langendoen, T. (1976). Pragmatics and presupposition. Language, 52, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kecskes, I. (2008). Dueling contexts: A dynamic model of meaning. Journal of Pragmatics, 40(3), 385–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kecskes, I. (2013). Intercultural pragmatics. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kecskes, I. (Forthcoming). Can intercultural pragmatics bring some new insight into pragmatic theories? In J. L. Mey & A. Capone (Eds.), Interdisciplinary studies in pragmatics, culture and society. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kecskes, I., & Zhang, F. (2009). Activating, seeking, and creating common ground. A socio-cognitive approach. Pragmatics & Cognition, 17(2), 331–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kecskes, I., & Zhang, F. (2013). On the dynamic relations between common ground and presupposition. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics, perspectives in pragmatics, philosophy & psychology (2nd ed., pp. 375–395). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kempson, R. (1975). Presupposition and the delimitation of semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J-B., & Sag, I. (2005) Variations in English object-extraposition. In Proceedings of the. 41st annual meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society 41, (pp. 251–265). Chicago: CLS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kissine, M. (2012). Sentences, utterances, and speech acts. In K. Allan & K. Jaszczolt (Eds.), Cambridge handbook of pragmatics (pp. 169–190). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Langendoen, T., & Savin, H. (1971). The projection problem for presuppositions. In C. J. Fillmore & D. T. Langėndoen (Eds.), Studies in linguistic semantics (pp. 54–60). New York: Irvington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. (2000). Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, F. (2012a). Presumptive reasoning in interpretation. Implicatures and conflicts of presumptions. Argumentation, 26(2), 233–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, F. (2012b). Reconstructing and assessing the conditions of meaningfulness. An argumentative approach to presupposition. In H. Ribeiro (Ed.), Inside arguments: Logic and the study of argumentation (pp. 247–268). Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, F., & Walton, D. (2013). Implicatures as forms of argument. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy (pp. 203–225). Cham: Springer International Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, F., & Walton, D. (2014). Emotive language in argumentation. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. (2008). The pragmatics of legal language. Ratio Juris, 21(4), 423–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, T. (1987). Verbs of result in the complements of raising constructions. Australian Journal of Linguistics, 7, 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mel’cuk, I. A. (1997).Vers une linguistique Sens-Texte. Leçon inaugurale, Collège de France, Chaire internationale. http://www.fas.umontreal.ca/LING/olst/FrEng/melcukColldeFr.pdf.

  • Mey, J. L. (2001). Pragmatics. An introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (2006). Presumption and the practices of tentative cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, A. O. (1980). Agent regret. In A. Rorty (Ed.), Explaining emotions (pp. 489–506). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, M. (2006). Presupposition without common ground. Unpublished manuscript, Carnegie Mellon University. Available at http://www.hss.cmu.edu/philosophy/simons/Presupposition%20without%20Common%20Ground.pdf

  • Simons, M. (2013). On the conversational basis of some presuppositions. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics, perspectives in pragmatics, philosophy & psychology (2nd ed., pp. 329–348). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1998). Mood and the analysis of non-declarative sentences. In K. Asa (Ed.), Pragmatics: Critical concepts, vol. II (pp. 262–289). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1970). Pragmatics. Synthese, 22(1–2), 272–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1973). Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2(4), 447–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1974). Pragmatic presuppositions. In M. Munitz & P. Unger (Eds.), Semantics and philosophy (pp. 197–214). New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2002). Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25, 701–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1996). Fallacies arising from ambiguity. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., & Krabbe, E. (1995). Commitment in dialogue. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (2013). The mechanism of the form-content correlation process in the paradigm of socio-natural sciences. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics (pp. 469–522). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessandro Capone .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Macagno, F., Capone, A. (2016). Presuppositions as Cancellable Inferences. In: Allan, K., Capone, A., Kecskes, I. (eds) Pragmemes and Theories of Language Use. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-43491-9_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-43491-9_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-43490-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-43491-9

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics