Skip to main content

The Philosophical Basis of Eudaimonic Psychology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being

Part of the book series: International Handbooks of Quality-of-Life ((IHQL))

Abstract

This chapter discusses the philosophical ideals animating eudaimonic psychology, arguing that eudaimonic measures of well-being reflect a reasonably coherent and defensible family of philosophical views centering on the notion of nature-fulfillment. Aristotelian theories are the best-known examples, but “eudaimonistic” views of well-being can take many forms, including the very different approach of John Stuart Mill. One goal of this chapter is to clarify the main theoretical options in this area, concerning the role of virtue in well-being; whether nature-fufillment is a matter of capacity-fulfillment or goal-fulfillment; and whether well-being is grounded entirely in the particulars of the individual’s makeup or in something else, such as species norms. A second goal is to defend eudaimonic measures, which are worth seeking regardless of our philosophical theories of well-being. The final part of the chapter sketches a “core schema for flourishing scales,” outlining the types of measures that will likely be most important to include in eudaimonic instruments, but leaving considerable room for variation. We can usefully think of the core eudaimonic insight in terms of this rough formula: happiness in a meaningful life that is rich in relationships and the free exercise of one’s capacities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 299.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    That is, eudaimonism about well-being. As noted below, this is simply a view of well-being and is distinct from, e.g., ethical eudaimonism, which takes all of ethics to be grounded in eudaimonia. Ancient eudaimonists tended to hold both views, but one could be a eudaimonist about well-being while rejecting the ancients’ effort to ground morality in the individual’s own well-being. Mill is arguably a good example of a welfare eudaimonist, though he was certainly not an ethical eudaimonist.

  2. 2.

    Perhaps the best survey of ancient eudaimonism is (Annas, 1993). Since ‘eudaimonia’ just was the ancient Greek term for well-being, rather than a term for a certain view of well-being, it is slightly odd to talk about “eudaimonistic” or “eudaimonic” theories of well-being, since one might just as well call them eudaimonistic theories of eudaimonia! I use it here to denote theories of well-being that exhibit characteristic features from the ancient tradition.

  3. 3.

    Epicureans indeed went to great lengths to argue for a strong link between well-being and virtue, but this was an (extremely bold and likely false) empirical claim. Today’s Benthamite hedonists can make it as well, if they wish, but it is no part of their philosophical theory about the nature of well-being, as it is for Aristotelians and the like.

  4. 4.

    For some recent philosophical discussions, see (Annas, 1993; Besser-Jones, 2014, 2015; Brink, 2003, 2013; Feinberg, 1992; Gewirth, 1998; Haybron, 2007, 2008a, 2008b; Hurka, 1993; Keyes & Annas, 2009; Kim, 2015; LeBar, 2013; Russell, 2013; Tiberius, 2013).

  5. 5.

    This is not to say that they don’t tacitly rely on substantial views of human nature or even eudaimonistic ideals. The point is just that they can and typically do defend their position without harnessing it to claims about what is essential to, characteristic of…human beings. For instance, you can simply point to the pleasantness of pleasant experience and say, that is what matters; and the reason it matters is simply because of its phenomenal quality. The claim that prudential value is grounded in the quality of experience is completely independent of any views about human nature, since it isn’t a claim about human beings at all. It certainly doesn’t rest on any interesting claims about human nature, the way Aristotelian theories do.

  6. 6.

    The notion of self-fulfillment seems to figure at least tacitly in many if not most modern nature-fulfillment views, for instance those of the existentialists, humanistic psychologists, and Mill. The use of this notion is made explicit in, e.g., (Haybron, 2008a, 2008b; Yelle, 2014). Complicating matters is that many authors use ‘self-fulfillment’ and similar terms loosely, as roughly equivalent to nature-fulfillment, without clearly linking them to the notion of the self. As I use the terms here, it is quite possible to hold a nature-fulfillment theory that, say, bases well-being on species norms without coupling this view in some way to an account of the self, or even thinking that there need be any such coupling. This would not be a self-fulfillment view, as understood here.

  7. 7.

    This paragraph is adapted from “Eudaimonism, Ancient, and Modern” (ms).

  8. 8.

    (Haybron, 2008a, 2008b). A seminal account of authenticity in the context of well-being is (Sumner, 1996), whose “authentic happiness” theory centers on life satisfaction and rests on a subjectivist, rather than eudaimonist, foundation.

  9. 9.

    Resourcefulness, for instance, is a virtue to which admiration would typically be a fitting response, other things equal. When put in the service of immoral aims, however, admiration might not be called for.

  10. 10.

    I am partly following Alan Gewirth here, but substituting ‘goal-fulfillment’ for ‘aspiration-fulfillment’, which has an overly narrow meaning (Gewirth, 1998), and further distinguishing perfection from the other two ideals.

  11. 11.

    There’s no consensus on exactly how to characterize the distinction between moral and nonmoral virtues. Roughly, when talking about character assessment (as opposed say to intellectual virtues), moral virtues concern at least our other-regarding obligations of, e.g., beneficence and justice, and arguably relate to how good or bad a person one is. Nonmoral virtues include, e.g. wit, resourcefulness, persistence, fortitude, grit, and concern norms that we don’t ordinarily regard as moral norms (and might indeed be expressed in immoral projects). Aristotelians are keen to emphasize that well-being for them is not simply a matter of moral virtue, but centers also on nonmoral virtues.

  12. 12.

    See especially Martha Nussbaum’s work (Nussbaum, 2000).

  13. 13.

    As noted above regarding hedonism, the question here isn’t whether a theory of human well-being could be truly independent of any view of human nature; perhaps it cannot, and indeed I suspect that hedonists and desire theorists profit from a covert reliance on eudaimonistic ideals. But we are talking about the theories as they are, not as they should be; and as they are, subjectivist accounts are typically not grounded in any appeal to selves or human nature, and so are not eudaimonistic in their structure. They lack the teleological structure of eudaimonism.

  14. 14.

    Recent defenses of value-fulfillment ideals of well-being—though not explicitly employing a eudaimonistic framework—include (Hall & Tiberius, 2015; Raibley, 2010, 2013; Tiberius, 2008, 2014). Benjamin Yelle defends an explicitly eudaimonistic value-fulfillment theory (Yelle, 2014). Accounts of the self centering on values include, e.g., (Doris, 2015; Frankfurt, 1971; Sripada, 2015; Watson, 1975; Wolf, 1993).

  15. 15.

    For discussion of the notion of self-fulfillment, see (Haybron, 2008a, 2008b).

  16. 16.

    (Nussbaum, 2011). For further discussion of these issues, see (Haybron & Tiberius, n.d.).

  17. 17.

    My other discussions of life satisfaction cited here explore these issues in much greater depth, but as some readers will likely want to push back on these claims, let me note, first, that some hedonists understand pleasure as something more like a judgment and hence akin to life satisfaction in that respect (Feldman, 2004). A standard complaint about such views is precisely that they miss their target: what they call “pleasure” is about something other than the pleasantness of one’s experience, and is not what hedonists have traditionally cared about. But even these views would have the result that Wittgenstein’s life was hedonically bad. A second objection is that suffering might preclude life satisfaction insofar as one has to feel good to truly be satisfied. The short answer is, that’s a possible view, but it isn’t what current measures, which assess judgments, are tracking; and at any rate it seems poorly motivated: feeling good is one thing, judging that you’ve achieved the things you care about, even if you don’t feel good, is quite another. Life satisfaction loses its distinctive attractions as a metric if we build very much in the way of pleasant feelings into it.

  18. 18.

    See also (Ponocny, Weismayer, Stross, & Dressler, 2015). It may be that life satisfaction reports are heavily driven by affective processes, but that is different from the question of what’s being asked of participants, and what they are doing when answering: they are being asked for a judgment about their life, and that’s what they seem to be giving. Whether the judgment is caused by rational deliberation, induced by mood, or whatever, is a different question.

  19. 19.

    For further discussion of emotional well-being, or the emotional state theory of happiness, see (Haybron, 2005, 2008b, 2013a, 2013c).

  20. 20.

    I explore this suggestion in (Haybron, n.d.-a). A difficulty with the “Millian” label is that Mill’s better-known discussion of well-being in Utilitarianism distinguishes pleasures by a metric of “quality,” and it is not clear that this view is really subject-dependent. But his discussion of individuality in On Liberty is arguably one of the finest articulations of a subject-dependent ideal of well-being.

References

  • Annas, J. (1993). The morality of happiness. New York: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Badhwar, N. K. (2014). Well-being: Happiness in a worthwhile life. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Besser-Jones, L. (2014). Eudaimonic ethics: The philosophy and psychology of living well. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Besser-Jones, L. (2015). Eudaimonism. In G. Fletcher (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of well-being (pp. 187–196). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradford, G. (2015). Achievement. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. O. (2003). Perfectionism and the common good: Themes in the philosophy of T.H. green. New York: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. O. (2013). Mill’s progressive principles. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chirkov, V. I., Ryan, R. M., Kim, Y., Kaplan, U. (2003). Differentiating autonomy from individualism and independence: A self-determination theory perspective on internalization of cultural orientations and well-being., 84(1), 97–110. http://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.84.1.97

    Google Scholar 

  • Chirkov, V. I., Sheldon, K. M., Ryan, R. M., Chirkov, V. I., Ryan, R. M., & Sheldon, K. M. (2010). Cross-cultural advancements in positive psychology (Vol. 1). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R. (2005). Well-being. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/well-being/

  • Darwall, S. (2002). Welfare and rational care. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., Inglehart, R., & Tay, L. (2012). Theory and validity of life satisfaction scales. Social Indicators Research, 112, 497–527. doi:10.1007/s11205-012-0076-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., Wirtz, D., Tov, W., Kim-Prieto, C., Oishi, S., & Biswas-Diener, R. (2009). New well-being measures: Short scales to assess flourishing and positive and negative feelings. Social Indicators Research, 97(2), 143–156. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-009-9493-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2015). Talking to our selves, 1–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1983). Sour grapes. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1992). Absurd self-fulfillment. In J. Feinberg (Ed.), Freedom and fulfillment (pp. 297–330). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (2004). Pleasure and the good life. New York: Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth, A. (1998). Self-fulfillment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glatzer, W. (1991). Quality of life in advanced industrialized countries: The case of West Germany. In F. Strack, M. Argyle, & N. Schwarz (Eds.), Subjective well-being (pp. 261–279). Elmsford, NY: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, A., & Tiberius, V. (2015). Well-being and subject dependence. In G. Fletcher (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of well-being (pp. 175–186). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2001). Happiness and pleasure. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), 501–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2005). On being happy or unhappy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(2), 287–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2007). Well-being and virtue. Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy, II(2), i.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2008a). The pursuit of unhappiness: The elusive psychology of well-being. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2008b). Happiness, the self and human flourishing. Utilitas, 20(01). http://doi.org/10.1017/S0953820807002889

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2011). Taking the satisfaction (and the life) out of life satisfaction. Philosophical Explorations, 14(3), 249–262. http://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2011.594959.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2013a). Happiness: A very short introduction. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2013b). The nature and significance of happiness. In I. Boniwell & S. David (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of happiness. New York: Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2013c). The value of positive emotion: Philosophical doubts and reassurances, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (n.d.-a). Eudaimonism, ancient and modern.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (n.d.-b). Mental state approaches to well-being. In M. D. Adler & M. Fleurbaey (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of well-being and public policy. New York: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M., & Tiberius, V. (n.d.). Well-being policy: What standard of well-being? Journal of the American Philosophical Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huppert, F. A., & So, T. T. C. (2011). Flourishing across Europe: Application of a new conceptual framework for defining well-being. Social Indicators Research. doi:10.1007/s11205-011-9966-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (1993). Perfectionism. New York: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (2010). The best things in life: A guide to what really matters. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kesebir, P., & Diener, E. (2014). In N. E. Snow & F. V. Trivigno (Eds.), A virtuous cycle: The relationship between happiness and virtue (pp. 287–306). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M. (2002). The mental health continuum: From languishing to flourishing in life. Journal of Health and Social Behavior, 207–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M. (2007). Promoting and protecting mental health as flourishing: A complementary strategy for improving national mental health. American Psychologist, 62(2), 95–108. http://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.62.2.95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keyes, C. L. M., & Annas, J. (2009). Feeling good and functioning well: Distinctive concepts in ancient philosophy and contemporary science. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 4(3), 197–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, R. (2015). Well-being and confucianism. In G. Fletcher (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of well-being (pp. 40–55). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeBar, M. (2013). The value of living well. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2000). Women and human development: The capabilities approach. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2011). Perfectionist liberalism and political liberalism. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 39(1), 3–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ponocny, I., Weismayer, C., Stross, B., & Dressler, S. G. (2015). Are most people happy? Exploring the meaning of subjective well-being ratings. Journal of Happiness Studies, 1–19. http://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-015-9710-0

    Google Scholar 

  • Raibley, J. (2010). Well-being and the priority of values. Social Theory & Practice, 36(4), 593–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raibley, J. R. (2013). Values, agency, and welfare. Philosophical Topics, 41(1), 187–214. http://doi.org/10.5840/philtopics20134119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricard, M. (2015). Altruism: The power of compassion to change yourself and the world. New York: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. (2013). Happiness for humans. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2001). On happiness and human potentials: A review of research on hedonic and eudaimonic well-being. Annual Review of Psychology, 52(1), 141–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, R. M., Huta, V., & Deci, E. L. (2008). Living well: A self-determination theory perspective on eudaimonia. Journal of Happiness Studies, 9(1), 139–170. http://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-006-9023-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryff, C. D. (1989). Happiness is everything, or is it? Explorations on the meaning of psychological well-being 57(6), 1069.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryff, C. D., & Singer, B. (1998). The contours of positive human health, 9(1), 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryff, C. D., & Singer, B. H. (2008). Know thyself and become what you are: A Eudaimonic approach to psychological well-being. Journal of Happiness Studies, 9(1), 13–39. http://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-006-9019-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schimmack, U., & Oishi, S. (2005). The influence of chronically and temporarily accessible information on life satisfaction judgments 89(3), 395–406. http://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.89.3.395

    Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, M. (2011). Flourish: A visionary new understanding of happiness and well-being. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1987). On ethics and economics. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C. (2015). Self-expression: A deep self theory of moral responsibility.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sumner, L. W. W. (1996). Welfare, happiness, and ethics. New York: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V. (2008). The reflective life: Living wisely with our limits. New York: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V. (2013). Recipes for a good life: Eudaimonism and the contribution of philosophy. In A. S. Waterman (Ed.), The best within us: Positive psychology perspectives on Eudaimonia (pp. 19–38). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V. (2014). How theories of well-being can help us help. Journal of Practical Ethics, 2(2), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waterman, A. S. (1993). Two conceptions of happiness: Contrasts of personal expressiveness (eudaimonia) and hedonic enjoyment., 64(4), 678.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waterman, A. S. (2013). The best within us: Positive psychology perspectives on eudaimonia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waterman, A. S., Schwartz, S. J., & Conti, R. (2008). The implications of two conceptions of happiness (hedonic enjoyment and eudaimonia) for the understanding of intrinsic motivation. Journal of Happiness Studies, 9(1), 41–79. http://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-006-9020-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. (1975). Free agency. Journal of Philosophy, 72(8), 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, M. P., & Dolan, P. (2009). Accounting for the richness of daily activities. Psychological Science, 20(8), 1000–1008. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2009.02392.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1993). Freedom within reason. Oxford University Press, Incorporated.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (2010). Meaning in life and why it matters. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (2014). The variety of values: Essays on morality, meaning, and love (1st ed.). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yelle, B. (2014). Alienation, deprivation, and the well-being of persons. Utilitas, 26(04), 367–384. http://doi.org/10.1017/S095382081400017X.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel M. Haybron .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Haybron, D.M. (2016). The Philosophical Basis of Eudaimonic Psychology. In: Vittersø, J. (eds) Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being. International Handbooks of Quality-of-Life. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-42445-3_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-42445-3_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-42443-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-42445-3

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics