Skip to main content

Analysing Practical Argumentation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis

Part of the book series: Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning ((LARI,volume 10))

Abstract

Argument analysis is a powerful tool for structuring policy deliberation and decision-making, especially when complexity and uncertainty loom large. Argument analysis seeks to determine which claims are justified or criticized by a given argumentation, how strong an argument is, on which implicit assumptions it rests, how it relates to other arguments in a controversy, and which standpoints one can reasonably adopt in view of a given state of debate. This chapter first gives an overview of the activities involved in argument analysis and discusses the various aims that guide argument analysis. It then introduces methods for reconstructing and evaluating individual arguments as well as complex argumentation and debates. In their application to decisions under great uncertainty, these methods help to identify coherent positions, to discern important points of (dis)agreement, as well as to avoid spurious consensus and oversimplification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    An “argumentative turn” in policy analysis and planning had first been proclaimed by Fisher and Forester (1993), who called for putting more emphasis on deliberative and communicative elements in decision making (see also Fischer and Gottweis 2012). We conceive of our chapter, and this book in general, as a genuinely normative, argumentation-theoretic contribution to – and extension of – the programme of an argumentative turn, which was so far mainly shaped by the perspectives of political science and empirical discourse analysis.

  2. 2.

    For examples, see Singer (1988:157–9).

  3. 3.

    We freely draw on our earlier work, specifically Brun (2014), Brun and Hirsch Hadorn (2014), Betz (2013), and Betz (2010).

  4. 4.

    We use “debate” in a sense which does not necessarily involve more than one person. One can “internalize” proponents of various positions and explore how they can argue against each other.

  5. 5.

    Sometimes “serial” or “subordinate” are used in place of “hierarchical”, and “convergent” in place of “multiple”. See Snoeck Henkemans (2001) a survey on terminology and basic structures of complex argumentation.

  6. 6.

    We use “inference” as a technical term for completely explicit and well-ordered arguments.

  7. 7.

    See Walton (1996:211–6); for a more comprehensive discussion of hermeneutical principles in the context of argument analysis see Reinmuth (2014).

  8. 8.

    On various aspects of clarification see also Morscher (2009:1–58) and Hansson (2000).

  9. 9.

    With p corresponding to “the animal is like us”, q to “there is no reason for performing the experiment” and r to “we ought not to perform on the animal an experiment that would be considered outrageous if performed on one of us.”

  10. 10.

    Of course, reconstructing enthymemes does not rest on the highly dubious idea that all implicit information should be made explicit. Even complete arguments virtually always involve a great deal of presuppositions. That the premise “The 2-degree-target can no longer be achieved”, as well as its negation, imply “Reaching the 2-degree-target is not impossible at every point in time” does not mean that the latter sentence should be reconstructed as an additional premise.

  11. 11.

    In fact, missing conclusions are often neglected in the literature.

    One alternative to the traditional approach relies on argument schemes and adds the elements needed to turn the argument at hand into an instance of such a scheme (Paglieri and Woods 2011). Another idea is to interpret arguments against the background of a belief-state ascribed to its author and deal with “incomplete” arguments by revising the ascribed belief state (Brun and Rott 2013).

  12. 12.

    This presupposes that charity is interpreted as a presumptive principle, not merely a tie-breaker.

    As Jacquette (1996) has pointed out, adding a premise is in some cases less charitable than strengthening a premise or weakening the conclusion.

  13. 13.

    Sentence S is logically stronger than sentence T (and T is logically weaker than S) just in case S implies T but not vice versa.

  14. 14.

    Other inconsistencies, e.g. inconsistency of a premise with known facts of science, are just a reason for assessing the premise in question as false.

  15. 15.

    In an undercut argument, the proponent (who puts forward the argument) uses premises which the opponent accepts to infer a conclusion which the opponent denies. See Betz (2013) for a typology of dialectical moves.

  16. 16.

    The distinction between deductive and non-deductive primarily applies to standards of evaluation and only derivatively to arguments. An arguments can then be called “deductive” either because it is meant or taken to be evaluated by deductive standards, or because it performs well with respect to deductive standards. (Skyrms 2000:ch. II.4).

  17. 17.

    In this chapter, we use “validity” simpliciter as an abbreviation for “deductive validity”; in the literature it often also abbreviates “formal validity”.

  18. 18.

    Lumer (2011) explains how argumentation schemes can be exploited for deductivist reconstructions.

  19. 19.

    There is a rich literature on fallacies; see section Resources. For specific fallacies in argumentation about risk, see Hansson (2016).

  20. 20.

    Harsanyi offers further considerations which may dispel the straw-man worry in the text that follows what we quoted as [Harsanyi].

  21. 21.

    This is a restricted perspective since there are other types of non-descriptive sentences as well, for example those which include evaluative terms (“good”, “better”). For a more precise and sophisticated discussion (using a different terminology), see Morscher (2013).

  22. 22.

    Strictly speaking, this is only true for practical arguments in which every premise and the conclusion either is entirely in the scope of a deontic modality or does not contain any deontic modality. The situation is much more complex if for practical arguments which include “mixed” sentences; that is, sentences only part of which are in the scope of a deontic modality. See Morscher (2013) for an accessible discussion.

  23. 23.

    Pollock (1987:485) distinguishes two further dialectic relations. An argument rebuts another argument if the arguments possess contradictory (or at least contrary) conclusions; an argument undercuts another argument if it questions the validity or applicability of an inference scheme applied in the latter. (Note that this is another use of “undercut” than in footnote 15.) The undercut relation is, however, not directly relevant in the framework we propose here. Validity of the individual arguments is guaranteed qua charitable reconstruction. Rather than using controversial inference schemes for the reconstruction, we suggest to add corresponding general premises that can be criticized. Pollock’s undercut-relation hence effectively reduces to the attack relation.

  24. 24.

    The proper analysis and evaluation of non-deductive reasoning poses serious theoretical problems and goes beyond the scope of this chapter. For a comprehensive state-of-the-art presentation compare Spohn (2012).

  25. 25.

    A prominent rival approach to the one presented in this chapter are Dung-style evaluation methods for complex argumentation, which have been developed in Artificial Intelligence over the last two decades (see Bench-Capon and Dunne 2007; Dung 1995). Dung-style evaluation methods impose far-reaching rationality constraints; e.g. non-attacked arguments must be accepted, and undefended arguments must not be accepted. According to the approach championed in this chapter, in contrast, any argument can be reasonably accepted, as long as the proponent is willing to give up sufficiently many beliefs (and other arguments).

  26. 26.

    Sometimes one and the same (“prima facie”) normative principle, when applied to a complex decision situation, gives rise to conflicting implications. This is paradigmatically the case in dilemmatic situations, where one violates a given norm no matter what one does. In argument-mapping terms: given all descriptive premises are accepted, there is no coherent position according to which the “prima facie” principle is true. In regard of such cases, we suggest to systematize the aggregation and balancing process through specifying the normative principle in question such that the differences between alternative choices are made explicit. E.g. rather than arguing with the principle “You must not lie” in a situation where one inevitably either lies to a stranger or to one’s grandma, one should attempt to analyze the reasoning by means of the two principles “You must not lie to relatives” and “You must not lie to strangers”, which can then be balanced against each other.

  27. 27.

    “Yes” stands for statement accepted; “no” for statement not accepted. For the sake of simplicity, we do not distinguish between denying a statement and suspending judgement.

  28. 28.

    This section is adapted from http://www.argunet.org/2013/05/13/mapping-the-climate-engineering-controversy-a-case-of-argument-analysis-driven-policy-advice/ [last accessed 16.03.2015].

  29. 29.

    On the ethics of climate engineering and the benefits of argumentative analysis in this field compare Elliott (2016).

  30. 30.

    Steele (2006) interprets the precautionary principle as a meta-principle for good decision-making which articulates essentially these two requirements.

References

  • Bench-Capon, T. J. M., & Dunne, P. E. (2007). Argumentation in artificial intelligence. Artificial Intelligence, 171, 619–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Betz, G. (2010). Theorie dialektischer Strukturen. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Betz, G. (2013). Debate dynamics: How controversy improves our beliefs. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Betz, G. (2016). Accounting for possibilities in decision making. In S. O. Hansson & G. Hirsch Hadorn (Eds.), The argumentative turn in policy analysis. Reasoning about uncertainty (pp. 135–169). Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-30549-3_6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Betz, G., & Cacean, S. (2012). Ethical aspects of climate engineering. Karlsruhe: KIT Scientific Publishing. doi:10.5445/KSP/1000028245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brun, G. (2014). Reconstructing arguments. Formalization and reflective equilibrium. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 17, 94–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brun, G., & Hirsch Hadorn, G. (2014). Textanalyse in den Wissenschaften. Inhalte und Argumente analysieren und verstehen (2nd ed.) Zürich: vdf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brun, G., & Rott, H. (2013). Interpreting enthymematic arguments using belief revision. Synthese, 190, 4041–4063.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, C. (2012). The asymmetry of formal logic. In M. Peliš & V. Punčochář (Eds.), The logica yearbook 2011 (pp. 49–62). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dung, P. M. (1995). On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning. Logic programming and n-person games. Artificial Intelligence, 77, 321–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. C. (2016). Climate geoengineering. In S. O. Hansson & G. Hirsch Hadorn (Eds.), The argumentative turn in policy analysis. Reasoning about uncertainty (pp. 305–324). Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-30549-3_13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, F., & Forester, J. (1993). The argumentative turn in policy analysis and planning. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, F., & Gottweis, H. (2012). The argumentative turn revisited. Public policy as communicative practice. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, S. M. (2006). A core precautionary principle. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 14, 33–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2000). Formalization in philosophy. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 6, 162–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2013). The ethics of risk: Ethical analysis in an uncertain world. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2016). Evaluating the uncertainties. In S. O. Hansson & G. Hirsch Hadorn (Eds.), The argumentative turn in policy analysis. Reasoning about uncertainty (pp. 79–104). Cham: Springer. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-30549-3_4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O., & Hirsch Hadorn, G. (2016). Introducing the argumentative turn in policy analysis. In S. O. Hansson & G. Hirsch Hadorn (Eds.), The argumentative turn in policy analysis. Reasoning about uncertainty (pp. 11–35). Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-30549-3_2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. C. (1975). Can the maximin principle serve as a basis for morality? A critique of John Rawls’ theory. American Political Science Review, 69, 594–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette, D. (1996). Charity and the reiteration problem for enthymemes. Informal Logic, 18, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lumer, C. (2011). Argument schemes. An epistemological approach. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Argumentation. Cognition and community. Proceedings of the 9th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), May 18–22, 2011. Windsor: University of Windsor. http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA9/papersandcommentaries/17/. Accessed 22.07.2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNamara, P. (2010). Deontic logic. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/logic-deontic/.

  • Morscher, E. (2009). Kann denn Logik Sünde sein? Die Bedeutung der modernen Logik für Theorie und Praxis des Rechts. Wien: Lit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morscher, E. (2013). How to treat naturalistic fallacies. In H. Ganthaler, C. R. Menzel, & E. Morscher (Eds.), Aktuelle Probleme und Grundlagenfragen der medizinischen Ethik (pp. 203–232). St. Augustine: Academia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri, F., & Woods, J. (2011). Enthymematic parsimony. Synthese, 178, 461–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1987). Defeasible reasoning. Cognitive Science, 11, 481–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. A theory of justice (Rev. ed.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinmuth, F. (2014). Hermeneutics, logic and reconstruction. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 17, 152–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (2001). Philosophical reasoning. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rickels, W., et al. (2011). Large-scale intentional interventions into the climate system? Assessing the climate engineering debate. Scoping report conducted on behalf of the German Federal Ministry of Education and Research (BMBF). Kiel: Kiel Earth Institute. http://www.kiel-earth-institute.de/scoping-report-climate-engineering.html?file=tl_files/media/downloads/scoping_reportCE.pdf. Accessed 22.07.2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sather, T. (1999). Pros and Cons. A debater’s handbook (18th ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. J. (1954). The foundation of statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schefczyk, M. (2016). Financial markets: the stabilisation task. In S. O. Hansson & G. Hirsch Hadorn (Eds.), The argumentative turn in policy analysis. Reasoning about uncertainty (pp. 265–290). Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-30549-3_11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1988). Ethical experts in a democracy. In D. M. Rosenthal & F. Shehadi (Eds.), Applied ethics and ethical theory (pp. 149–161). Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2002). Animal liberation (3rd ed.). New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2000). Choice and chance. An introduction to inductive logic (4th ed.). Belmont: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2001). Argumentation structures. In F. H. van Eemeren (Ed.), Crucial concepts in argumentation theory (pp. 101–134). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2012). The laws of belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steele, K. (2006). The precautionary principle: A new approach to public decision-making? Law, Probability, and Risk, 5, 19–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1992). Argumentation, communication, and fallacies: A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2004). A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1996). Argument structure. A pragmatic theory. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N., Reed, C. A., & Macagno, F. (2008). Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Georg Brun .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Resources Supporting Argument Analysis

Resources Supporting Argument Analysis

  • Bowell, Tracy, and Gary Kemp. 2015. Critical Thinking. A Concise Guide. 4th ed. London: Routledge.

Chapter 5 gives a very accessible yet reliable introduction to techniques of argument reconstruction focusing on the analysis of individual arguments and complex argumentation.

Two online tutorials focusing on analysing complex argumentation are:

A more extensive treatment of fallacies can be found in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://www.iep.utm.edu/fallacy/.

Argunet is an argument mapping software designed to support the reconstruction of complex argumentation and debates: http://www.argunet.org/.

Links were correct on 22.07.2015.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brun, G., Betz, G. (2016). Analysing Practical Argumentation. In: Hansson, S., Hirsch Hadorn, G. (eds) The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis. Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning, vol 10. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30549-3_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics