Skip to main content

Pluralism in Historiography: A Case Study of Case Studies

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 319))

Abstract

In history the same historical episodes can be reconstructed from multiple perspectives, leading to different interpretations and evaluations of the same events, and sometimes even to different factual claims. In this paper, I analyze what I call “historiographical pluralism”—situations of conflict between different case studies of the same historical episodes. I address two interrelated questions: First, which features of historical reconstruction and representation give rise to such conflicts? Second, can we assess rival historical case studies and decide between them, thus restricting historiographical pluralism? As an answer to the first question, I highlight the selective and theory-laden character of historical representation and argue that the narrative dimension of historiography is central for the knowledge that a historical case study can convey. I then go on to analyze how—in practice—disagreement about historical facts emerges. I discuss four case studies paired around two historical episodes and show that conflicts arise from the selective, theory-laden, and narrative aspects of historical methodologies. The second question I answer by discussing different criteria for assessing historical accounts. I note a dilemma in the evaluation of historical reconstructions. On the one hand, there exist neutral and almost universally accepted evaluation criteria. But these criteria are weak and cannot always decide between conflicting accounts of the same episodes. On the other hand, there are stronger methodological criteria. Alas, they are often not neutral with respect to the substantial theoretical issues at stake in situations of conflict between different historical reconstructions. I conclude that because of this dilemma, we have to accept some degree of pluralism in historiography.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Comparable issues arising within the natural sciences have been recently addressed in debates on scientific pluralism (Chang 2012; Kellert et al. 2006). Although I acknowledge that there may exist important parallels between pluralism in science and pluralism in historiography, in this paper I focus on the latter only. Note also that my aim in this paper is to provide a descriptive account of pluralism in historiography. I do not seek to answer the normative question whether historiographical pluralism is epistemically desirable or not.

  2. 2.

    I use the term “theory” broadly here, such that it includes all sorts of high-level conceptions. These conceptions need not be coherent systematic accounts; indeed, at times it may even be only single assumptions rather than elaborate theoretical constructions that are at issue. Also, I include methodological and basic philosophical commitments about the character of science and the nature of historical change among the sorts of theoretical assumptions that are relevant when talking about theory-ladenness in the historiography of science.

  3. 3.

    There is some disagreement as to whether the narrative structure of a historical account carries information, conveys knowledge and is properly representational, or whether narrative is a superfluous, merely “rhetorical” aspect of historical discourse. Different accounts of the role of narrative in historical representation have been developed by Carr (2008), Carroll (2001), White (1980). I cannot go into these debates here. However, I believe that my analysis in the next section will show that narratives do convey information about the past. In this sense, they should be seen as epistemic rather than “merely rhetorical.”

  4. 4.

    Many aspects of White’s narratological account are deeply problematic. On the one hand, his structuralist taxonomy of different modes of historical writing is static, artificial and irritatingly ahistorical. On the other hand, from insights into the constructive dimension of historiography, White draws radical conclusions about its subjective and fictional character. I share neither White’s structuralist inclinations, nor his radical subjectivism, and wish to take from his reflections only the central theses that historical accounts have a narrative structure and that there can exist plural narrative emplotments of the same historical events.

  5. 5.

    In the philosophy of science, epistemic criteria such as simplicity, variance of the evidence, surprising predictions, fruitfulness, and explanatory power are often thought to help scientists reach a verdict in situations of theory-choice. Since most of these criteria cannot be applied to historiography without difficulties, I develop my account of historiographical evaluation without substantially drawing on discussions of theory-choice in the philosophy of science.

References

  • Ashplant, T., and A. Wilson. 1988. Present-centered history and the problem of historical knowledge. The Historical Journal 31(2): 253–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bakhtin, M. 1986. The Bildungsroman and its significance in the history of realism (Toward a historical typology of the novel). In Speech Genres and other Late Essays, ed. C. Emerson, and M. Holquist, 10–59. Austin: University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, B., D. Bloor, and J. Henry. 1996. Scientific knowledge. A sociological analysis. London: Athlone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal, G. 2013. On Lavoisier’s achievement in chemistry. Centaurus 55(1): 20–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, H. 1949. The origin of modern science 1300–1800. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. 2008. Narrative explanation and its malcontents. History and Theory 47(1): 19–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, N. 2001. Interpretation, history and narrative. In Philosophical Essays, ed. Beyond Aesthetics, 133–156. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. 2009. We have never been whiggish (about Phlogiston). Centaurus 51(4): 239–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. 2012. Is water \(H_2O\) ? evidence, realism and pluralism. Dordrechtht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M. 1981. What is TRASP: The radical programme as a methodological imperative. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 11: 215–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M. 1985. Changing order: Replication and induction in scientific practice. Beverley Hills and London: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M. 1994. A strong confirmation of the experimenters’ regress. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 25(3): 493–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crombie, A.C. 1953. Robert Grosseteste and the origins of experimental science, 1100–1700. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, A. 1988. Getting the game right: Some plain words on the identity and invention of science. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 19(3): 365–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, A., and P. Williams. 1993. De-centring the ‘Big Picture’: The origins of modern science and the modern origins of science. The British Journal for the History of Science 26(4): 407–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L., and P. Galison. 2007. Objectivity. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldhay, R. 1994. Narrative constraints on historical writing. The case of the scientific revolution. Science in Context 7(1): 7–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, A. 1986. The neglect of experiment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, A. 1994. How to avoid experimenters’ regress. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 25: 463–491.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frye, N. 1957. The anatomy of criticism. Four essay. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N. 2004. How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science 71(5): 742–752.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holton, G. 1978. Subelectrons, presuppositions, and the Millikan-Ehrenhaft Dispute. Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 9: 161–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine, N. 2000. Uses and abuses of anachronism in the history of sciences. History of Science 38(3): 251–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellert, S.H., H.E. Longino, and C.K. Waters. 2006. Scientific pluralism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinzel, K. 2012. Geschichte ohne Kausalität. Abgrenzungsstrategien gegen die Wissenschaftssoziologie in zeitgenössischen Ansätzen historischer Epistemologie. Berichte zur. Wissenschaftsgeschichte 35(2): 147–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kinzel, K. 2015. Narrative and evidence. How can case studies from the history of science support claims in the philosophy of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 49: 48–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koyré, A. 1957. From the closed world to the infinite universe. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, M. 2015. Scientific pluralism and the chemical revolution. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 49: 69–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. 2011. Structural realism versus standard scientific realism: The case of phlogiston and dephlogisticated air. Synthese 180(2): 87–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindberg, D.C. 1990. Conceptions of the scientific revolution from Bacon to Butterfield: A preliminary sketch. In Reaprraisals of the Scientific Revolution, ed. D.C. Lindberg, and R.S. Westman, 1–27. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McEvoy, J. 2010. The historiography of the chemical revolution: Patterns of interpretation in the history of science. London: Pickering and Chatto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. 1976. Why did oxygen supplant phlogiston? Research programmes in the chemical revolution. In Method and appraisal in the physical sciences. The critical background to modern science, 1800–1905, ed. C. Howson, 181–210. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pomata, G. 1998. Close-Ups and long shots. Combining particular and general in writing the histories of women and men. In Geschlechtergeschichte und allgemeine Geschichte. Herausforderungen und Perspektiven, ed. H. Medick, and A.-C. Trepp, 99–124. Göttingen: Wallstein.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, R. 1986. The scientific revolution: A spoke in the wheel? In Revolution in history, ed. R. Porter, and M. Teich, 290–316. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, P.A. 1988. Narrative explanations. The case of history. History and Theory 27(1): 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sapp, J. 1990. The nine lives of Gregor Mendel. In Experimental inquiries: Historical, philosophical and social studies of experimentation in science, ed. H. Le Grand, 137–166. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Secord, J.A. 1993. Introduction to ‘The Big Picture’. The British Journal for the History of Science 26(4): 387–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S. 1998. The scientific revolution. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tosh, N. (2003). Anachronism and retrospective explanation. In Defence of a present-centered history of science. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 34(3): 647–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B.C. 2008. Scientific representation. Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • White, H. 1973. Metahistory. The historical imagination in nineteenth-century Europe. Baltimore, London: Johns Hopkins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, H. 1978. The historical text as a literary artifact. In The writing of history. literary form and historical understanding, ed. R.H. Canary, and H. Kozicki, Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, H. 1980. The value of narrativity in the representation of reality. In The content of the form. Narrative discourse and historical representation, 1–25. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yates, F.A. 1964. Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic tradition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For suggestions and comments on earlier drafts of this paper I am grateful to Martin Kusch, Veli Mitova, Martha Rössler, Katharina Bernhard, and Martin Strauss. I also want to thank the participants of the workshop “The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies” in Bern for their engaging discussions and criticism. Research leading up to this paper was made possible by grants from the Austrian Science Foundation (FWF) (“Contingency, Inevitability and Relativism in the History and Philosophy of Science”, Project no.: P25069-G18) and the European Research Council (ERC) (“The Emergence of Relativism”, Grant agreement no. 339382).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Katherina Kinzel .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kinzel, K. (2016). Pluralism in Historiography: A Case Study of Case Studies. In: Sauer, T., Scholl, R. (eds) The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 319. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30229-4_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30229-4_7

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-30227-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-30229-4

  • eBook Packages: HistoryHistory (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics