Skip to main content

John Rawls: Liberal Neutrality and Subsidizing Art

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Liberal Neutrality and State Support for Religion

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life ((BSPR,volume 5))

Abstract

Like Dworkin, Rawls allows state support for art, while at the same time arguing for state neutrality. In order to be neutral, this state support is only legitimate if there is a unanimous consensus about the value of art and about state support. However, taking into account reasonable pluralism, this consensus is an impossible aim and this is why Rawls’s argumentation is not fully convincing. In addition, he uses the concept of public goods in two distinct ways, which is rather confusing. In order to create conceptual clarity, we will make a distinction between public and nonpublic goods on one hand, and perfectionist and nonperfectionist goods on the other.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the difference between direct and indirect benefits, see e.g. Feinberg (1994). Dworkin (1985, 224 ff) also mentions that some goods are directly to someone’s advantage, while other goods are indirectly to someone’s advantage. Besides, a combination of direct and indirect benefits is also possible. Vaccination programs for instance, are in a direct way to the advantage of the vaccinated people, but at the same time, they are also in an indirect way to the advantage of non-vaccinated people. In this regard, we can speak about spillover benefits.

  2. 2.

    Rawls frequently mentions arts and humanities all together, but I will only focus on state support for art here.

  3. 3.

    It is rather confusing that Rawls uses the term ‘public goods’ here as well, even though art is not necessary to everyone’s advantage. In the next section, I will further clarify this concept of public goods and propose an alternative conceptual framework, in order to avoid further confusion.

  4. 4.

    In A Theory of Justice (§43), Rawls distinguishes five branches that are needed in order to guarantee the socio-economic conditions in a just society: the exchange branch, the allocation branch, the stabilization branch, the transfer branch and the distribution branch. Different from the last four branches, the exchange branch is not required in order to realize justice as fairness: “[…] the basis of this scheme is the benefit principle and not the principles of justice” (Rawls 1971, 283). Accordingly, there is a distinction between “the exchange budget” that can be used to support valuable goods on one hand, and “the national budget” that is used for public goods that are to everyones advantage (i.e. public goods characterized by publicness and sometimes also by non-excludability, indivisibility, and the risk of free-riding) on the other. Regarding state subsidies for art, the exchange branch seems to be the only option for Rawls.

  5. 5.

    As George Klosko (2003, 189 n.44) rightly remarks, the borders between perfectionism and neutrality are very close here.

  6. 6.

    Wicksel (1967, cited in Johnson 2010, 191) writes: “It will always be theoretically possible, and approximately so in practice, to find a distribution of costs such that all parties regard the expenditure as beneficial and may therefore approve it unanimously”.

References

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1985. Can a liberal state support art? In A matter of principle, ed. Ronald Dworkin, 221–233. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 1994. Not with my tax money. The problem of justifying government subsidies for the arts. Public Affairs Quarterly 8(2): 101–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Marianne. 2010. Wicksell’s social philosophy and his unanimity rule. Review of Social Economy 68(2): 187–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klosko, George. 2003. Reasonable rejection and neutrality of justification. In Perfectionism and neutrality. Essays in liberal theory, ed. Stephen Wall and George Klosko, 167–189. Lanham: Rowman & Littleffield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 2001. Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Franken, L. (2016). John Rawls: Liberal Neutrality and Subsidizing Art. In: Liberal Neutrality and State Support for Religion. Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-28944-1_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics