Skip to main content

Faith, Philosophy and the Elemental

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Religion and Culture in Dialogue
  • 429 Accesses

Abstract

In recent debate concerning the relationship between faith and reason, a pervasive assumption is evident according to which one or other is considered to be original and basic. This paper develops an alternative view of the status of both rational and religious modes of thought drawing on the work of Adriaan Peperzak, and bringing his suggestion in this area into dialogue with a series of interlocators including Pascal, Levinas, Heidegger, Desmond and Van der Veken. Accordingly, neither rational and/or scientific methods, nor by religious orthodoxies, can claim primordiality. Rather, both of these phenomena are determinate concretions of a more elemental pre-conceptual source that can be spoken about in terms of a background experiential faith, or a metaphysical trust. It is on this basis that an alternative account of the relation between religious faith and reason is offered, according to which they are understood to be distinct yet intimately related at source.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Note that the classificatory terms introduced in this first section are used descriptively with reference to the content matter of this essay. As such, they are not to be understood with reference to their usage in other familiar philosophical debates (e.g., incompatibilism with reference to the metaphysics of human freedom, or eliminativism with reference to physicalist accounts of mind).

  2. 2.

    Space constraints preclude a more expansive typology of worldviews that have been lumped together here under the headings of “rational-empirical” approaches (by which I include both scientific and rational philosophical outlooks in their myriad varieties) and “religious” interpretations (in their equally diverse manifestations). However, given the contentions of the essay that seeks to challenge at least one important aspect by which these two approaches are so commonly opposed, little is lost in initially granting such a broad-brush (if, in itself inadequate) characterisation.

  3. 3.

    Such claims are akin to pre-emptive notions about the ultimate sameness of all religions; claims that – as any careful analysis will show – are at best inconclusive, most likely misleading, and often just plain false.

  4. 4.

    Peperzak generally takes philosophy as his representative discipline of modern rationality. However, it seems to me perfectly consistent to extend this (as I do in this essay) to include all forms of rational thought, including the contemporary empirical sciences.

  5. 5.

    This is a matter on which I have written at length elsewhere. See Colledge 2014.

  6. 6.

    Having said that, Peperzak does not help his cause, it seems to me, by his references to this fecund “existential” dimension of human life as “the religious dimension” (2005, 74; emphasis added). His justification for this “very broad definition of religion” is, to my reading, never sufficiently explained, for it is not clear why faith in this more elemental and existential sense needs to be associated with the religious per se, with the elemental religious dimension then having to be distinguished from “concrete (or ‘positive’) religions” (2005, 74). Terminological confusions aside, there is also a significant risk here of a telling asymmetry forming according to which an ambiguous priority is afforded after all to the religious over the rational, where no such slanting is necessary. In what follows, I abstain from using this terminology which seems to me both unnecessary and incurring significant risks of misunderstanding.

  7. 7.

    Such staunchly incompatibilist thinking is echoed in a very different context by Leo Strauss in his famous address on Jerusalem and Athens: “According to the Bible, the beginning of wisdom is fear of the Lord; according to the Greek philosophers it is wonder. We are thus compelled from the very beginning to make a choice, to take a stand. Where then do we stand? Confronted by the incompatible claims of Jerusalem and Athens, we are open to both and willing to listen to each … Yet since we say that we wish to hear first and then to act or to decide, we have already decided in favor of Athens against Jerusalem (Strauss 2011).

  8. 8.

    In saying as much, I admit that across his various works Peperzak is not especially consistent with his use of the terminology of “faith”. A notable case in point is his 1999 text, Reason in Faith (the sub-title of which is “On the Relevance of Christian Spirituality for Philosophy”), where faith is often used in a specific sense to mean adherence to the Christian tradition.

  9. 9.

    It is interesting that Peperzak prefers the term “pre-intentional” (which is more suggestive of Merleau-Ponty and indeed Husserl) than it is of Levinas. To speak of the pre-intentional is to suggest a temporal orientation in relation to the intentional. The “non-intentional”, on the other hand, is entirely other to intentionality, and it is perhaps for this reason that it is generally preferred by Levinas. Nonetheless, the absoluteness suggested by utter “non-intentionality” is in some senses inconvenient for Peperzak, given his interest in the transition from indeterminate to determinate forms of faith.

  10. 10.

    While I do not deal with this topic here, Peperzak’s phenomenological roots are also evident in his suspicion of the impoverished metaphysics of rationalistic and empirical scientific accounts of the world. Even while being highly critical of the Heideggerian and post-Heideggerian critique of onto-theology, he clearly accepts aspects of this critique insofar as western thinking about God has reduced the Divine to a definable term in a syllogistic game of chess (see Peperzak 2005, 98 ff).

References

  • Cobb, John. 2007. A Christian natural theology, 2nd ed. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colledge, Richard J. 2014. Rethinking disagreement: Philosophical incommensurability and meta-philosophy. Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy 18(2): 33–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, William Lane. 2008. Reasonable faith: Christian truth and apologetics. Wheaton: Crossway.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Botton, Alain. 2012. Religion for atheists: A non-believer’s guide to the uses of religion. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmond, William. 1995. Perplexity and ultimacy: Metaphysical thoughts from the middle. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmond, William. 2001. Ethics and the between. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmond, William. 2008. God and the between. Malden: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C. Stephen. 2008. Kierkegaard and the limits of reason: Can there be a responsible Fideism? Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 64(2): 1021–1035.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, Stephen J. 1999. Rocks of ages: Science and religion in the fullness of life. New York: Ballantine Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grayling, A.C. 2013. The god argument: The case against religion and for humanism. New York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, David R. 2004. Two great truths: A new synthesis of scientific naturalism and Christian faith. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hand, Seán. 1989. The Levinas reader. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1984. The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic. Trans. Michael Heim. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lonergan, Bernard. 1990. Method in theology. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moses, Greg. 2004. Faith and reason: Naturalised and relativised. In Faith and reason: Friends or foes in the new millennium? ed. Anthony Fisher and Hayden Ramsay, 37–57. Hindmarsh: ATF Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onfray, Michel. 2005. Traité d’athéologie. Paris: Grasset. Translated as: Onfray. 2006. Atheist Manifesto: The Case Against Christianity, Judaism, and Islam. Trans. Jeremy Leggatt. New York: Arcade Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pascal, Blaise. 1968. Pensées. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peperzak, Adriaan T. 1999. Reason in faith. New York: Paulist Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peperzak, Adriaan T. 2003. The quest for meaning. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peperzak, Adriaan T. 2005. Philosophy between faith and theology. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peperzak, Adrian T. 2013. Trust. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, Alvin, and Nicholas Wolterstorff. 1991. Faith and rationality: Reason and belief in god. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne, John. 2008. Quantum physics and theology: An unexpected kinship. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shestov, Lev. 1966. Athens and Jerusalem. Trans. Bernard Martin. Athens: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Robert C. 2006. Spirituality for the skeptic: The thoughtful love of life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, Leo. 2011. Jerusalem and Athens: Some preliminary reflections. Reprinted in Jewish Ideas Daily. http://www.jewishideasdaily.com/1032/features/jerusalem-and-athens. Accessed 16 Dec 2014.

  • Swinburne, Richard. 1993. The coherence of theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard J. Colledge .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Colledge, R.J. (2016). Faith, Philosophy and the Elemental. In: Tālivaldis Ozoliņš, J. (eds) Religion and Culture in Dialogue. Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures, vol 15. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-25724-2_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics