Skip to main content

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 1))

Abstract

In this paper, we aim to criticise the dualistic approach of gender-specific medicine with regard to sex and gender. Firstly, we analyse the definition of intersexuality and reject the idea that it is a disease unto itself. Medicine classifies cases of intersexuality as disorders of sex development, because they do not conform to the dualist scheme that defines an individual’s sex as “either male or female”. However, we argue that there is no compelling reason to label intersexuality as a disease unto itself. In order to support this claim, we then consider some relevant naturalistic conceptions of health and disease. Secondly, we show that gender-specific medicine, and medicine in general, could be improved by abandoning rigid dualism concerning sex and gender. Taking sex and gender pluralism seriously would potentiate us to recognise that intersexual, transsexual, and transgender people have their own specific physiology, pathophysiology, and health concerns, which up to now have been mostly overlooked and unaddressed by gender-specific medicine. It would also encourage us to consider intersexual, transsexual, and transgender people, and to include them in clinical trials, medical research, and treatment. All this would be an ethical, epistemological, and medical improvement.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Even if there are important differences between notions such as disease, disorder, illness, injury, and malady, the conceptual issues raised by them in the present context are similar enough to let us put these distinctions aside.

  2. 2.

    Even if, from a theoretical point of view, the difference between sex and gender is acknowledged by gender-specific medicine, there is still a tendency to misrepresent and confuse the concepts of sex and gender, which are sometimes even regarded as interchangeable. We discussed this problem arguing that a distinction between the notion of sex (which refers solely to biological, anatomical, physiological, and pathophysiological differentiations) and that of gender (which considers cultural, historical, psychological, and social influences and characteristics) may still be useful in medicine (Amoretti and Vassallo 2013b).

  3. 3.

    We remarked on this particular bias, and discussed other epistemological problems of gender-specific medicine, in previous works (Amoretti and Vassallo 2012, 2013a, b).

  4. 4.

    On November 1st, 2013 Germany became the first country in Europe to allow parents to register intersex babies not as male or female. Australians have had the option of selecting “X” as their sex on passport applications since 2011, New Zealanders since 2012. Similar recognitions of a “third” sex can also be found in Bangladesh, India, Nepal, and Pakistan.

  5. 5.

    We do not survey transsexuality, but many of the following reflections apply to it too.

  6. 6.

    Even if it has been questioned that sterility is a disease unto itself, for the sake of the argument we won’t consider this option.

  7. 7.

    We do not consider normativist accounts because, as they explicitly refer to what is good/bad, flourishing/harmful for someone (subject, culture, etc.), we feel that it would be easier to accommodate them instead with the idea that intersexuality is not a disease unto itself. Also, we do not want to defend any of the naturalist accounts we consider in this study, as our purpose is merely to show that the claim that intersexuality is not a disease is compatible with (almost) all of them.

  8. 8.

    Some scholars have criticised the idea that biological fitness is the common goal of all human life, as humans have multiple and different goals. As we have already seen, it has also been questioned that sterility is a disease unto itself. If these claims were correct, then it would be easier to maintain that intersexuality is not a disease. For the sake of the argument, however, we won’t take this possibility into account.

  9. 9.

    This conclusion might be problematic for the BST, as some diseases generally associated with certain forms of intersexuality could become typical within the reference class selected. This puzzle, however, is not new, as other diseases are typical within a reference class.

  10. 10.

    We wish to thank the anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments and objections.

References

  • Amoretti, M. C., & Vassallo, N. (2012). Women and medicine: Some notes from an epistemological point of view. In J. Hu (Ed.), 2nd international conference on applied social science (pp. 406–411). Newark: IERI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amoretti, M. C., & Vassallo, N. (2013a). Is there any problem with gender-specific medicine? Verifiche, 42(1–3), 139–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amoretti, M. C., & Vassallo, N. (2013b). Sex and gender concepts in gender-specific medicine. In G. Lee (Ed.), Social science and health (Vol. 19, pp. 221–226). Newark: IERI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1987). Functions. The Journal of Philosophy, 84(4), 181–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackless, M., Charuvastra, A., Derryck, A., Fausto-Sterling, A., Lauzanne, K., & Ellen, L. (2000). How sexually dimorphic are we? Review and synthesis. American Journal of Human Biology, 12, 151–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1977). Heath as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44, 542–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1997). A rebuttal on health. In J. M. Humber & R. F. Almeder (Eds.), What is disease? (pp. 1–134). Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (2011). Concepts of health and disease. In F. Gifford (Ed.), Philosophy of medicine (pp. 13–64). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Callahan, G. N. (2009). Between XX and XY: Intersexuality and the myth of two sexes. Chicago: Chicago Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 741–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, M., & Beh, H. G. (2008). Changes in the management of children with intersex conditions. Nature Clinical Practice Endocrinology and Metabolism, 4(1), 4–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreger, A. D. (1998a). “Ambigous sex” – or ambivalent medicine? Ethical issues in the treatment of intersexuality. The Hastings Center Report, 28, 24–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreger, A. D. (1998b). Hermaphrodites and the medical invention of sex. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fausto-Sterling, A. (1993). The five sexes: Why male and female are not enough. The Sciences, March/April, 20–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fausto-Sterling, A. (2000). Sexing the body: Gender politics and the construction of sexuality. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. J. (2000). Line drawings: Defining women through feminist practice. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legato, M. J., & Bilezikian, J. P. (Eds.). (2010). Principles of gender-specific medicine. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1989). In defense of proper functions. Philosophy of Science, 56(2), 288–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1991). Functions as selected effects: The conceptual analyst’s defense. Philosophy of Science, 58, 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oertelt-Prigione, S., & Regitz-Zagrosek, V. (Eds.). (2012). Sex and gender aspects in clinical medicine. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reis, E. (2007). Divergence or disorder? Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 50(4), 535–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salamon, G. (2010). Assuming a body: Transgender and rhetorics of materiality. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schenck-Gustafsson, K. (2012). Handbook of clinical gender medicine. Basel: Karger.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stryker, S., & Aizura, A. Z. (2013). The transgender studies reader 2. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (1992). The concept of mental disorder. On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist, 47, 373–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1973). Functions. The Philosophical Review, 82, 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maria Cristina Amoretti .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Amoretti, M.C., Vassallo, N. (2015). Against Sex and Gender Dualism in Gender-Specific Medicine. In: Mäki, U., Votsis, I., Ruphy, S., Schurz, G. (eds) Recent Developments in the Philosophy of Science: EPSA13 Helsinki. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-23015-3_27

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics