Skip to main content

Subjective and Objective Aspects of Points of View

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Temporal Points of View

Abstract

One of the most puzzling features of points of view is their bipolarity between the subjective and the objective. First, we will distinguish in a precise way subjective points of view from objective ones. Both of them have a subject as their bearer, so the distinction between subjective and objective points of view will have to be made over the peculiar explicit contents of the points of view involved. After doing that distinction, we will define other connected notions as those of intersubjective points of view and private points of view. Finally, we will consider in detail the positions of relativism and perspectivism. This will offer, so to speak, a panoramic view from the subjective side of points of view. From the objective side, we will analyse the notions of independence from a perspective, absolute points of view, and transcendental points of view. Also, we will distinguish between independence from all perspectives and independence from any particular perspective. The second notion will be crucial for a certain way of understanding objectivity.

This work has been granted by Spanish Government, “Ministerio de Economía y Competividad”, Research Projects FFI2008-01205 (Points of View. A Philosophical Investigation), FFI2011-24549 (Points of View and Temporal Structures), and FFI2014-57409-R (Points of View, Dispositons, and Time. Perspectives in a World of Dispositions).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    About that, see Davidson [33].

  2. 2.

    In that line, see more recently Putnam [111, 113, 114, 115], Rorty [130, 131] and Brandom [12, 13]. One crucial difference between the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus [171] and the Wittgenstein post-Tractatus lies precisely in the contrast between private and intersubjective points of view. The solipsist option of the Tractatus, a private point of view which cannot but be the only correct one, is completely discarded as a serious option by the Wittgenstein of the Investigations [173], especially in relation to the problematic of “following a rule”. And it is discarded too, although for different reasons, by the Wittgenstein of On certainty [172].

  3. 3.

    Davidson [33].

  4. 4.

    See Williams [166], Moore [97] and Putnam [112].

  5. 5.

    See Goodman [51, 50].

  6. 6.

    Putnam [110:xi]. Also, it comes close to other projects like Dennett [37]’s “heterophenomenology”.

  7. 7.

    A detailed analysis of Nietzsche’s positions can be found in Conant [31, 32]. See also Hales and Welshon [59].

  8. 8.

    In particular, see Cratilo, Teethetus, and Republic.

  9. 9.

    A recent rejection of relativism based on what would be entailed by the identification and interpretation of “other” conceptual schemes, is Davidson [35]. In close connection with some ideas of the Wittgenstein of the Investigations, Putnam [118] is also very interesting. Other analyses and refutations of relativism can be found in Siegel [143]. About relativism in general, see again Clark [29], Haack [56], Hales [57] and Hales (ed.) [58].

  10. 10.

    See, for instance, Putnam [118].

  11. 11.

    See Stroud [156].

  12. 12.

    About that idea, see Moore [97].

  13. 13.

    See Berger and Luckmann [7].

  14. 14.

    See Bloor [8].

  15. 15.

    See Foucault [42, 41].

  16. 16.

    See, for instance, Lyotard [85]. For a critical view of relativism, see Boghossian [10].

  17. 17.

    See McGinn [93].

  18. 18.

    About that, see Searle [139] and Tuomela [159, 160].

  19. 19.

    See for instance, McDowell [92].

  20. 20.

    With respect to relativist approaches to norms and values, see Harman [64], Honderich (ed.) [65], Krausz and Meiland (eds.) [70] and Mackie [90].

  21. 21.

    See Ashman and Barringer (eds.) [4, 14], Callon [18], Gross and Levitt [54], Labinger and Collins (eds.) [75], Parsons (ed.) [106], Sokal [147] and Sokal and Bricmont [148].

  22. 22.

    See Davidson [34] and von Wright [174].

  23. 23.

    See Show [146].

  24. 24.

    See Sellars [141].

  25. 25.

    See Sokal and Bricmont [148] and Sokal [147]. Other authors with relevant contributions to all of these debates are Boghossian [10], Frankfurt [43, 44], Nagel [99], Searle [139] and Williams [168]. From different perspectives, all of them argue against relativism and defend the value of things like truth, reality, objectivity and rationality.

  26. 26.

    As an example of that kind of gender relativism, see Hardin [61, 62, 63].

  27. 27.

    A paradigmatic presentation of that argument can be found in Russell [133].

  28. 28.

    See Hamlyn [60], McGinn [93] and Stroud [157].

  29. 29.

    See Bender [6], Bonjour [11], Davidson [35], Lehrer [80, 81], Rescher [124, 125] and Sosa [149].

  30. 30.

    Two recent and very important approaches in that sense are Rorty [129] and Stich [153]. Among classical pragmatists, James [68] constitutes the most explicit assumption of perspectivism.

  31. 31.

    See Armstrong [3], Goldman [47] and Nozick [102].

  32. 32.

    See Sosa [150, 151, 152]. See also Greco (ed.) [52] and Greco [53].

  33. 33.

    About that requirement, see specially Sosa [150, 152].

  34. 34.

    See Goodman [49].

  35. 35.

    With respect to justice, see Rawls [122]; with respect to conceptual analysis, see Sosa [150].

  36. 36.

    About that, see Farkas [39], Quinton [121], Williams [166] and Williamson [169].

  37. 37.

    This is argued in Farkas [39].

  38. 38.

    See Chisholm [26].

  39. 39.

    We can mention Feyerabend [40], Foucault [42], Goodman [50], Kuhn [71], Quine [119, 120], Putnam [110, 111, 113, 114, 115]; and in a very radical way Rorty [128, 129, 130, 131].

  40. 40.

    Carnap [20].

  41. 41.

    See Whorf [165] and Gumperz and Levinson (eds.) [55].

  42. 42.

    For a reconstruction and criticisms of these relativist ideas, see Malotki [91].

  43. 43.

    In particular, this is so with Feyerabend [40], Davidson [35], Goodman [49], Kuhn [71], Quine [119, 120], Putnam [110, 111, 113, 114, 115] and Rorty [128, 129, 130, 131].

  44. 44.

    See Quine [119, 120].

  45. 45.

    See Davidson [35].

  46. 46.

    Recanati [123] offers a very clear and useful classification of the main forms of “context dependence”. He distinguishes between pre-semantic context dependences and semantic context dependences. Among the first ones, the most relevant cases are language-relativity, syntactic ambiguity and lexical ambiguity. Among the second ones, the most relevant cases are circumstance-relativity, indexical token-reflexivity, indexical semantic under-specification and modulation. About contextualism in general, see Preyer and Peter [108]. About the relationships between contextualism and relativism, see Richard [127].

  47. 47.

    About that, see Perry [107].

  48. 48.

    Among the vast literature concerning this topic, see García-Carpintero and Kölbel (eds.) [45], Kölbel [72, 73, 74]; Lasersohn [77, 78], MacFarlane [87, 88, 89]; Preyer and Peter [108], Recanati [123], Richard [127], Williamson [169], Cappelen and Hawthorne [19], Stojanovic [154] and López de Sa [86].

  49. 49.

    See Tye [162, 163, 164]. See also Levine [82], who coined the expression “explanatory gap” to emphasise the differences between the first-person point of view and scientific third-person points of view.

  50. 50.

    See Dennett [36, 37], Ryle [135], Türing [161], Patricia Churchland [27] and Wittgenstein [173].

  51. 51.

    See Sellars [140] and Paul Churchland [28].

  52. 52.

    See Cassam [21], Chalmers [23], Chisholm [25], Dreyfus [38], Farkas [39], Jackson [67], McGinn [93], Mellor [95], Nagel [100, 98], Searle [136, 137, 138], Lewis [83] and Shoemaker [142].

  53. 53.

    See Putnam [117] and Burge [15, 16, 17]. See also Boghossian [9] and Liz [84]. The need for a perspectival self-consciousness is particularly demanding in the case of thoughts about oneself. The phenomenology of the “I” has been analysed by Chisholm [25] and Castañeda [22]. Its radical indexicality has been emphasised by Perry [107]. And the connections among perception, action, and self-consciousness have been stressed by Hurley [66]. Extending Hurley’s ideas, Noë [104, 105] has defended the non-conceptuality of perspectival self-consciousness. Some of our analyses of points of view would have relevant implications here. Perhaps the proper space for “self-consciouness” and “self-knowledge” is that space which is internal to points of view without being internal to the subjects having those points of view.

  54. 54.

    See Gomila [48].

  55. 55.

    For that change of perspective, see Lakatos and Musgrave (eds.) [76] and Toulmin [158].

  56. 56.

    In the first field, Kuhn’s notions of “paradigm” and “incommensurability” have had an enormous influence. See Kuhn (1996, 3 ed.). With respect to the second field, see Bloor [8], Barnes and Bloor [5] and Collins [30]. Holding a harder constructivism, see Latour and Wolgar [79] and Knorr-Cetina [69].

  57. 57.

    About the perspectival character of causality, see Menzies and Price [96], Price [109] and Álvarez [1].

  58. 58.

    See Sellars [141] and Rosenberg [132].

  59. 59.

    See Giere [46].

  60. 60.

    About all those distinctions, and many others, see Wilson [170] and Rescher [126].

  61. 61.

    See Simon [144, 145].

  62. 62.

    About “bounded rationality”, and its contrast with “ideal conceptions of rationality”, see Cherniak [24].

  63. 63.

    About that, see Anderson [2].

  64. 64.

    With respect to 1, see the preceding sections. With respect to 2 and 3, see the previous chapter of this book.

  65. 65.

    For a discussion of this subject, see Nagel [98, 99]. See, also, the discussions of Moore [97] of the “ineffable” character of some theses of absolutism, relativism, and transcendentalism.

  66. 66.

    About the relations between “invariance” and “objectivity”, see Nozick [103].

  67. 67.

    About “absolute” points of view, see Williams [166] and Moore [97]. About “transcendental” points of view, see Moore [97].

  68. 68.

    As we said, the notion of an “absolute conception” of the world, and of ourselves as part of it, comes from Williams [166, 167], and has one on its main sources in Descartes. It has been recently analysed and vindicated by Moore (1987, [97], and criticised by Nielsen [101] and Putnam [110, 111, 113, 114, 115, 116].

  69. 69.

    See again Moore [97]. We can also say that, in those cases, truth works as an “extensive” measure. In non-absolute (relative) points of view, truth would work as an “intensive” measure.

  70. 70.

    The classical locus for what we are calling the “transcendental mood” in epistemology is Plato’s criticism of the Sophists rejection that things have a way of being in themselves. Such transcendentalism offers an absolute, non-perspectival ontological position about our epistemic relation with reality.

  71. 71.

    Our definitions of absolute points of view, transcendental points of view (of a conceptual kind), absolutism and transcendentalism fit very well with an exclusivist scientific realism involving projects for naturalizing epistemology, ethics, etc. The peculiar transcendental mood that we find here can be called “scientificism”.

  72. 72.

    About that, see again Williams [166], Moore [97] and Nozick [103].

  73. 73.

    Plato, for instance in his Cratilus, develops the first option. The second one is one of he main topics of Wittgenstein in his Tractatus, one of the more important works in the transcendentalist tradition.

  74. 74.

    About that, see Stroud [155]. According to him, the main claim of radical scepticism is that a full understanding of the whole of reality is simply non possible.

  75. 75.

    Apart from McTaggart, we have in Mellor [94], one of the most elaborated rejections of the real existence of a “fluent time”. In other chapters of this book, these issues will be discussed in depth.

  76. 76.

    In Russell [134], we can find a clear case of a relational time which is internal to a construed “space of perspectives” without being merely internal to the subjects from which that space of perspectives is construed. The construction of a Russellian space of perspectives is explained in other chapters of this book.

  77. 77.

    And this is so with independence of all the problems about the possibility of “simultaneity” in relation to physical time,.

  78. 78.

    See Russell [134]. A very important reference for Russell’s approach was Leibniz’s Monadology. Leibniz was also an important reference for the perspectivist position of the Spanish philosopher Ortega y Gasset.

  79. 79.

    The details of Russell’s construction of a “space of perspectives” are explained in other chapters of this book. Russell claims that the spaces of experience are “private”. This is consistent with his insistence in that the constructions offered (of a space of perspectives, of a physical space and a physical time, of ordinary things and physical objects, of matter, etc.) could be made from a solipsist basis. According to our definitions, however, a “private point of view” could not be intersubjective. So, to the extent that spaces of experience can be intersubjective, and this can put us on the track of objectivity, they could not be “purely private”.

References

  1. Álvarez, S. (2014). Causation and the Agent's Point of View. International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science, 29(79), 133–47.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Anderson, R. (1998). Truth and objectivity in perspectivism. Synthese, 115(1), 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Armstrong, D. (1973). Belief, truth, and knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ashman, K., & Barringer, Ph (Eds.). (2001). After the science wars. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Barnes, B., & Bloor, D. (1982). Relativism, rationalism, and the sociology of knowledge. In M. Hollis & S. Lukes (Eds.), Rationality and relativism (pp. 21–47). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Bender, J. (1989). The current state of the coherence theory. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Berger, P., & Luckmann, T. (1966). The social construction of reality: A treatise in the sociology of knowledge. New York: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Bloor, D. (1992). Knowledge and social imaginary (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Boghossian, P. (1989). Content and self-knowledge in philosophy of mind. Philosophical Topics, 17(1), 5–26.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Boghossian, P. (2006). Fear of knowledge. Against relativism and constructivism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Bonjour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Brandom, R. (2002). Articulating reasons. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Brown, J. (2001). Who rules in science? An opinionated guide to the wars. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4(1), 73–121.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Burge, T. (1988). Individualism and selfknowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, 85, 649–663.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Burge, T. (1989). Individualism and psychology. Philosophical Studies, 40, 39–75.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Callon, M. (1999). Whose impostures? Physicists at war with the third person. Social Studies of Science, 29(2), 261–286.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cappelen, H., & Hawthorne, J. (2009). Relativism and monadic truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4, 20–40.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cassam, Q. (1989). Reductionism and first-person thinking. In D. Charles & K. Lennon (Eds.), Reductionism, explanation and realism (pp. 361–379). Oxford: Clarendon Press (1992).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Castañeda, H. (1999). The phenomeno-logic of the I. Essays in self-consciousness. In J. Hart & T. Kapitan (Eds.) Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cherniak, Ch. (1992). Minimal rationality. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Chisholm, R. (1976). Person and object. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Chisholm, R. (1966). Theory of Knowledge. Englewoods Cliffs: Prentice Hall [3rd. ed., 1988].

    Google Scholar 

  27. Churchland, Patricia. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind/brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Churchland, Paul. (1988). Matter and consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Clark, M. (1990). Nietzsche on truth and philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Collins, H. (1981). Stages in the empirical program of relativism. Social Studies of Science, 11, 3–10.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Conant, J. (2005). The dialectic of perspectivism, 1. Nordic Journal of Philosophy, 6, 5–50.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Conant, J. (2006). The dialectic of perspectivism, 2. Nordic Journal of Philosophy, 7, 6–57.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Davidson, D. (2001). Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons and causes. Journal of Philosophy 60: 685–700 [Also in Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press].

    Google Scholar 

  35. Davidson, D. (1974). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 47: 5–20 [Also in Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press].

    Google Scholar 

  36. Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Dreyfus, H. (1972). What computers (still) can’t do: A critique of artificial reason (6th ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press (1999).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Farkas, K. (2008). The subject’s point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method: Outline of an anarchist theory of knowledge, (1993 (3rd ed.). London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Foucault, M. (1980). Power/knowledge: Selected interviews and other writings, 1972–1977. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Foucault, M. (1969). The archeology of knowledge. New York: Pantheon Books (1972).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Frankfurt, H. (2005). On bullshit. Princeton: Princeon University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Frankfurt, H. (2005). On truth. Nueva York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  45. García-Carpintero, M., & Kölbel, M. (Eds.). (2009). Relative truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Giere, R. (2006). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Gomila, A. (2010). Musical expression and the second person perspective. In I. Álvarez, F. Pérez-Carreño, & H. Pérez (Eds.), The expression of subjectivity in the performing arts. Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Goodman, N. (1954). Fact, fiction and forecast. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Goodman, N. (1960). The way the world is. Review of Metaphysics, 14, 48–56 [Also in Goodman, N. (1972). Problems and projects. New York: Bobbs-Merrill].

    Google Scholar 

  52. Greco, J. (Ed.). (2004). Ernst sosa and his critics. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Greco, J. (Ed.). (2011). Virtue epistemology. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu.

  54. Gross, P., & Levitt, N. (1994). Higher supersticion: The academic left and its quarrels with science. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Gumperz, J., & Levinson, S. (Eds.). (1996). Rethinking linguistic relativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Haack, S. (1996). Reflections on relativism: From momentous tautology to seductive contradiction. Philosophical Perspectives, 10, 297–315.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Hales, S. (2006). Relativism and the foundations of philosophy. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Hales, S. (Ed.). (2011). A companion to relativism. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Hales, S., & Welshon, R. (2000). Nietzsche’s perspectivism. Illinois: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Hamlyn, D. (1961). Sensation and perception. A history of the philosophy of perception. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Hardin, S. (1986). The science question in feminism. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Hardin, S. (1991). Whose science? Whose knowledge? Thinking from women’s lives. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Harding, S. (1998). Is science multicultural? Postcolonialism, feminism and epistemology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Harman, G. (1975). Moral relativism defended. Philosophical Review, 84, 3–22.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Honderich, T. (Ed.). (1985). Morality and objectivity. Londres: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Jackson, F. (1986). What mary didn’t know. The Journal of Philosophy, 83, 291–295.

    Google Scholar 

  68. James, W. (1907). Pragmatism: A new name for some old ways of thinking. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Knorr-Cetina, K. (1983). The ethnographic study of scientific work: Towards a constructivist interpretation of science. In K. D. Knorr-Cetina & M. Mulkay (Eds.), Science observed (pp. 189–204). Hollywood: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Krausz, M., & Meiland, J. (Eds.). (1982). Relativism: Cognitive and moral. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Kuhn, T. (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Kölbel, M. (2002). Truth without objectivity. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Kölbel, M. (2003). Faultless disagreement. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104, 53–73.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Kölbel, M. (2004). Indexical relativism versus genuine relativism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 12(3), 297–313.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Labinger, J., & Collins, H. (Eds.). (2001). The one culture? A conversation about science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Lakatos, I., & Musgrave, A. (Eds.). (1970). Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Lasersohn, P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistic and Philosophy, 28, 643–686.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Lasersohn, P. (2009). Relative truth, speaker commitment, and control of implicit arguments. Synthese, 166, 359–374.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1979). Laboratory life: The social construction of scientific facts. Beverly Hill: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Lehrer, K. (1974). Knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Lehrer, K. (1986). The coherence theory of knowledge. Philosophical Topics, 14(1), 5–25.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes De Dicto and De Se. Philosophical Review, (88), 513-43.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Liz, M. (2003). Intentional states: Individuation, explanation, and supervenience. In M. J. Fapolli & E. Romero (Eds.), Meaning, basic knowledge, and mind (pp. 129–223). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Lyotard, J. (1979). The postmodern condition. A report on knowledge. Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  86. López de Sa, D. (2009). Presuppositions of commonality: An indexical relativist aconceptual contentsount of disagreement. In M. García-Carpintero & M. Kölbel (Eds.), Relative truth (pp. 297–310). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  87. MacFarlane, J. (2003). Future contingents and relative truth. The Philosophical Quarterly, 53, 321–336.

    Google Scholar 

  88. MacFarlane, J. (2005). Making sense of relative truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 105, 321–336.

    Google Scholar 

  89. MacFarlane, J. (2007). Relativism and disagreement. Philosophical Studies, 132, 17–31.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Malotki, E. (1983). Hopi time: A linguistic analysis of the temporal concepts in the hopi language. Berlin: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  92. McDowell, J. (1998). Mind, Value, and Reality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  93. McGinn, C. (1983). The subjective view: Secondary qualities and indexical thoughts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Mellor, D. (1998). Real time II. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Mellor, D. (1991). I and now. In Matters of metaphysics (pp. 17–29). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Menzies, P., & Price, H. (1993). Causation as a secondary quality. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44, 187–203.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Moore, A. (1997). Points of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Nagel, T. (1986). The view from nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Nagel, T. (1997). The last word. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a vat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450 [Also in Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press].

    Google Scholar 

  101. Nielsen, K. (1993). Perspectivism and the absolute conception of the world. Crítica XXV, 74, 105–116.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambidge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Nozick, R. (2001). Invariances. The structure of the objective world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Noë, A. (2002). Is perspectival self-consciousness nonconceptual? The Philosophical Quarterly, 52(207), 185–194.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Parsons, K. (Ed.). (2003). The science wars: Debating scientific knowledge and technology. New York: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21 [Also in The Problem of the Essential Indexical and other Essays, 1993: 33–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press].

    Google Scholar 

  108. Preyer, G., & Peter, G. (Eds.). (2005). Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, meaning and truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Price, H. (2007). Causal perspectivalism. In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Causation, physics and the constitution of reality, (pp. 225–292). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Putnam, H. (1987). The many faces of realism. La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Putnam, H. (1992). Renewing philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Putnam, H. (1994). Words and life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Putnam, H. (1994). Pragmatism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Putnam, H. (1994). Realism with a human face. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Putnam, H. (1999). The threefold cord mind, body and world. Nueva York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning”. In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Language, mind, and knowledge (pp. 131–193). Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Putnam, H. (1982). Why reason can’t be naturalized. Synthese 51 [Also in Realism and Reason (pp. 3–24). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press].

    Google Scholar 

  119. Quine, W. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Quine, W. (1969). Ontological relativity and other essays. Nueva York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Quinton, A. (1966). The foundations of knowledge. In B. Williams & A. Montefiore (Eds.), British analytical philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Recanati F. (2007). Perspectival thoughts. A plea for (Moderate) relativism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Rescher, N. (1973). The coherence theory of truth. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Rescher, N. (1973). The primacy of practice. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Rescher, N. (1988). Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Richard, M. (2004). Contextualism and relativism. Philosophical Studies, 119, 215–242.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Rorty, R. (1982). Consequences of pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Cambridge: Cambrdge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Rorty, R. (1991). Objectivity, relativism, and truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Rosenberg, J. (2007). Wilfrid sellars: Fusing the images. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Russell, B. (1912). Problems of philosophy (p. 1968). London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Russell, B. (1918). The relation of sense data to physics. In Mysticism and logic, and other essays (pp. 113–140). London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  135. Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: Chicago University Press (1963).

    Google Scholar 

  136. Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417–457.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Searle, J. (1985). Minds, brains and science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  138. Searle, J. (1992). The rediscovery of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  139. Searle, J. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  140. Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of the mental. In Empiricism and the philosophy of the mental (introduction by Richard Rorty and study guide by Robert Brandom). Cambridge: Harvard University Press (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  141. Sellars, W. (1962). Philosophy and the scientific image of the man. In Science, perception and reality (pp. 1–40). Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Company (1963).

    Google Scholar 

  142. Shoemaker, S. (1996). The first-person perspective and other essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  143. Siegel, H. (1987). Relativism refuted: A critique of contemporary epistemological relativism. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  144. Simon, H. (1957). Models of man. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  145. Simon, H. (1969). The sciences of the artificial. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  146. Snow, C. P. (2007). The two cultures (the 1959’s work, the 1964’s suplement, and later revisions). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  147. Sokal, A. (2008). Beyond the hoax: Science, philosophy and culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Sokal, A., & Bricmont, J. (1998). Intellectual impostures. London: Profile Books.

    Google Scholar 

  149. Sosa, E. (1980). The raft and the pyramid. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 3–26.

    Google Scholar 

  150. Sosa, E. (1991). Knowledge in perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  151. Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  152. Sosa, E. (2009). Reflective knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  153. Stich, S. (1990). The fragmentation of reason. Preface to a pragmatic theory of cognitive evaluation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  154. Stojanovic, I. (2008). Talking about taste: Disagreement, implicit arguments, and relative truth. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 691–706.

    Google Scholar 

  155. Stroud, B. (1968). Transcendental arguments. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 241–256.

    Google Scholar 

  156. Stroud, B. (1984). The significance of philosophical scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  157. Stroud, B. (2000). The quest for reality. Subjectivism and the metaphysics of colour. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  158. Toulmin, S. (1972). Human understanding. The collective use and evolution of concepts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  159. Tuomela, R. (1995). The importance of Us. A philosophical study of basic social notions. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  160. Tuomela, R. (2006). Joint intention. We-mode and I-mode. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 30(1), 35–58.

    Google Scholar 

  161. Turing, A. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.

    Google Scholar 

  162. Tye, M. (1986). The subjective qualities of experience. Mind, 95, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  163. Tye, M. (1989). The metaphysics of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  164. Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  165. Whorf, B. (1956). Language, thought and reality. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  166. Williams, B. (1978). Descartes: The project of pure enquiry. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  167. Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  168. Williams, B. (2002). Truth and truthfulness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  169. Williamson, T. (2005). Knowledge, context, and the agent’s point of view. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  170. Wilson, B. (1970). Rationality. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  171. Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus (p. 1961). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  172. Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  173. Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical investigations. Londres: Blackwell (1974).

    Google Scholar 

  174. von Wright, G. (1971). Explanation and understanding. New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antonio Manuel Liz Gutiérrez .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Liz Gutiérrez, A.M., Vázquez Campos, M. (2015). Subjective and Objective Aspects of Points of View. In: Vázquez Campos, M., Liz Gutiérrez, A. (eds) Temporal Points of View. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-19815-6_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics