Skip to main content

Signs, Science, and Religion: A Biosemiotic Mediation

  • Chapter
Issues in Science and Theology: What is Life?

Abstract

Following on the pragmatic notion of belief as propensity to action, this essay argues that science, philosophy, and religion form a Peircian triad. As with all such triads, no single part ‘has’ ontological status – each is a process that exists only as a function of the other parts. And so, Religion represents the ‘reading’ that generates a mental map; Philosophy, checking such a ‘map’ against itself for functionality, consistency of signage, etc.; and Science, checking it against some actual situation. Thus, religion (or, religare) is ubiquitous to life as it represents the core binding (Jamesian Pure Experience, and Peircian Thirdness become Firstness) that is the consequent of semiotic interaction (an interpretant consequential to an organism ‘minding’ its environment). As Santayana argued, this ‘animal faith’ defines life; it includes but is not limited to, self-knowing life. Yet also, as per C. I. Lewis’s inversion of idealism, structures of knowing consist of (and bear upon the world) a priori behavior and consequent need. And so, our methods ‘mind’ their business – often better than we do. They pull behind them a train of institutions, ‘jointly held stock’ replete with historically contrived symbolisms and other such tools of self-generative function, and ‘act’ in their ‘perceived’ interest, rather than that of their practitioners. The rub is that in order to either know or be all this must proceed on its terms, not ours. The upshot is that religion can be done ill or well, but cannot simply be abandoned. For even in the rare instances that result in self-knowing beings, religion (as heterarchically binding function within semiosis) is distinct from the objects we call ‘religions’. Moreover, every religion that ever existed (function and object alike) is prone to dysfunction. Whether limited to a single living thing or widely practiced and culturally ensconced, the binding of interpretation into being is more likely to result in a more successful interpreter when bound by philosophy and science. This becomes particularly significant when the process of religion is abstracted, set apart from its biological function and instituted within human society. In praxis, this analysis of psychogenetic semiosis demands that we ‘read again’ (relegere) the creative morality of Alan Watts.

A sign is something which stands for another thing to a mind.

(Peirce et al. 1998 : 82)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Bibliography

  • Emerson, R.W. 1941. Divinity school address. In Essays poems addresses, ed. G.S. Haight. New York: D. Van Nostrand Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, N. 1869–70. Proximate and remote cause. American Law Review 4: 201–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. 1912. Essays in radical empiricism. London: Longman Green and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C.I. 1923. A pragmatic conception of the a priori. Journal of Philosophy 20(7): 169–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marty, R. 1997. 76 definitions of the sign by C. S. Peirce. Arisbe: The Peirce Gateway. http://www.cspeirce.com/rsources/76defs/76defs.htm.

  • Ostdiek, G. 2010. Darwin’s ontology, the consequences of reciprocity. Dissertation, Charles University in Prague.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostdiek, G. 2012. The self as social artifice: Some consequences of Stanislavski. Biosemiotics 5(2): 161–179. doi:10.1007/s12304-011-9137-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce C.S. et al. 1998. The writings of Charles S. Peirce, vol. 3, ed. C.S.W. Kloesel. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romanini V. 2011. Periodic table of classes of signs. Minutesemeiotic.org. http://www.minutesemeiotic.org/home.php?id=1.

  • Santayana, G. 1955. Skepticism and animal faith. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watts, A. 1951. The wisdom of insecurity. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A.N. 1958. The function of reason. Boston: Beacon Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A.N. 1960. Religion in the making. Cleveland: Meridian Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. 2000. The evolutionary philosophy of Chauncey Wright in 3 volumes, vol 1, ed. F.X. Ryan and E.H. Madden. Bristol: Thommes.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerald Ostdiek .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ostdiek, G. (2015). Signs, Science, and Religion: A Biosemiotic Mediation. In: Evers, D., Fuller, M., Jackelén, A., Sæther, KW. (eds) Issues in Science and Theology: What is Life?. Issues in Science and Religion: Publications of the European Society for the Study of Science and Theology. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-17407-5_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics