Skip to main content

Quantum(-Like) Decision Making: On Validity of the Aumann Theorem

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Quantum Interaction (QI 2014)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNTCS,volume 8951))

Included in the following conference series:

Abstract

Through set-theoretic formalization of the notion of common knowledge, Aumann proved that if two agents have the common priors, and their posteriors for a given event are common knowledge, then their posteriors must be equal. In this paper we investigate the problem of validity of this theorem in the framework of quantum(-like) decision making.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For readers’ convenience, we now present the original Aumann’s definition of common knowledge for two agents: “An event \(E\) is common knowledge at the state of the world \(\omega \) if 1 knows \(E,\) 2 knows \(E,\) 1 knows 2 knows \(E,\) 2 knows 1 knows \(E,\) and so on.” The aforementioned heuristic notion of common knowledge can be formally described by various mathematical models. The classical probabilistic formalization of this notion was presented, e.g., in [29, 30]. (In fact, the problem of common knowledge plays very important role in cognitive science, psychology, philosophy, decision making, economics. There were published numerous papers enlightening various aspects of common knowledge studies. We are not able to review such studies in this paper, see, e.g., easily approachable work [31] for extended bibliography.) In this paper we present a novel formalization of the heuristic notion of common knowledge, namely, based on quantum probability and quantum logics. However, we do not change the cognitive meaning of this notion. Our quantum(-like) model just describe some features of common knowledge which were known by experts in aforementioned areas, but were not covered by the classical probability model.

  2. 2.

    We also remark that a deep connection between biased decision making and quantum modeling of cognition was established in the framework of theory of open quantum systems, where biases were modeled as components of the “mental environment” [19, 20].

  3. 3.

    The notion of possible worlds is very complex and it has been discussed in hundreds of papers, in philosophy, knowledge theory, modal logics. One can think about states as representing Leibniz’s possible worlds or Wittgenstein’s possible states of affairs. Of course, by representing the states of world by pure quantum states and saying nothing about a possible interpretation of the wave function, quantum state, we proceed in the purely operational way. What quantum state interpretation does match with the notion of the “possible worlds” used in literature? Suprisingly, it seems that the many worlds interpretation matches best, see also appendix 1. There is a similarity between the state of the world and the wave function of universe. However, since we are not so much excited by the many worlds interpretation, we proceed in the purely operational approach. The information interpretation of the quantum state (A. Zeilinger, C. Brukner) seems to be the most appropriate for our purposes.

References

  1. Khrennikov, A.: Information Dynamics in Cognitive, Psychological, Social, and Anomalous Phenomena. Ser.: Fundamental Theories of Physics. Kluwer, Dordreht (2004)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. Khrennikov, A.: Ubiquitous Quantum Structure: from Psychology to Finances. Springer, Berlin (2010)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  3. Busemeyer, J.R., Bruza, P.D.: Quantum Models of Cognition and Decision. Cambridge Press, Cambridge (2012)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. Haven, E., Khrennikov, A.: Quantum Social Science. Cambridge Press, Cambridge (2013)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  5. Khrennikov, A.: On quantum-like probabilistic structure of mental information. Open Syst. Inf. Dyn. 11(3), 267–275 (2004)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. Busemeyer, J.R., Wang, Z., Townsend, J.T.: Quantum dynamics of human decision making. J. Math. Psychol. 50, 220–241 (2006)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. Khrennikov, A.: Quantum-like formalism for cognitive measurements. Biosystems 70, 211–233 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Khrennikov, A.: Quantum-like brain: interference of minds. BioSystems 84, 225–241 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Conte, E., Todarello, O., Federici, A., Vitiello, F., Lopane, M., Khrennikov, A., Zbilut, J.P.: Some remarks on an experiment suggesting quantum-like behavior of cognitive entities and formulation of an abstract quantum mechanical formalism to describe cognitive entity and its dynamics. Chaos Solitons Fractals 31(5), 1076–1088 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Busemeyer, J.R., Santuy, E., Lambert-Mogiliansky, E.: Comparison of Markov and quantum models of decision making. In: Bruza, P., Lawless, W., van Rijsbergen, K., Sofge, D.A., Coeke, B., Clark, S. (eds.) Quantum interaction: Proceedings of the Second Quantum Interaction Symposium, pp. 68–74. College Publications, London (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Conte, E., Khrennikov, A., Todarello, O., Federici, A., Mendolicchio, L., Zbilut, J.P.: Mental state follow quantum mechanics during perception and cognition of ambiguous figures. Open Syst. Inf. Dyn. 16, 1–17 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Conte, E., Khrennikov, A., Todarello, O., Federici, A., Mendolicchio, L., Zbilut, J.P.: A pre-liminary experimental verification on the possibility of bell inequality violation in mental states. NeuroQuantology 6(3), 214–221 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Busemeyer, J.R., Wang, Z., Lambert-Mogiliansky, A.: Empirical comparison of Markov and quantum models of decision making. J. Math. Psychol. 53(5), 423–433 (2009)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. de Barros, A.J., Suppes, P.: Quantum mechanics, interference, and the brain. J. Math Psychol. 53, 306–313 (2009)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. Lambert-Mogiliansky, A., Zamir, S., Zwirn, H.: Type indeterminacy: a model of the KT (Kahneman-Tversky)-man. J. Math. Psychol. 53(5), 349–361 (2009)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  16. Pothos, E.M., Busemeyer, J.R.: A quantum probability explanation for violation of rational decision theory. Proc. Royal. Soc. B 276, 2171–2178 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Haven, E., Khrennikov, A.: Quantum mechanics and violation of the sure-thing principle: the use of probability interference and other concepts. J. Math. Psychol. 53, 378–388 (2009)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Trueblood, J.S., Busemeyer, J.R.: A quantum probability account of order effects in inference. Cogn. Sci. 35, 1518–1552 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Asano, M., Ohya, M., Tanaka, Y., Khrennikov, A., Basieva, I.: On application of Gorini-Kossakowski-Sudarshan-Lindblad equation in cognitive psychology. Open Syst. Inf. Dyn. 18, 55–69 (2011)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  20. Asano, M., Ohya, M., Tanaka, Y., Khrennikov, A., Basieva, I.: Dynamics of entropy in quantum-like model of decision making. J. Theor. Biol. 281, 56–64 (2011)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  21. Dzhafarov, E.N., Kujala, J.V.: Quantum entanglement and the issue of selective influences in psychology: an overview. Lect. Notes Comput. Sci. 7620, 184–195 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  22. Aerts, D., Sozzo, S., Tapia, J.: A quantum model for the Elsberg and Machina paradoxes. Lect. Notes Comput. Sci. 7620, 48–59 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  23. Atmanspacher, H., Filk, T.: Contra classical causality: violating temporal Bell inequalities in mental systems. J. Conscious. Stud. 19(5/6), 95–116 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Atmanspacher, H., Römer, H.: Order effects in sequential measurements of non-commuting psychological observables. J. Math. Psychol. 56, 274–280 (2012)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Asano, M., Basieva, I., Khrennikov, A., Ohya, M., Tanaka, Y.: Quantum-like generalization of the Bayesian updating scheme for objective and subjective mental uncertainties. J. Math. Psychol. 56, 166–175 (2012)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Khrennikova, P.: Evolution of quantum-like modeling in decision making processes. aip conf. proc. 1508, 108 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Asano, M., Basieva, I., Khrennikov, A., Ohya, M., Yamato, I.: Non-kolmogorovian approach to the context-dependent systems breaking the classical probability law. Found. Phys. 43, 2083–2099 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  28. Khrennikova, P.: A quantum framework for ’sour grapes’ in cognitive dissonance. In: Proceedings of Quantum Interaction-13, University of Leicester Press (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Aumann, R.J.: Agreeing on disagree. Ann. Stat. 4, 1236–1239 (1976)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  30. Aumann, R.J.: Backward induction and common knowledge of rationality. Game. Econ. Behav. 8, 619 (1995)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  31. Vanderschraaf, P., Sillari, G.: Common Knowledge. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Continuum Press, New York (2013). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/common-knowledge

    Google Scholar 

  32. Birkhoff, J., von Neumann, J.: The logic of quantum mechanics. Ann. Math. 37, 823–843 (1936)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Feynman, R., Hibbs, A.: Quantum Mechanics and Path Integrals. McGraw-Hill, New York (1965)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Von Neuman, J.: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1955)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Bostrom, N.: Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy (Studies in Philosophy). Routledge Publ, New York (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Garola, C.: A Pragmatic Interpretation of Quantum Logic. Preprint arXiv:quant-ph/0507122v2

  37. Garola, C., Sozzo, S.: Recovering nonstandard logics within an extended classical framework. Erkenntnis 78, 399–419 (2013)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  38. Khrennikov, A., Schumann, A.: Quantum Non-objectivity from Performativity of Quantum Phenomena. arXiv:1404.7077 [physics.gen-ph]. To be published in Physica Scripta

  39. Atmanspacher, H., Primas, H.: Epistemic and ontic quantum realities. In: Adenier, G., Khrennikov, A. (eds.), Foundations of Probability and Physics-3, Conf. Proc. Ser. vol. 750, pp. 49–62. AIP, Melville, NY (2005)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank J. Acacio de Barros, H. Atmanspacher, J. Busemeyer, E. N. Dzhafarov, E. Haven, E. M. Pothos, for discussions on quantum probabilistic modeling of cognitive phenomena and especially decision making and probability update.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrei Khrennikov .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendices

Appendix 1: Biased Decision Making and Violation of the Aumann Theorem

An important source of possible violation of the Aumann theorem is the presence of various biases in the “heads of agents”. Roughly speaking any bias may destroy the purity of the Bayesian update.

As a widely discussed example of the anti-Aumann bias, we consider the so called SSA-bias. A Self Sampling Assumption (SSA) says you are more likely to be present in worlds where a greater proportion of agents which are like you, see N. Bostrom for the detailed discussion on SSA [35]. Except that “agents” can be any set of things you could have been in some sense, even if you currently know you are not some of them. This group is called a reference class. Agents basing their reasoning on the SSA and having different reference classes need not come to the same posterior probabilities, even if the assumptions of the Aumann theorem, about the common prior and common knowledge, hold true. And this is clear why. Such an agent can ignore some of her/his information in forming her/his reference classe, since it asks for the proportion of her/his reference class of whom all of her/his information is true. This can lead to simple ignorance of a part of information presented in common knowledge. It is often argued that the decision making based on the selection of an appropriate reference class is irrational. And we agree with such evaluation of the SSA decision makers. However, we do not assign negative valuation to “irrationality” in the decision making. As was demonstrated in [35], the SSA-operating is quite common phenomenon. Since this happens and happens in many contexts, such a behavior of agents has to be modeled mathematically. And if in the classical probabilistic framework this is impossible (as signed in the violation of the Aumann theorem which is heavily based on Kolmogorov probability), then it is natural to explore other probabilistic models, e.g., quantum probability. In this short note we are not able to discuss quantum modeling of SSA in more details, it will be done in one of further articles. We finish this discussion on SSA with the following remark on the interpretation of the wave function, quantum state. The SSA approach to decision making matches well with the many world interpretation of the quantum state. A SSA-agent position her/him self as belonging to a few possible reference classes, which play here the roles of the worlds.

Appendix 2: On the Logical Structure of the Aumann Argument

As ia well known, he Aumann argument on the impossibility of agree on disagree is based on the special systems of axioms of the modal logic, the system S5. And, of course, any deviation from this system might lead to a violation of the classical Aumann theorem. In this paper it was shown that the usage of quantum logic can generate a possibility to agree on disagree. This is a good place to point out that our emphasize on similarity between the classical (S5) and quantum knowledge operators is a bit provocative, since this similarity is only formal, operational, and from the logical viewpoint these are very different representations of knowledge.

In fact, understanding of “what quantum logic is from semantic viewpoint” is a complex problem by itself, see, e.g., works of Garola [36] and of Garola and Sozzo [37] and the recent paper of Khrennikov and Schumann [38] for details. One of still debated problems is whether one can really assign to propositions a special “quantum truth” value or it is even possible to proceed with the classical truth value. In [38] it was motivated that the essence of logical nonclassicality is the performative part of quantum mechanics and at the theoretical level one can still proceed with classical logic. Thus it was motivated that even in quantum physics logical nonclassicality is only due to the language representation. Such a discussion is helpful to come closer to understanding the following fundamental problem: whether quantumness is in the world or in the mind. It seems that the argument presented in [38] supports the latter, i.e., that violations of classical logic and “quantum logical effects” are generated by the performative structure used for the interpretation of some natural and mental phenomena.

In this context it may useful to use the scientific methodology in which any scientific representation has two level, the ontic level and the epistemic level, see, e.g., Atmanspacher and Primas [39]. In such an approach violation of classical logic happens at the level of epistemic description.

Appendix 3: Classical Formalization for the Aumann Argument

Aumann’s considerations are applicable for a finite number of agents, call them \(i=1,2,..., N.\) These individuals are about to learn the answers to various multi-choice questions, to make observations.

Mathematically the situation is represented with the aid of classical probability space (based on the Kolmogorov axiomatics, 1933). Typically it is assumed that the state space \(\varOmega \) representing all possible states of the world is finite. Events are subsets of \(\varOmega .\)

Each agent creates its information representation for possible states of the world based on its own possibilities to perform measurements, “to ask questions to the world.” Mathematically these represetations are given by partitions of \(\varOmega : \mathcal{P}^{(i)}= (P_j^{(i)}),\) where \(\cup _j P_j^{(i)}= \varOmega \) and \(P_j^{(i)} \cap P_k^{(i)} \emptyset , j\not =k.\) Thus an agent cannot get to know the state of the world \(\omega \) precisely; she can only get to know to which element of its information partition \(P_j^{(i)}= P_j^{(i)}(\omega )\) this \(\omega \) belongs. The agent \(i\) knows an event \(E\) in the state of the world \(\omega \) if

$$\begin{aligned} P_j^{(i)}(\omega ) \subset E. \end{aligned}$$
(17)

It is assumed that on \(\varOmega \) there is defined probability \(p,\) the common prior of all agents. In the accordance with the measure-theoretic model of probability theory (Kolmogorov, 1933) there is given a \(\sigma \)-algebra, say \(\mathcal{F},\) of subsets of \(\varOmega ,\) its elements represent events (“propositions” in some interpretations), and there is given a probability measure \(p\) defined on \(\mathcal{F}.\) In the knowledge models it is typically assumed that \(\mathcal{F}\) is generated by agents’ partitions, i.e., this is the minimal \(\sigma \)-algebra containing all systems of set \(\mathcal{P}^{(i)}, i=1,...,N.\)

We consider the systems of sets \(\tilde{\mathcal{P}}^{(i)}=\{ \cup _m P^{(i)}_{j_m}\}\) consisting of finite unions of the elements of the systems \(\mathcal{P}^{(i)}\) and the system \(\tilde{\mathcal{P}} = \cap _i \tilde{\mathcal{P}}^{(i)}.\) We recall that the meet of the partitions \(\mathcal{P}^{(i)},\) denoted by the symbol \(\wedge _i \mathcal{P}^{(i)},\) is the finest common coarsening of \(\mathcal{P}^{(i)}.\) In particular, \(\wedge _i \mathcal{P}^{(i)} \subset \tilde{\mathcal{P}}.\)

As was proven in [29], an event \(E\) is common knowledge at \(\omega \) if \(E\) contains that element of \(\mathcal{P}^{(1)} \wedge \mathcal{P}^{(2)}\) (the meet) containing \(\omega .\) (See footnote 3 on the definition of common knowledge.)

This result implies that, for each \(i,\) the set of all states of the world for which \(E\) is common knowledge, denoted by the symbol \(\kappa E,\) can be represented (in the case \(\kappa E \not = \emptyset \)) in the form:

$$\begin{aligned} \kappa E= \cup _m P^{(i)}_{j_m}. \end{aligned}$$
(18)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this paper

Cite this paper

Khrennikov, A., Basieva, I. (2015). Quantum(-Like) Decision Making: On Validity of the Aumann Theorem. In: Atmanspacher, H., Bergomi, C., Filk, T., Kitto, K. (eds) Quantum Interaction. QI 2014. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 8951. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-15931-7_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-15931-7_9

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-15930-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-15931-7

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics