Skip to main content

Belief Revision and Dynamic Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 5))

Abstract

We explore belief change policies in a modal dynamic logic that explicitly delineates knowledge, belief, plausibility and the dynamics of these notions. Taking a Kripke semantics counterpart to Grove semantics for AGM as a starting point, we analyse belief in a basic modal language containing epistemic and doxastic modalities. We critically discuss some philosophical presuppositions underlying various modelling assumptions commonly made in the literature, such as the limit assumption and negative introspection for knowledge. Finally, we introduce in the language a general dynamic mechanism and define various policies of iterated belief expansion, revision, contraction and two-dimensional belief change operations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This caused in turn a proliferation of acronyms such as \({\mathsf {DEL}}\) for ‘dynamic epistemic logic’ which limits our freedom in using those that would naturally arise with our terminology throughout the chapter. We thus use \(\mathsf {EDL}\) to stand for ‘epistemic doxastic logic’. The reader should try not to get confused by this choice.

  2. 2.

    Grove [29] himself used maximal consistent sets of sentences rather than possible worlds, but this difference need not concern us here.

  3. 3.

    We choose the notation \(\fancyscript{B}\) as a mnemonic device for ‘belief’.

  4. 4.

    Grove does not talk about beliefs, but about theories, and his semantics is about theory change broadly construed. However, his semantics is directly tailored to accommodate the \({\mathsf {AGM}}\) postulates, so we focus exclusively on a doxastic interpretation of his system.

  5. 5.

    Unlike Grove, we read \(x\le _\fancyscript{B}y\) as “\(y\) is more plausible than \(x\) according to \(\le \)” and talk of maximal worlds instead of minimal worlds. Katsuno and Mendelzon [32] is a seminal reference for the use of ordering semantics within the belief revision community.

  6. 6.

    Alexandru Baltag (p.c.) has reminded us that Stalnaker [47, p. 102] endorses a condition akin to universality (see Stalnaker’s semantic condition (2)). Thus irrevocable belief must be true, and our argument against its identification with knowledge is no longer applicable. This is correct, but endorsing universality in this context means arguing that only metaphysical necessities can be known, since no metaphysically possible world gets epistemically excluded. For this reason, we strongly prefer not to require universality.

  7. 7.

    Our reservation to assume the limit assumption from the outset is not only driven by philosophical concerns. To find an adequate axiomatisation of the limit assumption in our framework is not easy, and presently we can only make an informed conjecture that, in the context of the other axioms we are using, the axiom known as the ‘Löb’s axiom’ is exactly what we need. We will come back to this point below.

  8. 8.

    The indexical stance is represented in the models of Board [14, pp. 60–61], van Ditmarsch [20, p. 237], and van Benthem [9, p. 138], while Baltag and Smets [3, p. 12] and [4, pp. 17–23] prefer a presentation in terms of global plausibility relations.

  9. 9.

    Similar ideas of extending positive and negative introspection assumptions about belief were advanced by Stalnaker [48, p. 145] [49, p. 189] and Board [14, pp. 60–61]. See Demey [19, p. 387] on “uniform” epistemic plausibility models.

  10. 10.

    We will return to this point later, see the comment on definitions (8.2)–(8.4) in Sect. 8.3.2.

  11. 11.

    Similarly for van Ditmarsch’s [20, p. 237] ‘doxastic-epistemic state’.

  12. 12.

    Perhaps making some worlds “infinitely implausible”.

  13. 13.

    Even positive introspection for knowledge, the so-called KK thesis, has been much contested, especially in the light of the success of externalist and reliabilist accounts in epistemology. Very recently, some new defenders of KK have entered the scene, see Okasha [38] and Greco [28].

  14. 14.

    Lenzen [35] and, following Lenzen, Stalnaker [49] offer very strong arguments in favour of defining \(B\varphi \) as \(\lnot K\lnot K\varphi \). In the light of this definition. Brouwer’s principle, which corresponds to the symmetry of the accessibility relation, just means \(B\varphi \rightarrow \varphi \), i.e., infallibility! Lenzen [35, p. 43], Lamarre and Shoham [33, pp. 415, 420] and Stalnaker [49, p. 179] advocate the principle of strong belief \(B\varphi \rightarrow BK\varphi \) (the term “strong belief” is Stalnaker’s, Lamarre and Shoham use the term “certainty”). Taken together with the strong belief principle, the interaction principle \(BK\varphi \rightarrow K\varphi \) implies the undesirable \(B\varphi \rightarrow K\varphi \). – In his attempt to maintain negative introspection for knowledge, Halpern [30] proposes to restrict the principle that knowledge implies belief to nonmodal sentences.

  15. 15.

    Given the transitivity of \(\le \), a condition equivalent to the transitivity of \(\sim \) thus defined is the requirement of weak connectedness of \(\le \) both forwards and backwards, also known as “no branching of \(\le \) to the left or to the right”:

    If \(\textit{w}\le u\) and \(\textit{w}\le \textit{v}\), then either \(u\le \textit{v}\) or \(\textit{v}\le u\)    (NBR)

    If \(u\le \textit{w}\) and \(\textit{v}\le \textit{w}\), then either \(u\le \textit{v}\) or \(\textit{v}\le u\)    (NBL)

    This requirement is used by Baltag et al. [6, p. 396].

  16. 16.

    The presence of \(\sim \) and \(<\) is thus redundant, as they are definable in terms of \(\le \) in models, but we keep them for reasons that will become clear later.

  17. 17.

    Here are a few hints how this situation could get remedied. The picture is basically that within each indistinguishability cell (\(\sim \)-cell), there is a single system of spheres \({\$}\) that need not exhaust this cell. In order to characterize \(\bigcup \$_\fancyscript{B}\), we suggest to extend epistemic doxastic models by a new relation \(\leadsto \) that helps representing non-universal systems of spheres (see Sect. 8.2—but now everything happens within every single \(\sim \)-cell). \(\leadsto \) should be a serial, transitive and Euclidean subrelation of the global indistinguishability relation \(\sim \) that specifies a unique set of “conceivable” worlds within each set of indistinguishable worlds. Intuitively, \(u \leadsto \textit{v}\) for worlds \(u\) and v means that \(u\sim \textit{v}\) and v is within the relevant \(\sim \)-cell’s system of spheres. Thus, if \(u\sim \textit{v}\) and \(u\leadsto \textit{w}\), then also \(\textit{v}\leadsto \textit{w}\). We would also need to harmonise \(\leadsto \) with \(<\) (and \(\le \)), by conditions like ‘If \(u\sim \textit{v}\) and \(\textit{w}\leadsto u\) but not \(\textit{w}\leadsto \textit{v}\), then \(\textit{v}<u\)’ and ‘If \(u\sim \textit{v}\) and there is no \(w\) such that \(\textit{w}\leadsto u\) or \(\textit{w}\leadsto \textit{v}\), then neither \(u<\textit{v}\) nor \(\textit{v}<u\).’ We would then use \(\langle \leadsto \rangle \) and \([\leadsto ]\) rather than \(\langle \sim \rangle \) and \([\sim ]\) in the definitions (8.4) and (8.7) of conditional belief. Correspondingly, the notion of irrevocable belief would reduce to \([\leadsto ]\varphi \) rather than \([\sim ]\varphi \). Knowledge that \(\varphi \) (in the indistinguishability sense) would then imply irrevocable belief that \(\varphi \), but not vice versa, as desired.

  18. 18.

    Definition (8.4) is an exception. But even on this definition, we have \(B(\varphi |\psi ) \rightarrow K B (\varphi |\psi )\). It is easy to see this. Assume that \(M, \textit{w}\models B(\varphi |\psi )\) for some w. For \(M, w\models KB(\varphi |\psi )\), we need to show that \(M, \textit{v}\models B(\varphi |\psi )\) for all \(v\) such that \(w\sim v\). By definition, \(M, w\models B(\varphi |\psi )\) means that either \(M, w\models [\sim ]\lnot \psi \) or \(M, w\models \langle \sim \rangle {(\psi \wedge [\le ]{(\psi \rightarrow \varphi )})}\). But the truth value of both of these sentences are independent of the world v of evaluation, as long as \(w\sim v\). So either \(M, \textit{v}\models [\sim ]\lnot \psi \) or \(M, \textit{v}\models \langle \sim \rangle {(\psi \wedge [\le ]{(\psi \rightarrow \varphi )})}\), and thus \(M, \textit{v}\models B(\varphi |\psi )\), as desired.

  19. 19.

    The modality ‘\([\le ]\)’ is referred to as “knowledge” by Lamarre and Shoham [33, p. 418], as “knowledge according to the defeasibility analysis” by Stalnaker [49, Sect. 6], and as “safe belief”, “defeasible knowledge” and “Stalnaker knowledge” by Baltag and Smets [4, see in particular pp. 27–32]. In contrast to \(K \varphi \) and \(B \varphi \), the truth value of \([\le ]\varphi \) is in general not constant within a \(\sim \)-cell. The early chapter of Lamarre and Shoham is interesting: It disavows negative introspection for knowledge and finds strong belief (“certainty”) that \(\varphi \) to be equivalent with \(\lnot K\lnot K\varphi \)—points we acclaim from a philosophical perspective. But it also finds knowledge that \(\varphi \) to be equivalent with the conditional belief \(B(\varphi |\lnot \varphi )\)—a result we object to from a philosophical perspective. This unexpected conjunction is connected with the fact that Lamarre and Shoham let not only knowledge, but also conditional belief and conditional certainty vary from world to world, and thus disavow negative introspection for conditional belief and conditional certainty, too.

  20. 20.

    The most descriptive term ‘modularity’ was suggested by Ginsberg [26, p. 49]; ‘almost-connectedness’ is due to van Benthem [7, 8], pp. 194, 232], ‘virtual connectivity’ to Alchourón and Makinson [2, p. 415]. Notice that there is also a different sense of ‘almost-connectedness’ in the literature (see Doble et al. [22]).

  21. 21.

    See Blackburn, de Rijke and Venema [13, pp. 130–132]. It would be nice to have a more compact axiomatisation of K4 plus (Mod\(<\)) and (Löb\(<\)). At this point, we can only conjecture that adding Löb is sufficient to get a complete axiomatisation with the limit assumption, but we have to leave open the problem of showing the logic to be (weakly) complete with respect to the relevant class of frames.

  22. 22.

    The accustomed reader will recognise this as something very much like a public announcement.

  23. 23.

    Any \(\mathsf {PDL}\) transformation which outputs a Grove relation would be formally legitimate. To categorise this general class of transformations is still an open problem in \(\mathsf {GDDL}\), and we will not address it here, as our main concern is with \({\mathsf {AGM}}\) motivated transformations.

  24. 24.

    Slightly abusing the term “maximality”, one could also experiment with putting \(\mathsf{{max} (\varphi )}::= (\varphi \wedge ([<] \lnot \varphi \vee [\le ] \varphi ))\), but we will not pursue this idea in the present chapter.

  25. 25.

    For complex sentences \(\varphi \) that involve doxastic operators, it is possible that \(\varphi \) becomes true again at a \(\lnot \varphi \)-world after other doxastic transformations. The old \(\varphi \)-worlds are irrevocable. It is the worlds that are irrevocable, not sentences. Only Boolean sentences (those without modalities) are truly irrevocable. This is related to the consideration of the \({\mathsf {AGM}}\) success postulate: Only Boolean sentences are guaranteed to be successful. If one revises by a sentence that says “\(p\) is true but you don’t know it”, then one does not get success.

  26. 26.

    How can we evaluate a sentence at a world v which has vanished in the course of the evaluation? Above, we have stipulated that \(M, \textit{w}\models [{\mathrm {\Lambda }}]\varphi \) to be vacuously true in case \(M, \textit{w}\not \models |{\mathrm {\Lambda }}|\), in order to avoid facing the main clause \({\mathrm {\Lambda }}M,\textit{w} \models \varphi \) when w fails to be in \({\mathrm {\Lambda }}W\) of \({\mathrm {\Lambda }}M\). But evidently, this is not a solution to the problem of untruthful public announcements or radical revisions.

  27. 27.

    The limit assumption guarantees this. If, however, the limit assumption is not satisfied, revision by comparison as defined below may fail to make the input sentence at least as firmly accepted as the reference sentence.

  28. 28.

    Also compare Rott [43].

  29. 29.

    Notice that the transformation \((\lnot [\le ]\psi ? \, ; \, \le ) \, \cup \, (\sim \, ; \, [<] \psi ?)\) is identical to the transformation \(\le \, \cup \, (\sim \, ; \, [<] \psi ?)\), because \(M,w\models [\le ]\psi \) and \(w\le v\) taken together imply \(M,v\models [<]\psi \).

References

  1. Alchourrón CE, Gärdenfors P, Makinson D (1985) On the logic of theory change: partial meet contraction and revision functions. J Symbolic Logic 50:510–530

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Alchourrón CE, Makinson D (1985) On the logic of theory change: safe contraction. Stud Logica 44:405–422

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Baltag A, Smets S (2006) Conditional doxastic models: a qualitative approach to dynamic belief revision. Electron Notes Theoret Comput Sci 165:5–21 (2006). (Proceedings WoLLIC 2006)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Baltag A, Smets S (2008) A qualitative theory of dynamic interactive belief revision. In: Bonanno G, van der Hoek W, Wooldridge M (eds) Logic and the foundations of game and fdecision theory (LOFT 7). Texts in logic and games, vol 3. Amsterdam University Press, Amsterdam, pp 11–58

    Google Scholar 

  5. Baltag A, Smets S (2008) The logic of conditional doxastic actions. In: Apt KR, van Rooij R (eds) New perspectives on games and interaction. Texts in logic and games, vol 4. Amsterdam University Press, Amsterdam, pp 9–31

    Google Scholar 

  6. Baltag A, van Ditmarsch H, Moss LS (2008) Epistemic logic and information update. In: Adriaans P, van Benthem J (eds) Philosophy of information. Handbook of the philosophy of science. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 361–455

    Google Scholar 

  7. van Benthem J (1982) Later than late: on the logical origin of the temporal order. Pac Philos Q 63:193–203

    Google Scholar 

  8. van Benthem J (1983) The logic of time. A model-theoretic investigation into the varieties of temporal antology and temporal discourse. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  9. van Benthem J (2007) Dynamic logic for belief revision. J Appl Non-class Logic 17:129–155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. van Benthem J, Girard P, Roy O (2009) Everything else being equal: a modal logic for ceteris paribus preferences. J Philos Logic 38:83–125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. van Benthem J, Liu F (2007) Dynamic logic of preference upgrade. J Appl Non-Class Logics 17:157–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. van Benthem J, Roy O, van Otterloo S (2006) Preference logic, conditionals, and solution concepts in games. In: Lagerlund, L, Sliwinski S (eds) Modality matters: twenty-five essays in honour of Krister Segerberg, vol 53. Uppsala Philosophical Studie. Uppsala Universitet, Uppsala

    Google Scholar 

  13. Blackburn P, de Rijke M, Venema Y (2001) Modal logic. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Board O (2004) Dynamic interactive epistemology. Games Econ Behav 49:49–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Boutilier C (1994) Unifying default reasoning and belief revision in a modal framework. Artif Intell 68:33–85

    Google Scholar 

  16. Boutilier C (1996) Iterated revision and minimal change of conditional beliefs. J Philos Logic 25:263–305

    Google Scholar 

  17. Darwiche A, Pearl J (1997) On the logic of iterated belief revision. Artif Intell 89:1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. David K (1973). Counterfactuals. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  19. Demey L (2011) Some remarks on the model theory of epistemic plausibility models. J Appl Non-class Logics 21:375–395

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. van Ditmarsch H (2005) Prolegomena to dynamic logic for belief revision. Synthese 147:229–275

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. van Ditmarsch H, van der Hoek W, Kooi B (2007) Dynamic epistemic logic, vol 1. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  22. Doble CW, Doignon J-P, Falmagne J-C, Fishburn PC (2001) Almost connected orders. Order 18:295–311

    Google Scholar 

  23. Fermé E, Rott H (2004) Revision by comparison. Artif Intell 157:5–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Fischer MJ, Ladner RE (1979) Propositional dynamic logic of regular programs. J Comput Syst Sci 18:194–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Gärdenfors P, Makinson D (1988) Revisions of knowledge systems using epistemic entrenchment. In: Vardi M (ed) Proceedings of the second conference on theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge (TARK’88), pp 83–95. Morgan Kaufmann, Los Altos, CA

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ginsberg ML (1986) Counterfactuals. Artif Intell 30:35–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Girard P, Seligman J, Liu F (2012) General dynamic dynamic logic. In: Bolander T, Braüner T, Ghilardi S, Moss LS (eds) Advances in modal logics, vol 9. College, London, pp 239–260

    Google Scholar 

  28. Greco D. Could KK be OK? J Philos. (Forthcoming)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Grove A (1988) Two modellings for theory change. J Philos Logic 17:157–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Halpern JY (1996) Should knowledge entail belief? J Philos Logic 25:483–494

    Google Scholar 

  31. Hintikka J (1962) Knowledge and belief, vol 414. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  32. Katsuno H, Mendelzon AO (1991) Propositional knowledge base revision and minimal change. Artif Intell 52:263–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Lamarre P, Shoham Y (1994) Knowledge, certainty, belief, and conditionalisation (abbreviated version). In: Proceedings of KR’94, pp 415–424

    Google Scholar 

  34. Leitgeb H, Segerberg K (2007) Dynamic doxastic logic: why, how, and where to? Synthese 155:167–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Lenzen W (1979) Epistemologische Betrachtungen zu [S4, S5]. Erkenntnis 14:33–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Levi I (2004) Mild contraction: evaluating loss of information due to loss of belief. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  37. Nayak A (1994) Iterated belief change based on epistemic entrenchment. Erkenntnis 41:353–390

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Okasha S (2013) On a flawed argument against the KK principle. Analysis 73:80–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Pagnucco M, Rott H (1999) Severe withdrawal—and recovery. J Philos Logic 28:501–547

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Plaza J (2007) Logics of public communications. Synthese 158:165–179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Pratt VR (1976) Semantical considerations on Floyd-Hoare logic. In: Technical report, MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  42. Rott H (2009) Shifting priorities: simple representations for twenty-seven iterated theory change operators. In: Makinson D, Malinowski J, Wansing H (eds) Towards mathematical philosophy. Trends in logic, vol 28. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 269–296

    Google Scholar 

  43. Rott H (2006) Revision by comparison as a unifying framework: severe withdrawal, irrevocable revision and irrefutable revision. Theoret Comput Sci 355:228–242

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Rott H (2012) Bounded revision: Two-dimensional belief change between conservative and moderate revision. J Philos Logic 41:173–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Segerberg K (1971) An essay in classical modal logic. Filosofiska studier utgivna av Filosofiska föreningen och Filosofiska institutionen vid Uppsala universitet, vol 1. Filosofiska föreningen och Filosofiska institutionen vid Uppsala universitet

    Google Scholar 

  46. Segerberg K (1998) Irrevocable belief revision in dynamic doxastic logic. Notre Dame J Formal Logic 39:287–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Stalnaker R (1968) A theory of conditionals. In: Rescher N (ed) Studies in logical theory. APQ monograph series, vol 2. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 98–112

    Google Scholar 

  48. Stalnaker R (1996) Knowledge, belief and counterfactual reasoning in games. Econ Philos 12:133–163

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Stalnaker R (2006) On logics of knowledge and belief. Philos Stud 128:169–199

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Alexandru Baltag, Johan van Benthem and Michael Hillas for very valuable comments on a previous version of this chapter. We dedicate this chapter to Johan van Benthem, whom we admire as a researcher and who has been, in many and various ways, a friend and mentor to both of us. Thank you so much, Johan!

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Girard .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Girard, P., Rott, H. (2014). Belief Revision and Dynamic Logic. In: Baltag, A., Smets, S. (eds) Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-06025-5_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics