Skip to main content

Affordances and Unreflective Freedom

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Phenomenology of Embodied Subjectivity

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 71))

Abstract

This chapter investigates the phenomenon of freedom in unreflective decision making and action from the perspective of the philosophy of embodied cognition. Phenomenological analysis suggests that in skillful unreflective decision and action we allow ourselves to be responsive to relevant affordances. Even though we respond to affordances with instinctive ease, we do not experience these actions as fully automatic, or beyond our control. I propose that if we want to understand the phenomenon of freedom in episodes of unreflective affordance-responsiveness, we should investigate it on its own terms and do justice to its specific phenomenology. I critically assess ideas on this type of freedom by Dreyfus and Kelly and show that their accounts still presuppose the possibility to reflect, which makes them inapt as accounts of the unreflective freedom in affordance responsiveness that adults share with children who do not yet have the capacity to reflect. I suggest that being bound by relevant affordances does not contradict freedom and sketch the outline of an alternative account of freedom in unreflective action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Let me briefly sketch the context in which freedom (strong spontaneity) appears within McDowell’s (1996) framework. McDowell wants to place strong spontaneity steadfastly in nature. He argues that conformity to natural law does not exhaust the notion of nature. Second nature is nature too. The notion of Bildung (upbringing) clarifies how we acquire the conceptual capacities (second nature, again remembering that this really is nature) that belong to strong spontaneity and make it possible to step back and reflect. We acquire these conceptual capacities thanks to our being initiated into language (McDowell 1996: 125–126). This account should make sure that such freedom is not considered as supra-natural or spooky.

  2. 2.

    Both humans and non-human animals (henceforth ‘animals’) can perceive affordances. McDowell, for instance, recently wrote: “[R]esponsiveness to affordances, necessarily bound up with embodied coping skills, is something we share with other animals.” (McDowell 2007a: 344).

  3. 3.

    Note that this leaves open the possibility that in the end the possibility to step back is relevant in unreflective freedom. I just want to avoid presupposing it, because that could easily lead to an over-intellectualization.

  4. 4.

    Thanks to Rasmus Thybo Jensen for helpful suggestions on how to make my approach explicit.

  5. 5.

    It is crucial to see that strong and weak notions of freedom are not necessarily exclusive. Someone can hold that our understanding of freedom in unreflective action benefits from using a weaker notion of freedom, without committing herself to denying that mature human beings in unreflective action have the capacity to step back and reflect (that is, strong spontaneity).

  6. 6.

    Merleau-Ponty gives a good description of an episode of absorbed coping: “For the player in action the football field is […] pervaded with lines of force […] and articulated in sectors (for example, the ‘openings’ between the adversaries) […]; the player becomes one with it and feels the direction of the ‘goal’, for example, just as immediately as the vertical and the horizontal planes of his own body. It would not be sufficient to say that consciousness inhabits this milieu. At this moment consciousness is nothing other than the dialectic of milieu and action. Each maneuver undertaken by the player modifies the character of the field and establishes in it new lines of force in which the action in turn unfolds and is accomplished, again altering the phenomenal field.” (Merleau-Ponty 1983/1942: 168–169).

  7. 7.

    Sean Kelly gave a lecture on this topic at Cornell University’s ‘Perception and Action Symposium’ on May 7, 2006. I would like to thank him for allowing me to discuss a text that is only a draft manuscript. The draft is available online: http://philpapers.org/rec/KELPNA.

  8. 8.

    The role of such lived normativity (Rietveld 2008a) becomes, for instance, clear in Dreyfus’ and Kelly’s elaboration on Sartre’s (1954) example of running to catch a streetcar: “[T]here is no ego […] in the runner’s mind when he is absorbed in reaching the streetcar […] But […] the experience of chasing a streetcar does not leave the mind empty. It essentially involves a felt solicitation to act in a certain way with respect to the streetcar.” (Dreyfus and Kelly 2007: 53, my italics). This “felt solicitation” contains a normative tension. The mind is not empty in absorbed coping because we “experience our current bodily situation as a tension away from the optimal stance” (Dreyfus and Kelly 2007: 53), and are immediately drawn to improve, running faster and getting closer.

  9. 9.

    Note that this seems to presuppose that resisting an affordance is something that I as a reflective subject must do.

  10. 10.

    Kelly models his account of a change in the nature of attention (from engaged to detached) on Heidegger’s (1927) account of a worldly breakdown: “The phenomenological story I’ve sketched so far involves moving from the kind of sensitivity to environmental norms that is involved in skillful absorbed coping to the kind of detached experience of an independent world that one can have when one is paying attention to it. In the metaphor from the introduction, it involves the crystallization of self and world.” (Kelly 2006: 14, my italics).

  11. 11.

    Note that sometimes Kelly (2006) uses the word ‘attention’ as shorthand for this attentive observation or detached attention.

  12. 12.

    Note the analogy of this aspect of Kelly’s proposal with McDowell’s account of strong spontaneity, which is based on the capacity to step back and reflect. A difference is that, as we will see below, Kelly stresses that the individual cannot exercise this capacity for attentive observation willfully in absorbed coping.

  13. 13.

    “[T]he source of the movement [from absorbed coping to attentive observation is] not the world but the coping agent himself. That is why it is a story about human freedom, rather than a story about worldly breakdown.” (Kelly 2006: 15).

  14. 14.

    Dreyfus and Kelly convincingly make this point by means of Sartre’s (1954) streetcar example: “When I run after a streetcar…there is no I…. I am plunged into the world of objects … which present themselves …with attractive and repellant qualities – but me, I have disappeared.” (Sartre 1954: 48, as quoted in Dreyfus and Kelly 2007: 46). This description suggests that we should not speak of a reflective subject or ego in absorbed coping: “[T]here is no ego […] in the runner’s mind when he is absorbed in reaching the streetcar […]” (Dreyfus and Kelly 2007: 53). Note that this example does not exclude the possibility that there is pre-reflective self-awareness in such an episode of absorbed coping. Even though in this episode of absorbed coping we do not experience ourselves as a reflective subject, on the basis of this example we cannot say that there is no self-awareness at all. We have to understand what is means that the mind is not “empty” (Dreyfus and Kelly 2007: 53). Minimally this type of skillful engagement with the world includes an experience of the lived body being drawn by solicitations.

  15. 15.

    Just to be clear: this is an aim my chapter does not share with Dreyfus.

  16. 16.

    To repeat Dreyfus’ own words: “Our involved freedom makes possible on some occasions finding ourselves becoming detached and choosing a course of action which, like all willful actions, we can perform at best competently, while on other occasions, letting ourselves be drawn to reenter our involved expert activity.” (Dreyfus 2007a: 355).

  17. 17.

    He writes for instance the following about such an experience in absorbed coping: “My experience of environmental norms is always such that resistance could occur, and this differentiates me from the animals. And to the extent that the norms continue to hold me, there is a sense in which I have allowed them to do so.” (Kelly 2006: 16). Kelly describes the experience of freedom in unreflective action well here, but the account he gives in terms of “noticing” does not do justice to this phenomenon.

  18. 18.

    However, we have seen also in the introduction that McDowell (2002) acknowledges in his response to Taylor (2002) that it is important to develop a better understanding of freedom in animal behavior.

  19. 19.

    This example comes from the work of primatologist Frans de Waal (2004). This example is also interesting because it reminds us of the importance of the network of social relationships for understanding freedom, the crucial link between care and freedom, emphasized in the closing sentences of Merleau-Ponty’s (2002/1945) chapter on freedom. Moreover, De Waal quotes Jane Goodall (1990: 213, in De Waal 2004: 389) saying: “In some zoos, chimpanzees are kept on man-made islands, surrounded by water-filled moats … Chimpanzees cannot swim and, unless they are rescued, will drown if they fall into deep water. Despite this, individuals have sometimes made heroic efforts to save companions from drowning – and were sometimes successful.” De Waal (2004: 389) notes that studies of animal behavior show that dolphins and elephants have similar powerful tendencies to help others.

  20. 20.

    Dreyfus (2005a: 60) calls the question about this transformation an “urgent” one.

  21. 21.

    On the other hand, we should not presuppose that intuitive responsiveness to possibilities for action does not also play a role in the activity of explicit deliberation. It might well be the case that explicit deliberation, as a form of skillful action, shares more characteristics with skillful unreflective action than is generally assumed at the moment. Moreover, the balance between reflection and unreflective action is typically maintained unreflectively (De Haan, Rietveld & Denys 2013).

  22. 22.

    A Wittgensteinian case of such a transition in a flow of unreflective action could be the situation in which the lapels have adequately been dealt with by the tailor and now he is moved to improve by another part of the same suit.

  23. 23.

    Note that in the case of mere movements that are not actions, for example when we are unexpectedly pushed by someone, the initial movements we make are not instances of responsiveness to relevant affordances. On the other hand, the way we respond briefly after being pushed, for example by grasping someone’s arm (but not her breasts or hair) to avoid falling, and the way the compensatory movements develop over time after the initial automatic reaction, can be understood in terms of such responsiveness to affordances.

  24. 24.

    I mean here situated normativity in the basic sense of distinguishing in the context of a particular situation between better and worse, optimal and suboptimal, appropriate and inappropriate, what is significant and what it less significant, etc.

References

  • Arendt, H. (1958). The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1977/1961). Between past and future: Eight exercises in political thought. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2003). An outline of a theory of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 15(2), 181–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Haan, S., Rietveld, E., & Denys, D. (2013). On the nature of obsessions and compulsions. In D. S. Baldwin & B. E. Leonard (Eds.), Anxiety disorders, modern trends in pharmacopsychiatry (pp. 1–15). Basel: Karger.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Haan, S., Rietveld, E., Stokhof, M., & Denys, D. (2013). The phenomenology of deep brain stimulation-induced changes in OCD: an enactive affordance-based model. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7(653), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Waal, F. B. M. (2004). On the possibility of animal empathy. In A. S. R. Manstead, N. H. Frijda, & A. H. Fisher (Eds.), Feelings and emotions: The Amsterdam symposium (pp. 381–401). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2005a). Overcoming the myth of the mental: How philosophers can profit from the phenomenology of everyday expertise (APA Pacific Division Presidential Address 2005). Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 79(2), 47–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2005b). Merleau-Ponty and recent cognitive science. In T. Carman & M. B. Hansen (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Merleau-Ponty (pp. 129–150). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2007a). The return of the myth of the mental. Inquiry, 50(4), 352–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2007b). Response to McDowell. Inquiry, 50(4), 371–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2007c). Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing it would require making it more Heideggerian. Barwise Lecture. http://cid.nada.kth.se/en/HeideggerianAI.pdf. Accessed 22 Nov 2007.

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2007c). Reply to Romdenh-Romluc. In T. Baldwin (Ed.), Reading Merleau-Ponty: On phenomenology of perception (pp. 59–69). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L., & Kelly, S. D. (2007). Heterophenomenology: Heavy-handed sleight-of-hand. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 45–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, N. H. (1986). The emotions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, N. H. (2007). The laws of emotion. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, N. H. (2010). Not passion’s slave. Emotion Review, 2, 68–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodall, J. (1990). Through a window: My thirty years with the chimpanzees of Gombe. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1996/1927). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, S. D. (2005). Closing the gap: Phenomenology and logical analysis. The Harvard Review of Philosophy, XIII, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, S. D. (2006, May 7). Perceptual normativity and human freedom. Unpublished draft paper presented at Cornell University’s ‘Perception and Action Symposium’, Ithaca, NY. http://philpapers.org/rec/KELPNA. Accessed 25 Apr 2013.

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2002). Responses. In N. H. Smith (Ed.), Reading McDowell: On mind and world (pp. 269–305). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2007a). What myth? Inquiry, 50(4), 338–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2007b). Response to Dreyfus. Inquiry, 50(4), 366–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1983/1942). The structure of behavior (A. L. Fisher, Trans.). Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002/1945). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaels, C. F. (2003). Affordances: Four points of debate. Ecological Psychology, 15(2), 135–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2004, June 26–28). The nature of everyday coping. Reinterpreting Merleau-Pontys phenomenology of concrete habitual coping in the light of Varelas naturalization of time-consciousness. In Presented at the ‘8th conference of the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness’ (ASSC8), Antwerp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2008a). Situated normativity: The normative aspect of embodied cognition in unreflective action. Mind, 117(468), 973–1001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2008b). The skillful body as a concernful system of possible actions: Phenomena and neurodynamics. Theory & Psychology, 18(3), 341–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2008c). Unreflective action. A philosophical contribution to integrative neuroscience. University of Amsterdam Dissertation, Amsterdam, ILLC-Dissertation Series.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2010). McDowell and Dreyfus on unreflective action. Inquiry, 53(2), 183–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2012). Bodily intentionality and social affordances in context. In F. Paglieri (Ed.), Consciousness in interaction. The role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness (pp. 207–226). Amsterdam: J. Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romdenh-Romluc, K. (2007). Merleau-Ponty and the power to reckon with the possible. In T. Baldwin (Ed.), Reading Merleau-Ponty: On phenomenology of perception (pp. 44–58). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1954). The transcendence of the ego. New York: Noonday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (2002). Foundationalism and the inner-outer distinction. In N. H. Smith (Ed.), Reading McDowell: On mind and world (pp. 106–119). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Hubert Dreyfus, Nico Frijda, Janna van Grunsven, Sean Kelly, Martin Stokhof, and Rasmus Thybo Jensen for feedback on an earlier version of this chapter. This research project was financially supported by ‘Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research’ (NWO VENI- and VIDI grants). I would like to express my gratitude for awarding these grants.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erik Rietveld .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rietveld, E. (2013). Affordances and Unreflective Freedom. In: Jensen, R., Moran, D. (eds) The Phenomenology of Embodied Subjectivity. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 71. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01616-0_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics