Skip to main content

Religion Plurality and the Logic of the Concept of God

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Beyond Babel: Religion and Linguistic Pluralism

Abstract

In this article, I address some higher-order issues involving the concept of God that arise within a pluralistic context: the problem of conceptual unity, the problem of unicity of extension and the problem of homogeneity/heterogeneity. My proposal to solve these questions involves a special hybrid theory of concepts, called the theory of ideal concepts. I argue that when associated with a pluralistic vision of concepts, and formalized within a possible world structure, such theory provides a satisfactory answer to these problems. The formalization is based on a specific version of the Simplest Quantified Modal Logic (SQML), and its presentation is exclusively semantic, keeping technical details to a minimum.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    To distinguish between the concept of God and the eventual object that falls under it, I refer to the latter using capital letters. Thus, while “God” means the (or a) concept of God, “GOD” means the entity which supposedly falls under the (or a) concept of God (although most of the time I will use the complex expression “concept of God”).

  2. 2.

    Although EAM entails AM, the converse is not true.

  3. 3.

    This appears very clearly, for example, in the Athanasian Creed. Out of its 44 theses, three of them state as follows: (1) “We worship GOD in Trinity and Trinity in Unity… Neither confounding the persons nor dividing the substance.”; (2) “So the Father is GOD, the Son is GOD, and the Holy Spirit is GOD.”; (3) “And yet they are not three GODS, but one GOD.”

  4. 4.

    He is the great Lord of all the worlds (5.29), the Supreme Divine Person (10.12), the God of the gods (10.14) and their origin (10.12, 11.38); no one is equal to or greater than Him (11.38). See Resnick (1995).

  5. 5.

    See that PG does not necessarily conflict with AM. It might be that each one of these concepts of God has at most one instance.

  6. 6.

    Locke seems to assume something very close to the classical theory when he gives an account of the concept of sun, for example: “[T]he Idea of the Sun, what is it, but an aggregate of those several simple Ideas, Bright, Hot, Roundish, having a constant regular motion, at a certain distance from us, and, perhaps, some other” (Locke, 1690/1975, 298–299). Plato’s use of what might be seen as the basic tenets of the classical theory can be found in the Euthyphro and Aristotle’s in the Categories.

  7. 7.

    See Silvestre (2022) for a comprehensive account of the problems with the classical theory applied to the concept of God.

  8. 8.

    While Sects. 2 and 3 rely on Silvestre (2022), Sect. 4 partially relies on Silvestre (2021).

  9. 9.

    George Lakoff, for example, writes as follows (1987, 6): “Many categories are understood in terms of abstract ideal cases—which may be neither typical nor stereotypical. […] Naomi Quinn (personal communication) has observed, based on extensive research on American conceptions of marriage, that there are many kinds of ideal models for a marriage: successful marriages, good marriages, strong marriages, and so on. Successful marriages are those where the goals of the spouses are fulfilled. Good marriages are those where both partners find the marriage beneficial. Strong marriages are those likely to last.” The emphasis is mine.

  10. 10.

    Commenting on this view of abstract objects, Gideon Rosen (2020) writes as follows: “It is widely maintained that causation, strictly speaking, is a relation among events or states of affairs. If we say that the rock—an object—caused the window to break, what we mean is that some event or state (or fact or condition) involving the rock caused the break. If the rock itself is a cause, it is a cause in some derivative sense. But this derivative sense has proved elusive. The rock’s hitting the window is an event in which the rock ‘participates’ in a certain way, and it is because the rock participates in events in this way that we credit the rock itself with causal efficacy. But what is it for an object to participate in an event? Suppose John is thinking about the Pythagorean Theorem and you ask him to say what’s on his mind. His response is an event—the utterance of a sentence; and one of its causes is the event of John’s thinking about the theorem. Does the Pythagorean Theorem ‘participate’ in this event? There is surely some sense in which it does. The event consists in John’s coming to stand in a certain relation to the theorem, just as the rock’s hitting the window consists in the rock’s coming to stand in a certain relation to the glass. But we do not credit the Pythagorean Theorem with causal efficacy simply because it participates in this sense in an event which is a cause. The challenge is therefore to characterize the distinctive manner of ‘participation in the causal order’ that distinguishes the concrete entities. This problem has received relatively little attention. There is no reason to believe that it cannot be solved. But in the absence of a solution, this standard version of the Way of Negation must be reckoned a work in progress.”

  11. 11.

    See that m is a member of both categories.

  12. 12.

    See Linsky and Zalta (1994) and Menzel (2018). What Hughes and Cresswell (1968, 141–169) call the modal lower predicate calculus is usually seen as a version of SQML.

  13. 13.

    See Silvestre (2021) for a full account – semantic as well as proof-theoretical – of this logical theory.

  14. 14.

    See Schurz (2002).

  15. 15.

    There is a third frame feature, which is pseudo-universality. Since the reason why I need pseudo-universal frames goes beyond the issues dealt with in this chapter, I will not explain it. For more on this, see Silvestre (2021).

References

  • Barsalou, L. W. (1985). Ideals, central tendency, and frequency of instantiation as determinants of graded structure in categories. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 11, 629–664.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito, J. (1998). The straight path. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, E. (2008). On the distinction between the concept of God and conceptions of God. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 64, 63–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. E., & Cresswell, M. J. (1968). An introduction to modal logic. Methuen and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1987). Cognitive models and prototype theory. In U. Neisser (Ed.), Concepts and conceptual development (pp. 63–100). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (1999). Concepts and cognitive science. In E. Margolis & S. Laurence (Eds.), Concepts: Core readings (pp. 3–81). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, B., & Zalta, E. N. (1994). In defense of the simplest quantified modal logic. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 8: Logic and language (pp. 431–458). Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1690/1975). An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2019). In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Concepts (Summer 2019 ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/concepts/. Accessed 19 Apr 2023

    Google Scholar 

  • Medin, D., & Schaffer, M. (1978). Context theory of classification learning. Psychological Review, 85, 207–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, C. (2018). In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Simplest Quantified Modal Logic (SQML), supplement to Actualism (Summer 2018 ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/actualism/SQML.html. Accessed 19 Apr 2023

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, G. (2002). The big book of concepts. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (2014). Describing Gods: An investigation of divine attributes. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Resnick, H. (1995). Kṛṣṇa in the Bhagavad-gītā: A beginning ontology from the Gauḍīya perspective. Journal of Vaishnava Studies, 3, 5–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E. (1975). Cognitive representations of semantic categories. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 104, 192–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E. (1978). Principles of categorization. In E. Rosch & B. B. Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition and categorization (pp. 27–48). Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2002). Alethic modal logics and semantics. In D. Jacquette (Ed.), A companion to philosophical logic (pp. 442–477). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silvestre, R. (2021). A formal-logical approach to the concept of God. Manuscrito, 44, 224–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silvestre, R. (2022). On the representation of the concept of God. Philosophia, 50, 731–755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, E., & Medin, D. (1981). Categories and concepts. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tuggy, D. (2006). In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Trinity (Winter 2016 ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/trinity/. Accessed April 19, 2023

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiskopf, D. (2009). The plurality of concepts. Synthese, 169, 145–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. N. (2000). A (Leibnizian) theory of concepts. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 3, 137–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ricardo Sousa Silvestre .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Silvestre, R.S. (2023). Religion Plurality and the Logic of the Concept of God. In: Vestrucci, A. (eds) Beyond Babel: Religion and Linguistic Pluralism. Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures, vol 43. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-42127-3_20

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics