Skip to main content

That Which Guilds the Lily: Moving from Aesthetic Value to an Ethical Aesthetic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Place Based Approaches to Sustainability Volume I

Abstract

For many members of contemporary western societies, the environment is either the theatre upon which we plan and play out our own aspirations, or a basket of resources from which to extract, produce and commercialize consumable ‘goods.’ Infrequently noticed, thought about, or cared for in any substantive way, it is merely the theatre upon which we plan and play out our own aspirations. The same might be said of many ‘sustainability enterprises,’ as the environment is taken, quite literally, as a place-less basket of resources from which to extract, produce and commercialize consumable ‘goods. There is a need, then, for continued work in reframing how we see, interact with, and respond to the environment.

Within the world of environmental conservation, one powerful tool employed to motivate care for the environment is drawn from the field of aesthetics. The attractive qualities of the natural world have long played a crucial role in shaping environmental policy and public concern. Even a cursory overview of the history of conservation work amply demonstrates the motivational leverage of beauty in stimulating significant change to environmental policy and even societal values. However, reliance upon the aesthetic realm also holds its own set of difficulties; employed as a designator of value, it can be overly anthropocentric, exclusionary and unjust, and its ethical purchase weak. What, then, are we to do with beauty and the aesthetic realm? Is it extraneous, representative of elitist ephemera, and even damaging in its influence upon ethical questions?

Against those who are critical of the use of aesthetics in environmental ethics, I take the position that drawing upon aesthetics is crucial if we hope to change human behavior. However, in a departure from the use of aesthetics as a designator of value in service of environmental ethics, I argue that the aesthetic-moral notion of ‘fittingness,’ useful for its familiarity in everyday language, holds normative potential for directing our manner of seeing and relating to the world around us. It holds particular value for the manner in which it directs attention to the local ecology, and challenges our manner of being within that ecology, or, more specifically, an ecological neighborhood. As such, the structure of decorum holds interesting potential for informing a more just and democratic approach to questions of sustainability.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a helpful discussion of sustainability, particularly as derived from the Planetary Boundaries concept, see Downing et al., 2020. For the sake of brevity and the reader’s familiarity, I work with the most well-known, if flawed, WCED definition.

  2. 2.

    Robin Wall Kimmerer describes the sort of local knowledge I have in mind, as she defines Traditional Ecological Knowledge (TEK) as “the knowledge, practice, and belief concerning the relationships of living beings to one another and to the physical environment, which is held by peoples in relatively nontechnical societies with a direct dependence upon local resources … It is born of long intimacy and attentiveness to a homeland and can arise whenever people are materially and spiritually integrated with their landscape. TEK is rational and reliable knowledge that has been developed through generations of intimate contact by native peoples with their lands (Kimmerer, 2002, p. 431 in Whyte, 2013, p. 6). Definitions of TEK are multiple, as is their perceived relationship to scientific knowledge. As Whyte explains, Kimmerer is among those who understand TEK as a type of knowledge parallel to science; they offer “complimentary perspectives on the environment and natural resources” (Whyte, p. 6).

  3. 3.

    Recognizing not all readers share my assumptions regarding a theistic approach to the environment, I will instead utilize a more broadly acceptable cluster of terms, recognizing that even these generate debate: nature, natural world, environment, ecology. I also recognize some will deem my choice to use them interchangeably too imprecise. Nevertheless, I do so as a way of making room for those whose presuppositions differ from my own.

  4. 4.

    See also Fiona Ellis’ notion of ‘expansive naturalism,’ whose work Brady looks to in order “to make room in environmental aesthetics – in theory and in practice – for ideas, concepts, perspectives, philosophies, cosmologies, epistemologies, and varieties of aesthetic experience” (Brady, 2020).

  5. 5.

    For an insightful, in-depth discussion of indigenous land-management practices, and the manner in which Indigenous peoples’ presence shaped the ecology of California in particular, see Anderson’s work: Tending the Wild: Native American Knowledge and the Management of California’s Natural Resources (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press: 2005).

  6. 6.

    The myths surrounding ‘pristine’ nature and the impetus to protect, or cleanse pristine environs of those people considered unclean, or uncivilized, permeated not only imaginary of settler colonialism of the early American landscape, but that of European explorers into ‘new lands’ across the oceans. For one cogent account, see Willie James Jennings, “Binding Landscapes: Secularism, Race, and the Spatial Modern” in Jonathon S. Kahn and Vincent W. Lloyd, eds., Race and Secularism in America (New York: Columbia University Press, 2016), 207–238. My thanks to Andre Price for drawing this article to my attention.

  7. 7.

    Cicero alternates between using the term ‘decorum’ and ‘fittingness.’ I will do the same.

  8. 8.

    Fittingness possesses a surprisingly substantial pedigree, for all of its apparent mundanity. Its elasticity enables all manner of borrowing from its origins in classical Greek rhetoric, from medieval theology to contemporary moral philosophy. Aquinas casts the notion as conveniens, a critical element of his understanding of divine necessity (Bauerschmidt, 2013). Leo Zaibert employs it in relation to questions of justice and punishment (Zaibert, 2006, pp. 331–350), while Christopher Howard examines the notion with regard to attitudes. Ian Hodder’s archeological work offers interesting insight into the relationship between humans and things (Hodder, 2012).

  9. 9.

    Remer contrasts Cicero’s approach with Machiavelli, who cast aside moral constraint for the sake of a thorough-going political utilitarianism. Other scholars concur, giving new attention to the Roman rhetor and politician as an important alternative to Aristotelian approaches to rhetoric and political morality. See also Joy Connolly, The State of Speech: Rhetoric and Political Thought in Ancient Rome (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007).

  10. 10.

    OMO does not take up the question of virtue formation. Nor is question of who may be virtuous, and how. Cicero assumes his readers, well-educated members of the ruling class, are already virtuous, needing guidance only with regard to virtue’s praxis within the rhetorical and political arenas. Indeed, as important as the concept is for Cicero, Remer observes that he never outlines “a clear plan for effecting the change of heart necessary” to engender practice of the virtue (Remer, 2017, p. 60).

  11. 11.

    The link existing between the aesthetic and the moral, or between perception and concept, was later severed by Enlightenment thinkers. However, the relationship between the two has re-emerged among contemporary philosophers and psychologists concerned with theories of mind. Is there a correspondence between these two systems, or are they entirely distinct? The issue is beyond the scope of this chapter to engage, other than to acknowledge that, as one early reader of my chapter commented, fittingness may be one possible avenue for overcoming the divide.

  12. 12.

    This is not to imply the human members of an ecosystem are the sole possessor of agency. It is merely to acknowledge the potential for outsized impact upon the environment human members can bring to an ecosystem.

  13. 13.

    John Wesley Powell was a pioneer of such thinking in the American west. John Wesley Powell, Report on the Lands of the Arid Region of the United States, with a More Detailed Account of the Lands of Utah (reprint ed.). (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1962). Others have since taken up his ideas, including Ched Meyers in Watershed Discipleship: Reinhabiting Bioregional Faith and Practice (Eugene, OR: Cascade Books, 2016), and Daniel Kemmis, a scholar-politician who has long advocated for the need to ‘think like a region’ with regard to ecological-political issues. Community and the Politics of Place (Norman: Oklahoma Press, 1992).

  14. 14.

    The relational strength of fittingness notwithstanding, Scruton does not extensively explore the concept. As I discuss in a larger work in progress, there are critical issues to be mitigated against in his particular drawing of the notion. For instance, the potential for exclusion, through what Turner and Bailey (2021) have termed ‘eco-bordering’ is a concern I take up elsewhere.

  15. 15.

    Space prevents me from discussing the important impact these developments have upon local Indigenous peoples who were the first to find their home in the region. With the development of Palm Springs, and the construction of water infrastructure discussed above, Indigenous peoples found themselves displaced, their lands submerged, and their lifeways ended. As Indigenous scholars argue, this is a recurring and devastating dynamic (Gilio-Whitaker, 2019; LaDuke, 2005).

  16. 16.

    As other scholars have argued, the resilience of social-ecological systems is increased when a strong fit exists between the social-ecological systems and the managing organizations. (Folke, 2006). Others find, further, that it increases management effectiveness, resulting in better allocation, water quality, regional economic performance and, of growing importance, a reduction in conflicts over water (Young, 2002 and Kemper et al., 2010, in Herrfahrdt-Pahle, 2014).

References

  • Anderson, M. K. (2005). Tending the Wild: Native American Knowledge and the Management of California’s Natural Resources. University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, S. B. (2003). Who Sustains Whose Development? Sustainable Development and the Reinvention of Nature. Organization Studies, 24(1), 143–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bauerschmidt, F. C. (2013). Thomas Aquinas: Faith, Reason, and Following Christ: Christian Theology in Context. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brady, E. (2020, October 2–3). Fittingness and Other-Regarding Attitudes in Environmental Aesthetics [Paper presentation]. ILSE Conference, Leuven, Belgium.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero, M. T. (1967). On Moral Obligation (J. Higginbotham, Trans.). University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clough, D. (2012). On Animals. Volume One Systematic Theology. T&T Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coachella Water District. (n.d.). Where Does My Water Come From? http://www.cvwd.org/154/Where-does-my-water-come-from

  • Colish, M. L. (1985). The Stoic Tradition from Antiquity to the Early Middle Ages: Stoicism in Classical Latin Literature (Vol. 1). Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, J. (2007). The State of Speech. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conradie, E. (2005). An Ecological Christian Anthropology: At Home on Earth? Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downing, A. S., Chan, M., Kuiper, J. J., Campenni, M., Häyhä, T., Cornell, S. E., Svedin, U., & Mooij, W. M. (2020). Learning from Generations of Sustainability Concepts. Environmental Research Letters, 15. https://doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/ab7766

  • Eaton, M. (1989). Aesthetics and the Good Life. Fairleigh Dickenson University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Folke, C (2006). Resilience: The emergence of a perspective for social–ecological systems analyses. Global Environmental Change, 16(3), 253–267. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gloenvcha.2006.04.002

  • Gilio-Whitaker, D. (2019). As Long as Grass Grows: The Indigenous Fight for Environmental Justice, from Colonization to Standing Rock. Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, C. (1998). Personhood and Personality: The Four-Personae Theory in Cicero, De Officis I. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 6, 173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, M. T., & Atkins, E. M. (Eds.). (1991). Cicero: On Duties. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hargrove, E. C. (1979). The Historical Foundations of American Environmental Attitudes. Environmental Ethics, 1, 209–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hepburn, R. (1966). Contemporary Aesthetics and the Neglect of Natural Beauty. In B. Williams & A. Montefiore (Eds.), British Analytical Philosophy. Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrfahrdt-Pahle, E. (2014). Applying the Concept of Fit to Water Governance Reforms in South Africa. Ecology and Society, 19(1), 25. https://doi.org/10.5751/ES-05964-190125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, L. (2020). The Menace of Non-being: On Nestle Waters’ Plunder and Jürgen Moltmann’s Sabbath Peace. Journal of Religious Ethics, 48, 201–221. https://doi.org/10.1111/jore.12306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodder, I. (2012). Entangled: An Archaeology of the Relationship Between Humans and Things. Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jennings, W. J. (2016). Binding Landscapes: Secularism, Race, and the Spatial Modern. In J. S. Kahn & V. W. Lloyd (Eds.), Race and Secularism in America (pp. 207–238). Columbia University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kapust, D. (2011). Cicero on Decorum and the Morality of Rhetoric. European Journal of Political Theory, 10(1), 92–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimmerer, R. W. (2002). Weaving Traditional Ecological Knowledge into Biological Education: A Call to Action. Bioscience, 52(5), 432–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaDuke, W. (2005). Recovering the Sacred: The Power of Naming and Claiming. South End Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loftis, R. J. (2003). Three Problems for the Aesthetic Foundations of Environmental Ethics. Philosophy in the Contemporary World, 10(2), 41–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marotto, M., Roos, J., & Victor, B. (2007). Collective Virtuosity in Organizations: A Study of Peak Performance in an Orchestra. Journal of Management Studies, 44, 388–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Remer, G. A. (2017). Ethics and the Orator: The Ciceronian Tradition of Political Morality. University of Chicago Press. Kindle.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, M. (2016). Grace and Beauty. In What Are We Doing Here?: Essays. Farrar, Strauss and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saito, Y. (2007). Everyday Aesthetics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saito, Y. (2017). The Ethical Dimensions of Aesthetic Engagement. Espes, 6(2), 19–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scruton, R. (2013). Green Philosophy: How to Think Seriously About the Planet. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiva, V. (2005). Earth Democracy: Justice, Sustainability, and Peace. South End Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shrivastava, P., & Kennelly, J. J. (2013). Sustainability and Place-Based Enterprise. Organization and Environment, 26(1), 83–101. https://doi.org/10.1177/1086026612475068

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J., & Bailey, D. (2021). ‘Ecobordering’: Casting Immigration Control as Environmental Protection. Environmental Politics. https://doi.org/10.1080/09644016.2021.1916197

  • Waistell, J. (2016). Can Environmental Aesthetics Promote Corporate Sustainability? Organization and Environment, 29(2), 175–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • WCED (World Commission for Economic Development). (1987). Our Common Future. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whyte, K. P. (2013). On the Role of Traditional Ecological Knowledge as a Collaborative Concept: A Philosophical Study. Ecological Processes, 2(7) http://www.ecologicalprocesses.com/content/2/1/7

  • Zaibert, L. (2006). The Fitting, the Deserving and the Beautiful. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 3(3), 331–350. https://doi.org/10.1177/1740468106071229

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

My gratitude to the Issachar Fund for their funding of a fellowship at Evangelische Theologische Faculteit in Leuven, Belgium as part of my larger research project on fittingness undertaken in 2018. Also, to the Collegeville Institute at St. John’s University in Collegeville, Minnesota for their generous provision of extended stays as a Scholar in Residence during the 2022–2023 year, as well as to the Graduate Theological Union in Berkeley, California for access to library resources as a visiting scholar during the 2021–2022 academic year. Finally, to Portia Hopkins for helpful comments on an earlier draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Herrmann, L. (2024). That Which Guilds the Lily: Moving from Aesthetic Value to an Ethical Aesthetic. In: Del Baldo, M., Baldarelli, MG., Righini, E. (eds) Place Based Approaches to Sustainability Volume I. Palgrave Studies in Sustainable Business In Association with Future Earth. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-41606-4_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics