Skip to main content

How Useful Is the Term ‘Modernism’ for Understanding the History of Early Twentieth-Century Mathematics?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Richness of the History of Mathematics

Part of the book series: Archimedes ((ARIM,volume 66))

  • 486 Accesses

Abstract

The present article is intended as a critical assessment of some basic assumptions underlying the analysis of modernism in mathematics in its relationship with the broader aspects of cultural modernism, especially in the period 1890–1930. It discusses the potential historiographical gains of approaching the history of mathematics in the periods under such a perspective and suggests that a fruitful analysis of the phenomenon of modernism in mathematics must focus not on the common features of mathematics and other contemporary cultural trends, but rather on the common historical processes that led to the dominant approaches in all fields.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Some of the main ideas were sketched earlier in (Gray 2004, 2006).

  2. 2.

    See, e.g., (Calinescu 1987; Childs 2000; Eysteinsson 1990, 2021; Gay 2007).

  3. 3.

    Although more naturally seen as dealing with the history of physics, Galison’s book devotes considerable attention to Poincaré’s mathematics as well.

  4. 4.

    The most prominent example that would come to mind is that of Luitzen J.E. Brouwer, whose doctoral advisor urged him to delete the more philosophical and controversial parts of the dissertation and to focus on the more mainstream aspects of mathematics that it contained. It was only somewhat later, as he became a respected practitioner of a mainstream mathematical domain, that he started publishing and promoting his philosophical ideas, and to devote his time and energies to developing new kinds of radical, intuitionistic mathematics. Brouwer promoted a kind of logic, later called “intuitionistic logic”, deviating from the mainstream but not implying a call to abandon classical logic, but rather to revert logic to a previous stage in its evolution, where no considerations of the actual infinite had (wrongfully and dangerously, from his perspective) made deep headway into mainstream mathematics. See (van Dalen 1999, 89–99). Another interesting case is that of Doron Zeilberger’s call, after a distinguished carrer in classical disciplines, for an abandonment of “Human-Supremacist”, “human-generated, and human-centrist ‘conceptual’ pure math mathematics” in favor of computer-generated, “experimental mathematics”.

  5. 5.

    In an illuminating article about the use of the terms “classical” and “modern” by physicists in the early twentieth century, Staley (2005) addresses this difference from an interesting perspective. In his opinion, whereas in physics discussions about “classical” theories and their status were more significant for the consolidation and propagation of new theories and approaches than any invocation of “modernity”, in mathematics, different views about “modernity” were central to many debates within the mathematical community.

  6. 6.

    An even broader and more comprehensive such analysis should also pay attention to philosophy and the social sciences with their own specificities, but for reasons of space I will leave them outside the scope of the present discussion. See, e.g., (Ross 1994; Vrahimis 2012).

  7. 7.

    A typical version of which appears in (Miller 2002).

  8. 8.

    Similar in this respect, with an emphasis on mathematics, are the account presented in (Gamwell 2015).

  9. 9.

    See also (Epple 1996).

  10. 10.

    For additional discussions on Gray’s book, see (Feferman 2009; Rowe 2013; Schappacher 2012; Scholz 2010).

  11. 11.

    An alternative, but not very convincing, way to connect mathematics with the general phenomenon of modernism appears in (Everdell 1997), where Cantor and Dedekind are presented as the true (unaware) initiators of modernism because the way in which they treated the continuum in their mathematical work. See also (Pollack-Milgate 2021).

  12. 12.

    One can find in Greenberg’s own texts support for such a view, but in other places he emphatically denied that his analysis was ever intended as anything beyond pure description. See, e.g., (Greenberg 1983): “I wrote a piece called ‘Modernist Painting’ that got taken as a program when it was only a description.”

  13. 13.

    It is worth stressing, however, that the issue of self-criticism and the ability of an individual (or a collective for that matter) to effectively distance himself from the normative framework in which he functions in order to be self-critical and innovative is a truly complex one, when considered from a broader philosophical point of view. For a through discussion that examines the views of philosophers like Brandom, Friedman, Davidson, Habermas, Rorty, and others, see (Fisch and Benbaji 2011).

  14. 14.

    A discussion of “purity” and its centrality in modernism, from a different perspective appears in (Cheetham 1991).

  15. 15.

    Greenberg, of course, is not the only one to discuss modernism in terms of the processes that led to its rise, rather than by just providing a checklist of characteristic features. Also worthy of mention here is the work of Dan Albright (Albright 1997, 2000), who stresses the crisis of values in art that led to modernism. In his view, if in previous centuries, artists, writers, and musicians could be inherently confident about the validity of the delight and edification they provided to their audiences, during the twentieth century art found itself in a new and odd situation, plagued with insecurity. Faced with the crisis, radical claims about the locus of value in art were advanced in various realms at nearly the same time. The various radical modernist manifestoes thus produced reflect the need of the artist not only to create, as was always the case in the past, but also to promote new standards of value and to provide some new kind of justification to the very existence of art.

  16. 16.

    (Galison 1990) presents an analysis that complements this view and locates the Bauhaus movement in relation with logical positivism, as part of Viennese modernism.

  17. 17.

    (Janik 2001, 147–69) discusses the somewhat different relation between Hertz’s famous Introduction and the late Wittgenstein.

  18. 18.

    Epple’s description of the intellectual background to fin-de-siècle Vienna also strongly relies on the classical study (Schorske 1980).

  19. 19.

    In this context it is natural to stress that also Wittgenstein was born to a privileged and immensely wealthy Viennese family, who generously supported the likes of Gustav Klimt and Alfred Loos as well as the poets Georg Trakl and Rainer Maria Rilke. The circle of friends of the Wittgenstein family included many distinguished figures of the Viennese musical milieu, such as Johannes Brahms (Monk 1991).

References

  • Albright, Daniel. 1997. Quantum Poetics: Yeats, Pound, Eliot, and the Science of Modernism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Untwisting the Serpent: Modernism in Music, Literature, and Other Arts. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ash, Mitchell G. 2018. Multiple Modernisms in Concert: The Sciences, Technology and Culture in Vienna around 1900. In Being Modern: The Cultural Impact of Science in the Early Twentieth Century, ed. Robert Bud, Paul Greenhalgh, Frank James, and Morag Shiach, 23–39. London: University College London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barany, Michael J. 2020. Histories of Mathematical Practice: Reconstruction, Genealogy, and the Unruly Pasts of Ruly Knowledge. ZDM Mathematics Education 52 (6): 1075–1086. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11858-020-01175-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David. 1991. Knowledge and Social Imagery. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottazzini, U., and Amy Dahan-Dalmédico, eds. 2001. Changing Images in Mathematics: From the French Revolution to the New Millennium, Studies in the History of Science, Technology, and Medicine. Vol. 13. London: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradbury, Malcolm, and James Walter McFarlane. 1976. Modernism: A Guide to European Literature, 1890–1930. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calinescu, Matei. 1987. Five Faces of Modernity: Modernism, Avant-Garde, Decadence, Kitsch, Postmodernism. 2nd ed. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carson, Cathryn, Alexei Kojevnikov, and Helmuth Trischler, eds. 2011. Weimar Culture and Quantum Mechanics: Selected papers by Paul Forman and Contemporary Perspectives on the Forman Thesis. London: Imperial College Press. https://www.twirpx.com/file/3325749/.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheetham, Mark A. 1991. The Rhetoric of Purity: Essentialist Theory and the Advent of Abstract Painting. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Childs, Peter. 2000. Modernism. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corry, Leo. 1989. Linearity and Reflexivity in the Growth of Mathematical Knowledge. Science in Context 3 (02): 409–440. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0269889700000880.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. David Hilbert and the Axiomatization of Physics (1898–1918), Archimedes. Vol. 10. Dordrecht: Springer. http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-1-4020-2778-9.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007a. Calculating the Limits of Poetic License: Fictional Narrative and the History of Mathematics. Configurations 15 (3): 195–226. https://doi.org/10.1353/con.0.0034.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007b. From Algebra (1895) to Moderne Algebra (1930): Changing Conceptions of a Discipline. A Guided Tour Using the Jahrbuch Über Die Fortschritte Der Mathematik. In Episodes in the History of Modern Algebra (1800–1950), ed. Jeremy J. Gray and Karen H. Parshall, 221–244. Providence: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007c. Number Crunching vs. Number Theory: Computers and FLT, from Kummer to SWAC (1850–1960), and Beyond. Archive for History of Exact Sciences 62 (4): 393–455. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00407-007-0018-2.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Steht Es Alles Wirklich Schon Bei Dedekind? Ideals and Factorization between Dedekind and Noether. In In Memoriam Richard Dedekind (1831–1916), ed. Katrin Scheel, Thomas Sonar, and Peter Ullrich, 134–159. Münster: Verlag für wissenschaftliche Texte und Medien.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, Nina. 2018. Modernism, Fiction and Mathematics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021. Mathematics and Modernism. In The Palgrave Handbook of Literature and Mathematics, ed. Robert Tubbs, Alice Jenkins, and Nina Engelhardt, 281–298. Cham: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55478-1_16.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, Nina, and Robert Tubbs. 2021. Introduction: Relationships and Connections Between Literature and Mathematics. In The Palgrave Handbook of Literature and Mathematics, ed. Robert Tubbs, Alice Jenkins, and Nina Engelhardt, 1–20. Cham: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55478-1_1.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Epple, Moritz. 1996. Die Mathematische Moderne Und Die Herrschaft Der Zeichen: Über Herbert Mehrtens, Moderne –Sprache – Mathematik. NTM Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 4: 173–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Styles of Argumentation in Late 19th-Century Geometry and the Structure of Mathematical Modernity. In Analysis and Synthesis in Mathematics: History and Philosophy, ed. Marco Panza and Michael Otte, 177–198. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Die Entstehung Der Knotentheorie: Kontexte Und Konstruktionen Einer Modernen Mathematischen Theorie. Wiesbaden: Vieweg +Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Knot Invariants in Vienna and Princeton During the 1920s: Epistemic Configurations of Mathematical Research. Science in Context 17 (1–2): 131–164. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0269889704000079.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Everdell, William R. 1997. The First Moderns: Profiles in the Origins of Twentieth-Century Thought. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eysteinsson, Astradur. 1990. The Concept of Modernism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021. Modernism—Borders and Crises. Humanities 10 (2): 76. https://doi.org/10.3390/h10020076.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eysteinsson, Astradur, and Vivian Liska, eds. 2007. Modernism. Chlel.Xxi. 2 vols. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. https://benjamins.com/catalog/chlel.xxi.

  • Feferman, Solomon. 2009. Modernism in Mathematics, Review of Plato’s Ghost by Jeremy Gray. American Scientist 97 (5): 417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisch, Menachem, and Yitzhak Benbaji. 2011. The View from Within: Normativity and the Limits of Self-Criticism. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. https://muse.jhu.edu/book/13384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forman, Paul. 1971. Weimar Culture, Causality, and Quantum Theory, 1918–1927: Adaptation by German Physicists and Mathematicians to a Hostile Intellectual Environment. Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 3 (January): 1–115. https://doi.org/10.2307/27757315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. The Primacy of Science in Modernity, of Technology in Postmodernity, and of Ideology in the History of Technology. History and Technology 23 (1–2): 1–152. https://doi.org/10.1080/07341510601092191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, E. 1982. In Memoriam Oskar Perron. Journal of Number Theory 14: 281–291.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Galison, Peter. 1990. Aufbau/Bauhaus: Logical Positivism and Architectural Modernism. Critical Inquiry 16 (4): 709–752.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Einstein’s Clocks, Poincaré’s Maps: Empires of Time. 1st ed. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gamwell, Lynn. 2015. Mathematics and Art: A Cultural History. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gay, Peter. 2007. Modernism: The Lure of Heresy. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giedion, Sigfried. 1941. Space, Time and Architecture. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, Donald, ed. 1992. Revolutions in Mathematics, Oxford Science Publications. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, Catherine. 1999. Sur La Question Des Méthodes Quantitatives En Histoire Des Mathématiques: Le Cas de La Théorie Des Nombres En France (1870–1914). Acta Historiae Rerum Naturalium Nec Non Technicarum, New Series, 3 (28): 187–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, Jeremy J. 2004. Anxiety and Abstraction in Nineteenth-Century Mathematics. Science in Context 17 (1–2): 23–47. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0269889704000043.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Modern Mathematics as a Cultural Phenomenon. In The Architecture of Modern Mathematics, ed. Jeremy J. Gray and José Ferreirós, 371–396. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Plato’s Ghost: The Modernist Transformation of Mathematics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, Clement. 1971. Necessity of ‘Formalism’. New Literary History 3 (1): 171–175. https://doi.org/10.2307/468386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1980. Modern and Postmodern. Art 54 (6) http://www.sharecom.ca/greenberg/postmodernism.html.

  • ———. 1983. Taste. January 18. http://www.sharecom.ca/greenberg/taste.html.

  • ———. 1995. Modernist Painting. In The Collected Essays and Criticism, Volume 4: Modernism with a Vengeance, 1957–1969 (The Collected Essays and Criticism, Vol 4), ed. John O’Brien, 85–93. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallett, M. 1979a. Towards a Theory of Mathematical Research Programmes (i). The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (1): 1–25.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1979b. Towards a Theory of Mathematical Research Programmes (II). The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (2): 135–159.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, Linda Dalrymple. 1983. The Fourth Dimension and Non-Euclidean Geometry in Modern Art. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Editor’s Introduction: I. Writing Modern Art and Science– An Overview; II. Cubism, Futurism, and Ether Physics in the Early Twentieth Century. Science in Context 17 (4): 423–466.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Duchamp in Context: Science and Technology in the “Large Glass” and Related Works. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Modernism and Science. In Modernism, ed. Vivian Liska and Astradur Eysteinsson, 383–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janik, Allan. 2001. Wittgenstein’s Vienna Revisited. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janik, Allan, and Stephen Edelston Toulmin. 1973. Wittgenstein’s Vienna. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Caroline A. 2000. The Modernist Paradigm: The Artworld and Thomas Kuhn. Critical Inquiry 26 (3): 488–528.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Eyesight Alone: Clement Greenberg’s Modernism and the Bureaucratization of the Senses. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levenson, Thomas. 2003. Einstein in Berlin. New York: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie, Donald. 1993. Negotiating Arithmetic, Constructing Proof: The Sociology of Mathematics and Information Technology. Social Studies of Science 23 (1): 37–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehrtens, Herbert. 1990. Moderne Sprache, Mathematik: Eine Geschichte Des Streits Um Die Grundlagen Der Disziplin Und Des Subjekts Formaler Systeme, 1. Aufl. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Modernism vs. Counter-Modernism, Nationalism vs. Internationalism: Style and Politics in Mathematics 1900–1950. In L’Europe Mathématique/Mathematical Europe. Histoires, Mythes, Identités/History, Myth, Identity, ed. Catherine Goldstein, Jim Ritter, and Jeremy J. Gray, 518–529. Paris: Editions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Arthur I. 2000. Insights of Genius: Imagery and Creativity in Science and Art. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Einstein, Picasso: Space, Time and The Beauty That Causes Havoc. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monk, Ray. 1991. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. Later Printing. edition. London: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parshall, Karen Hunger. 2004. Defining a Mathematical Research School: The Case of Algebra at the University of Chicago, 1892–1945. Historia Mathematica 31 (3): 263–278. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0315-0860(03)00048-X.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Perron, Oskar. 1911. Über Wahrheit und Irrtum in der Mathematik. Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung 20: 196–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1952. Alfred Pringsheim. Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung 56 (1): 1–6.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Pollack-Milgate, Howard. 2021. Mathematics in German Literature: Paradoxes of infinity. In The Palgrave Handbook of Literature and Mathematics, ed. Robert Tubbs, Alice Jenkins, and Nina Engelhardt, 299–318. Cham: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55478-1_17.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pringsheim, Alfred. 1904. Über Wert und angeblichen Unwert der Mathematik. Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung 13: 357–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Remmert, Volker R., Martina R. Schneider, and Henrik Kragh Sørensen, eds. 2016. Historiography of Mathematics in the 19th and 20th Centuries. New York: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg. 1997. Toward a History of Epistemic Things: Synthesizing Proteins in the Test Tube. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, Dorothy, ed. 1994. Modernist Impulses in the Human Sciences, 1870–1930. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, David E. 2004. Making Mathematics in an Oral Culture: Göttingen in the Era of Klein and Hilbert. Science in Context 17: 85–129. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0269889704000067.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Review of Jeremy Gray’s Plato’s Ghost: The Modernist Transformation of Mathematics (2008). Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 50 (3): 513–521.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schappacher, Norbert. 2012. Panorama Eines Umbruchs. NTM Zeitschrift Für Geschichte Der Wissenschaften, Technik Und Medizin 20 (September). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00048-012-0072-y

  • Scholz, Erhard. 2010. The Tale of Modernist Mathematics. Metascience 19: 213–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schorske, Carl E. 1980. Fin-De-Siecle Vienna: Politics and Culture. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sigmund, Karl. 1999. Musil, Perutz, Broch – Mathematik Und Die Wiener Literaten. Mitteilungen DMV, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staley, R. 2005. On the Co-Creation of Classical and Modern Physics. Isis 96 (4): 530–558.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Stichweh, Rudolf. 1984. Zur Entstehung Des Modernen Systems Wissenschaftlicher Disziplinen: Physik in Deutschland, 1740–1890. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dalen, Dirk. 1999. Mystic, Geometer, and Intuitionist: The Life of L. E. J. Brouwer Volume 1: The Dawning Revolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargish, Thomas, and Delo E. Mook. 1999. Inside Modernism: Relativity Theory, Cubism, Narrative. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, Richard. 1922. Über Die Gegenwärtige Krise Der Mechanik. Die Naturwissenschaften 10: 25–29. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01590406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vrahimis, Andreas. 2012. Modernism and the Vienna Circle’s critique of Heidegger. Critical Quarterly 54 (3): 61–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner-Döbler, Roland, and Jan Berg. 1993. Mathematische Logik von 1847 Bis Zur Gegenwart: Eine Bibliometrische Untersuchung. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisstein, Ulrich. 1995. How Useful Is the Term ‘Modernism’ for the Interdisciplinary Study of Twentieth Century Art? In The Turn of the Century. Modernism and Modernity in Literature and the Arts, ed. Christian Berg, Frank Durieux, and Geert Lernout, 409–441. Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yourgrau, Palle. 2005. A World Without Time: The Forgotten Legacy of Godel and Einstein. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

An earlier version of this paper was written about ten years ago and remained unpublished. Nevertheless, it was posted on my website, and it was read in its preliminary format and even cited in several places. I am glad and proud to be able to publish a fully revised and updated version in this volume dedicated to Jeremy Gray. I thank Jeremy for our interesting conversations on the topic of modernism and beyond, and, above all, for his decisive and lasting contribution to our discipline.

For enlightening discussions and comments on the topic of the present text, I would also like to thank Moritz Epple, Gal Hertz and Menachem Fisch. For important editorial comments that led to an improved final version of this text, I am thankful to Karine Chemla, Hongxing Zhang, and two anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Corry, L. (2023). How Useful Is the Term ‘Modernism’ for Understanding the History of Early Twentieth-Century Mathematics?. In: Chemla, K., Ferreirós, J., Ji, L., Scholz, E., Wang, C. (eds) The Richness of the History of Mathematics. Archimedes, vol 66. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-40855-7_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics