Skip to main content

Conceptions of Human Dignity in African and European Legal Systems: Consonance or Dissonance?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Human Dignity in an African Context
  • 44 Accesses

Abstract

Inherent and universal human dignity was an entirely novel legal concept when it was promulgated by the Universal Declaration of Rights in 1948. Prior to its judicialisation, human dignity had a twofold connotation in anthropology, religion and philosophy, denoting a relationship of contingent status in human relations and relying heavily on duties, rather than rights, as a requirement to achieve dignity. In contrast, the post-WWII paradigm dictates that dignity is equal, universal and unacquired, premised on a right to have one’s inherent dignity respected and protected. The Afrocentric idea of human dignity is also contingent since dignity must be achieved through good deeds towards one’s community, meaning that an individual’s dignity is subordinate to the dignity of one’s community. It has been argued that inherent and universal human dignity is a Western concept, considering that it is rooted in individual rights rather than duties, and therefore takes an approach to human relations that is antithetical to Africa’s communitarian worldview based on duties. Therefore, this chapter explores whether inherent dignity is universal to such an extent that it can accommodate African communitarianism and whether judicialised dignity in all instances should trump the competing rights of a community over individual liberalism and autonomy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The phrase European constitutionalism will be applied in this chapter, in contrast to the usual term “Western civilisation”, which references mostly the American idea. In European constitutionalism individual rights and autonomy can be curtailed in favour of a community, and legal personhood is constituted by a vision of man as an extension of his community, which differs substantially from the American situation where preference is given to individual rights over community rights.

  2. 2.

    See Hannah Arendt (1973, ix): “… human dignity needs a new guarantee which can be found in a new law on earth, whose political validity this time must comprehend the whole of humanity …”.

  3. 3.

    For example, the second paragraphs of the preambles of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (adopted 16 December 1966), the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (adopted 16 December 1966) and Principle VII par 2 of the Helsinki Final Act (adopted 1 August 1975).

  4. 4.

    All moral judgments, including rights-claims, consist directly or indirectly of precepts rooted in the philosophical principle regarding how persons ought to act toward one another. See Alan Gewirth (1979, 1143, 1148).

  5. 5.

    Gerald Neuman (2000, 250) states that dignity, thus defined, may be contrasted with “organic theories of nationalism that submerge the individual, with authoritarian political doctrines that condemn human nature as degraded by sin, with racist doctrines of biological inferiority and with aristocratic doctrines of national hierarchy”.

  6. 6.

    As the South African Constitutional Court held in S v Lawrence 1997 (4) SA 1176, para 168: “Indeed, there is a core to the individual conscience so intrinsic to the dignity of the human personality that it is difficult to imagine any factors whatsoever that could justify it being penetrated by the state”.

  7. 7.

    Immanuel Kant, quoted by Jack Donnelly, 2009, “Human dignity and human rights,” www.udhr60.ch/report/donnelly-Human dignity, stating: “Every man has a legitimate claim to respect from his fellow men and is in turn bound to respect every other”.

  8. 8.

    Ibid.

  9. 9.

    Ubuntu is synonymous with African humanness and the idea that the essence of being human is to develop one’s personhood through one’s communitarian relationships. Human dignity, however, is not to be equated with ubuntu—see Yvonne Mokhoro and Stu Woolman (2010, 407).

  10. 10.

    See Dikolo v Mokhatla 2006 (6) SA 235 (CC): “In our constitutional democracy the basic institutional value of human dignity relates closely to ubuntu or botho, an idea based on deep respect for the humanity of another”. Additionally, see the explanation of Justice Langa in S v Makwanyane 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) para 308: “Ubuntu captures, conceptually, a culture which places some emphasis on communality and on the interdependence of the members of a community. It recognises a person’s status as a human being, entitled to unconditional respect, dignity, value and acceptance from the members of the community such a person happens to be part of”. In the Ugandan case of Salvatori Abuki and Richard Abuga v Attorney General [1997] UGCC 10, page 9, the judge referred to S v Makwanyane: “I would gladly associate myself with the view expressed by MADALA J. in the same case (of Makwanyane (ibid) that the African concept [of ubuntu] embodies within itself humaneness, social justice and fairness, and permeates fundamental human rights. LANGA J. in the same case expressed the same ideas when he concluded that the concept carries with it the idea of human dignity and true humanity”.

  11. 11.

    Online Translator and Dictionary, s.v. “Isithunzi”.

  12. 12.

    Contrary to the prescript of the first element of generic dignity, the South African Constitutional Court found in S v Jordan 2002 6 SA 642 (CC) para 74 that prostitution diminishes human dignity. This view personifies human dignity in the prewar paradigm.

  13. 13.

    S v Makwanyane 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC), para 262; Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC), para 10.

  14. 14.

    The Citizen 1978 (Pty) Ltd. v McBride 2011 (4) SA 191 (CC), para 145.

  15. 15.

    Albert Luthuli referred to this struggle in his Nobel lecture Africa and Freedom on 11 December 1961 after he was awarded the Nobel Prize for Peace in 1960, stating that Africans’ “strivings for nationhood and national dignity have been beaten down by force”.

  16. 16.

    Apartheid itself, rooted in the ontological primacy of race, was a purported collective right.

  17. 17.

    The preamble of the Constitutive Act of the African Union (adopted 11 July 2000) also refers to the “heroic” fight of the African people for their dignity and independence.

  18. 18.

    1934 AD 167.

  19. 19.

    Ibid, 190.

  20. 20.

    (TPD) (unreported) case number CC254/75 of 15 December 1976.

  21. 21.

    Ibid, 21. This phrase originated from a speech presented by Steve Biko in Cape Town in 1971. See “South African History Online.//www.sahistory.org.za/archive/quotes-steve-biko (accessed November 1, 2022)”.

  22. 22.

    In the African context, Asmaron Legesse (1980, 129) argues that “if Africans were the sole authors of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, they might have ranked the rights of communities above those of individuals, and they might have used a cultural idiom fundamentally different from the language in which the ideas are now formulated”.

  23. 23.

    Additionally, see Legesse (1980, 124): “The critical difference between African and Western traditions concerns the importance of the human individual. In the liberal democracies of the Western world the ultimate repository of rights is the human person. The individual is held in a virtually sacralised position. There is a perpetual, and in our view obsessive, concern with the dignity of the individual, his worth, personal autonomy and property”.

  24. 24.

    The African Charter has given effect to the wider principle of duties consistent with the African historical tradition and values by incorporating the instruction in para 6 of the Preamble that “the enjoyment of rights and freedoms also implies the performance of duties on the part of everyone”.

  25. 25.

    Additionally, compare Judge Otas’s dictum in African Echo (Pty) Ltd. t/a Times of Swaziland vs Inkhosatana Gelane Simelane (77/2013) SZSC 83 (3 December 2014) at para 34: “It needs also be emphasised that the Bogoshi decision was based on the uniquely liberal Constitution of South Africa, which exhibits some marked difference with our Constitution and should be approached with trepidation”.

  26. 26.

    Donald Kommers (2002, 64) shares the same view: “The notion of dignity inherent in the new constitutionalism of the postwar era has a core meaning that seems to differ from the core meaning of what we Americans understand by liberty, and these meanings are often found in the different images of society and personhood that they project”.

  27. 27.

    Eckart Klein, quoting from BVerfGE 27, 344, 351 (1970) and Donald P Kommers and Russel A Miller (2012, 362).

  28. 28.

    30 BVerfGE 173, 193 (1971). In this judgment the Court included in its vision of the community not only the living but also the dead, by finding that the human dignity of the deceased writer Klaus Mann trumped the right to freedom of art and science, as the posthumous publishing of his novel Mephisto impinged on his human dignity. See Donald P Kommers and Russel A Miller (2012, 358, 362).

  29. 29.

    4 BVerfGE 7 (1954).

  30. 30.

    1998 (12) SA 1517 (CC), para 117.

  31. 31.

    South African Police Service v Solidarity obo Barnard 2014 (6) SA 123 (CC).

  32. 32.

    As Donald Kommers (2002, 66) argues: “The other approach—dominant in Europe, Canada, and South Africa—emphasises balance and equilibrium in constitutional interpretation, the harmonisation of conflicting rights and values, and a perspective that envisions the constitution as a unified structure, requiring a holistic approach to interpretation. These differing methodologies are important because they project alternative visions of the human person, society, community, equality, and democracy”.

  33. 33.

    Joseph Raz (1990), as quoted by Neomi Rao (2011b, 223).

  34. 34.

    In the Namibian case of ES v AC 2015 NASC 11, however, the Supreme Court ruled that personal autonomy trumps community interests. In this case, a practising Jehovah’s Witness refused a blood transfusion and opposed her brother’s application to be appointed as her guardian in order to be authorised to request the blood transfusion. Her opposition to the application was dismissed by the High Court but the decision was reversed by the Supreme Court. Judge Shivute held at para 73 that: “moral autonomy is of central importance to the protection of human dignity and liberty in free and open democracies such as ours”.

  35. 35.

    2004 (1) SA 406 (CC).

  36. 36.

    Ibid, para 61.

  37. 37.

    Edward J. Eberle (1997, 974), Donald P Kommers and Russel A Miller (2012, 362), Henk Botha (2009, 187).

  38. 38.

    George P Fletcher (1984, 176).

  39. 39.

    Edward J Eberle (1997, 974), Donald P Kommers and Russel A Miller (2012, 362).

  40. 40.

    D Kommers and Miller (2012), Eberle (1997, 973), George P Fletcher (1984, 179).

  41. 41.

    Additionally, see Lorraine E. Weinrib (2002, 15): “The rights-protecting instruments adopted in the aftermath of the Second World War invite comparative reflection and analysis because they rest on a shared constitutional conception that, by design, transcends the history, cultural heritage, and social mores of any particular nation-state”.

  42. 42.

    This practise is not necessarily legally sound—see: Rinie Steinmann (2016b, 359–360).

  43. 43.

    Oscar Schachter (1983, 849), shared the same view, stating that dignity must rather be left for “intuitive understanding”.

References

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1973. The origins of totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beyleveld, Deryk, and Roger Brownsword. 2001. Human dignity in bioethics and biolaw. Oxford: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botha, Henk. 2009. Human dignity in comparative perspective. Stellenbosch Law Review: 171–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cancik, Hubert. 2002. ‘Dignity of man’ and ‘persona’ in stoic anthropology: Some remarks on Cicero. In The concept of human dignity in human rights discourse, ed. David Klein and Eckhart Kretzmer, 19–39. The Hague: Kluwer Law International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chaskalson, Arthur. 2000. Human dignity as a foundational value of our constitutional order. South African Journal on Human Rights: 193–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Wet, Erica. 1995. Can the social-state principle in Germany guide state action in South Africa in the fields of socio and economic rights? African. Journal of Human Rights: 30–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, Jack. 1985. The Concept of Human Rights London: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Human dignity and human rights. www.udhr60.ch/report/donnelly-HumanDignity. Accessed 12 Nov 2022.

  • Eberle, Edward J. 1997. Human dignity, privacy and personality in German and American law. Utah Law Review: 964–1056.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eberle, Edward J. 2008. The German idea of freedom. Oregon Journal of International Law: 1–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, George. 1984. Human dignity as a constitutional value. University of Western Ontario Law Review: 171–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelaye, Tsega A. 2019. The role and migration of human dignity in African constitutional orders: A comparative study of South Africa, Kenya and Uganda. Budapest: Central European University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth, Alan. 1978–1979. The basis and content of human rights. The German Law Journal: 1143–1170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glendon, Mary Anne. 1999. Knowing the universal declaration of human rights. Notre Dame Law Review: 1153–1190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jurgen. 2010. The concept of human dignity and the realistic utopia of human rights. Metaphilosophy: 464–480.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, Rhoda E. 1995a. Dignity, community and human rights. In Human rights in cross-cultural perspectives: A quest for consensus, ed. Abdullahi A. An-Na’im, 81–102. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995b. Human rights and the search for community. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ikuenobe, Polycarb. 2016. The communal basis for moral dignity: An African perspective. Philosophical Papers: 437–469.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2019. Human rights, personhood, dignity and African communalism. Journal of Human Rights: 589–604.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirste, Stephan. 2013. A legal concept of human dignity as a foundation of law. In Human dignity as a Foundation of law, ed. Winfried Brugger and Stephan Kirste, 63–82. Sinzheim: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kommers, Donald P. 2002. Comparative constitutional law: Its increasing relevance. In Defining the field of comparative constitutional law, ed. Vicky C Jackson and Mark Tushnet, 66–120. Connecticut: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kommers, Donald P., and Russel A. Miller. 2012. The constitutional jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany. London: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Legesse, Asmaron. 1980. Human rights in African political culture. In The moral imperatives for human rights: A world survey, 123–138. Washington, DC: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luthuli, Albert J. 1961. Africa and freedom (Nobel lecture, 11 December 1961). Oslo: University of Oslo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makwinja, Simon. 2019. Human dignity in African communitarianism. Pietermatirzburg: University of KwaZulu-Natal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maritain, Jacques. 1948. Philosophical examinations of human rights. In UNESCO Human rights comments and interpretations, 59–64. Paris: UNESCO.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCrudden, Christopher. 2008. Human dignity and judicial interpretation of human rights. European Journal of International Law: 656–724.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menkiti, Ifeanyi. 1984. Person and community in African traditional thought. In African philosophy: An introduction, ed. Richard Wright, 171–181. New York: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metz, Thaddeus. 2012. African conceptions of human dignity: Vitality and community as the ground of human rights. Human Rights Review 13: 19–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mokhoro, Yvonne, and Woolman, Stu. 2010. Where dignity ends and Ubuntu begins: An amplification of, as well as an identification of a tension in, Drucilla Cornell’s thoughts. SA Public Law 25: 400–407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, Motsamai. 2022. Human dignity in Africa: A very short introduction. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murithi, Tim. 2007. A local response to the global human rights standard: The Ubuntu perspective on human dignity. Globalisation, Societies and Education: 277–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neuhaeuser, Christian. 2011. Humiliation: The collective dimension. In Humiliation, degradation, dehumanisation: Human dignity violated, ed. Paulus Kaufmann, Hannes Kuch, Christian Neuhaeuser and Elaine Webster, 21–36. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neuman, Gerald L. 2000. Human dignity in United States constitutional law. In Zur autonomy des individuums, ed. Dieter Simon and Manfred Weiss, 249–271. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rao, Neomi. 2011a. Three conceptions of human dignity in constitutional law. Notre Dame Law Review: 183–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011b. On the use and abuse of dignity in constitutional law. Columbia Journal of European Law: 201–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schachter, Oscar. 1983. Human dignity as a normative concept. American Journal of International Law: 848–854.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sensen, Oliver. 2011. Human dignity in historical perspective: The contemporary and traditional paradigms. European Journal of Political Theory: 71–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Respect towards elderly demented patients. Diametros a Journal of Philosophy: 109–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinmann, Rinie. 2016a. The core meaning of human dignity. Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal: 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016b. The legal significance of human dignity. Potchefstroom: North-West University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinrib, Lorraine E. 2002. Constitutional conceptions and constitutional comparativism. In Defining the field of comparative constitutional law, ed. Vicky Jackson and Mark Tushnet, 3–34. Connecticut: Westport.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werner, Micha. 2014. Individual and collective dignity. In The Cambridge handbook of human dignity: Interdisciplinary perspectives, ed. Marcus Düwell, Jens Braarvig, Roger Brownsword, and Dietmar Mieth, 443–456. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zongwe, Dunia P., and Tjatjara, Bernhard. 2022. Making dignity supreme: The Namibian supreme court’s dignity jurisprudence since independence. In Namibia’s supreme court at 30 years, ed. Tapiwa Warikandwa and John Baloro, 123–154. Windhoek: Konrad Adenauer Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rinie Steinmann .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Steinmann, R. (2023). Conceptions of Human Dignity in African and European Legal Systems: Consonance or Dissonance?. In: Molefe, M., Allsobrook, C. (eds) Human Dignity in an African Context. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-37341-1_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics