Skip to main content

Of Mice-Rats and Pig-Men: Ethical Issues in the Development of Human/Nonhuman Chimeras

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Bioethical Decisions. Volume I

Part of the book series: Collaborative Bioethics ((CB,volume 2))

  • 557 Accesses

Abstract

The modern biological definition of a chimera is a single organism composed of cells with multiple distinct genotypes. Chimeras combining human and nonhuman cells are invaluable for various kinds of research, providing a platform for the study of human cell development while avoiding the ethical issues involved in conducting this research on human subjects. There is also the possibility that human/nonhuman chimeras could one day be used to produce human organs for transplant. Yet human/nonhuman chimeras raise a number of unique ethical challenges as well. Critics worry that they are ‘unnatural’, or will cause a kind of ‘moral confusion’, or pose a threat to human dignity. There are also concerns about the kinds of treatment we might owe to human/nonhuman chimeras. For example, introducing human pluripotent stem cells into a gorilla blastocyst could result in the animal developing a ‘humanlike’ brain, or developing human behaviours or characteristics. Would we need to treat such a being as we do our fellow humans? This chapter examines various arguments concerning research involving human/nonhuman chimeras, and the implications of these arguments for research policy. I conclude that research involving human/nonhuman chimeras is not intrinsically morally wrong, though it may be morally impermissible in some cases. However, I criticize the standard approach to evaluating the treatment of nonhumans in research, arguing that the moral treatment of nonhuman animals, including human/nonhuman chimeras, depends on contextual factors, rather than their moral status.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Mules, created by breeding a female horse and a male donkey, are ‘hybrids’ rather than chimeras. A hybrid results from inter-species breeding, with each cell containing genetic material from both parent species.

  2. 2.

    This definition also implies that there could be animals that do possess human dignity. Karpowicz and colleagues state “the family of capacities associated with human dignity seem to belong uniquely to human beings.” If we take this to mean that only humans have any of the capacities associated with dignity, this claim is false; many kinds of non-human animals exhibit rationality, emotional complexity, or social relations. Or, if we take it to mean that only humans have a certain kind of combination of these capacities, this claim might be true, but implies that some humans lack dignity. Thus, if capacities determine human dignity, it cannot be the case that all and only human beings have dignity.

  3. 3.

    This is not to say that moral practices must remain unchanging, or cannot be criticized. Without the ability to criticize practice, we risk perpetuating morally illegitimate practices. But appealing to theory or principles is not the only way to criticize practice; most people are able to distinguish certain actions as morally right or wrong without appealing to a moral theory. Various accounts of our pre-theoretical moral practices have been given by Ross (2003), Hare (1981), and Dewey (2008).

References

  • Assisted Human Reproduction Act, S.C. (2004). C.2 Available https://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/eng/acts/a-13.4/

  • Bourret, R., Martinez, E., Vialla, F., Giquel, C., Thonnat-Marin, A., & De Vos, J. (2016). Human-animal chimeras: Ethical issues about farming chimeric animals bearing human organs. Stem Cell Research & Therapy, 7, 87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charland, L. C. (2003). Are there answers? The American Journal of Bioethics, 3(3), W1–W2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, A. T., Voth, V. P., Shen, F. X., & Low, W. C. (2019). Concise review: Human-animal neurological chimeras: Humanized animals or human cells in an animal? Stem Cells, 37(4), 444–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, A. T., Shen, F. X., Brown, J. L., Cormack, W., Ruiz-Estevez, M., Voth, J. P., et al. (2020). The American public is ready to accept human-animal chimera research. Stem Cell Reports, 15, 804–810.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crary, A. (2010). Minding what already matters: A critique of moral individualism. Philosophical Topics, 38(1), 17–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Melo-Martin, I. (2008). Chimeras and human dignity. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 18(4), 331–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2007). Human-animal chimeras: Human dignity, moral status, and species prejudice. Metaphilosophy, 38(2–3), 309–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (2008). The later works of John Dewey, 1925–1953. Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, C. (1978). Eating meat and eating people. Journal of Philosophy, 53, 465–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2003). The moral emotions. In R. Davidson, K. Scherer, & H. Goldsmith (Eds.), Handbook in affective sciences (pp. 852–870). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Han, X., Chen, M., Wang, F., Windrem, M., Wang, S., Shanz, S., et al. (2013). Forebrain engraftment by human glial progenitor cells enhances synaptic plasticity and learning in adult mice. Cell Stem Cell, 12(3), 342–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking: Its levels, method and point. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. T. (1998). Clones, genes, and immortality: Ethics and the genetics revolution. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauskeller, M. (2006). Telos: The revival of an Aristotelian concept in present day ethics. Inquiry, 48(1), 62–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Head, S. J., Celik, A., & Kappetein, A. P. (2017). Mechanical versus prosthetic aortic valve replacement. European Heart Journal, 38(28), 2183–2191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Homer, M. (1987). The Illiad. Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Human Chimera Prohibition. (2005). Act, S.1373, 109th Congress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act. (2008). (c22). Available https://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2008/22/contents

  • Human-Animal Chimera Prohibition. (2016). Act, H.R. 6131, 114th Congress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2006). Applying virtue ethics to our treatment of other animals. In J. Welchman (Ed.), The practice of virtue: Classic and contemporary readings in virtue ethics. Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2011). Virtue ethics and the treatment of animals. In T. L. Beauchamp & R. G. Frey (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of animal ethics (pp. 119–143). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hyun, I., Taylor, P., Testa, G., Dickens, B., Jung, K. W., McNab, A., et al. (2007). Ethical standards for human-to-animal chimera experiments in stem cell research. Cell Stem Cell, 1(2), 159–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • International Society for Stem Cell Research. (2021). ISSCR guidelines for stem cell research and clinical translation. Available https://www.isscr.org/policy/guidelines-for-stem-cell-research-and-clinical-translation/key-topics/chimeras

  • Jaworska, A., & Tannenbaum, J. (2021). The grounds of moral status. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Available https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/grounds-moral-status/#GrouMoraStat

  • Karpowicz, P., Cohen, C. B., & van der Kooy, D. (2004). It is ethical to transplant human stem cells into nonhuman embryos. Nature Medicine, 10, 331–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karpowicz, P., Cohen, C. B., & van der Kooy, D. (2005). Developing human-nonhuman chimeras in human stem cell research: Ethical issues and boundaries. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 15(2), 107–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kass, L. R. (1998). The wisdom of repugnance: Why we should ban the cloning of humans. Valparaiso University Law Review, 32(2), 679–705.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kobayashi, T., Yamaguchi, T., Hamanaka, S., Kato-Itoh, M., Yamazaki, Y., Ibata, M., et al. (2010). Generation of rat pancreas in mouse by interspecific blastocyst injection of pluripotent stem cells. Cell, 142(5), 787–799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koplin, J. J., & Savulescu, J. (2019). Time to re-think the law on part-human chimeras. Journal of Law and the Biosciences, 6(1), 37–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landry, D. W., & Zucker, H. A. (2004). Embryonic death and the creation of human embryonic stem cells. Journal of Clinical Investigation, 114(9), 1184–1186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, S., & Grabel, L. (2017). The contribution of human/non-human animal chimeras to stem cell research. Stem Cell Research, 24, 128–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Madan, K. (2020). Natural human chimeras: A review. European Journal of Medical Genetics, 63(9), 103971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Midgley, M. (1983). Animals and why they matter. University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ministry of Education, Culture, Sports, Science and Technology. (2019). Guidelines for the handling of specified embryos. Ministry of Education Sports, Science and Technology. Available https://www.lifescience.mext.go.jp/files/pdf/n2163_03.pdf

    Google Scholar 

  • Monso, S., & Grimm, H. (2019). An alternative to the orthodoxy in animal ethics? Limits and merits of the Wittgensteinian critique of moral individualism. Animals, 9(12), 1057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palacios-Gonzalez, C. (2015). Human dignity and the creation of human-nonhuman chimeras. Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy, 18(4), 487–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • President’s Commission on Bioethics. (2003). Toward a richer bioethics: chimeras and the boundaries of the human. [Meeting transcript. October 13, 2003] Available https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcbe/transcripts/oct03/session2.html

  • Prinz, J. J. (2006). The emotional basis of moral judgements. Philosophical Explorations, 9, 29–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prohibition of Human Cloning for Reproduction. (2002). Act. No. 144 Available https://www.legislation.gov.au/Details/C2017C00306

  • Regan, T. (1985). The case for animal rights. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert, J. S., & Baylis, F. (2003). Crossing species boundaries. The American Journal of Bioethics, 3(3), 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rollin, B. E. (2003). Ethics and species integrity. The American Journal of Bioethics, 3(3), 15–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (2003). The right and the good. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherringham, T. (2008). Mice, men, and monsters: Opposition to chimera research and the scope of federal regulation. California Law Review, 96(3), 765–800.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, A. W. (2003). The moral insignificance of crossing species boundaries. The American Journal of Bioethics, 3(3), 33–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1990). Animal liberation (Revised edition). Avon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1993). Practical ethics (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streiffer, R. (2003). In defense of the moral relevance of species boundaries. The American Journal of Bioethics, 3(3), 37–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Streiffer, R. (2005). At the edge of humanity: Human stem cells, chimeras, and moral status. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 15(4), 347–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tan, T., Wu, J., Si, C., Dai, S., Zhang, Y., Sun, N., et al. (2021). Chimeric contribution of human extended pluripotent stem cells to monkey embryos ex vivo. Cell, 184(8), 2020–2032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tri-Council Policy Statement. (2018). Ethical conduct for research involving humans. Canadian Institutes of Health Research, Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council of Canada, Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council. Available https://ethics.gc.ca/eng/documents/tcps2-2018-en-interactive-final.pdf

  • Waltz, E. (2017). When pig organs will fly. Nature Biotechnology, 35, 1133–1138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Windrem, M. S., Schanz, S. J., Morrow, C., Munir, J., Chandler-Militello, D., Wang, S., & Goldman, S. A. (2014). A competitive advantage by neonatally engrafted human glial progenitors yields mice whose brains are chimeric for human glia. Journal of Neuroscience, 34(48), 16153–16161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, J., Platero-Luengo, A., Sakurai, M., Sugawara, A., Gil, M. A., Yamauchi, T., et al. (2017). Interspecies chimerism with mammalian pluripotent stem cells. Cell, 168(3), 473–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mackenzie Graham .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Graham, M. (2023). Of Mice-Rats and Pig-Men: Ethical Issues in the Development of Human/Nonhuman Chimeras. In: Valdés, E., Lecaros, J.A. (eds) Handbook of Bioethical Decisions. Volume I. Collaborative Bioethics, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-29451-8_28

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics