Skip to main content

Phenomenology and the Species Problem: The Need for Dialogue Between Traditions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy, History and Biology: Essays in Honour of Jean Gayon

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 30))

  • 136 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter explores the relevance of insights drawn from the Continental tradition of Phenomenology for the solution of the long-standing “species problem” in the philosophy of biology. Returning to the roots of Continental Phenomenology in the work of Edmund Husserl, rather than to its later developments, the paper situates the discussion of the species concept in relation to the concepts of “intentionality” and the “life-world” as developed by Husserl. Current conflicts surrounding the interpretation of the meaning of “species” in biological discourse are described in terms of two different intentional “thematizings” of the life-world, both of which satisfy theoretical scientific interests. One of these deals with the interest in the synchronic classification of the world. The other concerns the diachronic historical development of life. It is argued that this Phenomenological analysis give a more satisfactory interpretation of the species problem than that which has been generated by conflicts between advocates of “individualist” and “class” conceptions of natural species. The larger goal of this chapter is to highlight the importance of Jean Gayon’s work in developing a dialogue between Continental and Analytic approaches to the philosophy of biology.

Adapted from Sloan (2018).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See the useful collection in Gutting (2005).

  2. 2.

    See Pierre-Olivier Méthot’s valuable analysis of some of these issues in his (2023 in Bianco et al., 2023).

  3. 3.

    On change from the original “semantic” physicalism of Schlick, Neurath, Carnap, Hempel, and the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus, to the ontological reductionism manifest in identity theory and emergentism, see the overview by Ansgar Beckermann (1992).

  4. 4.

    See Méthot, Brenner, and Duchesneau, this volume. To be sure, Biology and Philosophy now deals with an expanded range of issues.

  5. 5.

    For a clear, uncomplicated, and incisive introduction to phenomenology, I recommend Robert Sokolowski’s overview (Sokolowski, 2000).

  6. 6.

    For a current overview of Marjorie Grene’s arguments, I am indebted to Phillip Honenberger (2021, 2023).

  7. 7.

    On the negative reception of Polanyi’s Personal Knowledge by the philosophical community, see Nye (2014), Chap. 8. Marjorie Grene’s philosophical contributions to the philosophy of science, and specifically the philosophy of biology, have been more favorably assessed, but have often generated controversy. See Auxier and Hahn (2002), Part 2; and Gayon and Burian (2007). I have been unable to locate any literature that directly engages the similarities and differences between the discussions within the Phenomenological literature and the arguments of Polanyi and Grene. The extensive effort to develop a more creative interface between phenomenology and life science, edited by Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka (Tymieniecka, 1999), has no index entry to either name. Documented readings by Polanyi of Husserl’s works seem to date only from late in Polanyi’s career although more research is needed. There are two pages of notes on what seems to be Husserl’s “Philosophy as Rigorous Science” dated August 5, 1963 in the Polanyi Archives at the University of Chicago. In these comments he criticizes Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, and Jaspers, for failing to recognize “non-conceptual” knowledge. He also critiques Husserl for his failure to include a concept of “effort or commitment” in his understanding of intentionality (University of Chicago Michael Polanyi archives, Box 23, folders 4, 16, fol. 1, cited with permission of the University of Chicago Library). I thank Professor Mary Jo Nye for this valuable lead (personal communication), and Dr. Xiaoxing Jin for assistance in obtaining this material. In one text composed a year after the date of this document, Polanyi speaks of his concept of “indwelling” as “being-in-the-world,” and that this has been studied by “Existentialism and phenomenology…under other names.” He then comments that “we must re-interpret such observations now in terms of the more concrete structure of tacit knowing” (Polanyi, 1964, “Preface,” p. xi).

  8. 8.

    Searle commented earlier that he simply ignored the rich tradition of prior discussion, “partly out of ignorance of most of the traditional writings on Intentionality...in the relentless pursuit of my own investigations” (Searle, 1983, p. ix). His notion of intentionality, although much richer than that found in Dennett, for example, still does not address the more comprehensive set of issues dealt with by Husserl from the date of the composition of Logical Investigations and beyond. For Husserl, the intentionality assumed by Dennett, and to a large degree by Searle, would only be an intentionality of the “natural attitude,” and does not bear on the primary intentionality of consciousness. On this distinction see Husserl (1970a [1913], II, V: paras. 16–20, pp. 576–86). For remarks on Husserl and Searle, see Smith and McIntyre (1982, p. 225) where it is concluded that there are broad points of agreement. Where I would see a primary difference is in Searle’s assumption of the primacy of scientific materialism. Husserl’s primary analysis of intentionality requires suspending such assumptions in the “bracketing” of the natural attitude.

  9. 9.

    See the collection in Beckermann et al. (1992). It is indicative of the lack of dialogue between traditions that there is no mention of Husserl or Continental discussions in this entire series of essays. More comprehensive is the collection by Salice (2012a). This is framed by Searle’s introductory essay (pp. 9–22), which continues to develop the theme of intentionality in relation to a consensus scientific materialism. But the volume also has the important discussions by Salice (2012b) and Besoli (2012) that develop the phenomenological themes in dialogue with analytic philosophy.

  10. 10.

    As Sokolowski summarizes this point: “What happens in categorial intentions is that the things we perceive become elevated into the space of reasons, the domain of logic, argument, and rational thinking” (2000, p. 94).

  11. 11.

    I am indebted for this clarification to Philippe Huneman. The important discussion of Ideas I, Chap. 9 deals with this distinction.

  12. 12.

    This does not mean that Husserl denies causality, but that empirical causal relations are part of the “bracketing” in the phenomenological reduction. I thank my colleague Karl Ameriks for this clarification.

  13. 13.

    Husserl (1972 [1913], paras. 27–30).

  14. 14.

    It is generally concluded that this development was in response to Heidegger’s discussions set forth in Sein und Zeit of 1927, especially the discussion of Dasein and his concept of Being-in-the-World (Heidegger, 1962 [1927], Pt. I, ii. 78 ff). David Carr (Husserl, 1970b, “Introduction,”) instead puts more emphasis on the importance of Wilhelm Dilthey for generating this new concern. There is no mention of Heidegger in the entire text of the Crisis although there are several to Dilthey. I will not attempt to deal with this issue here. On Husserl and Dilthey, see Tillman (1976).

  15. 15.

    Husserl (1970b; § 9–10), and Kockelmans (1966, pp. 166–167).

  16. 16.

    Although employing different vocabulary, John Searle’s distinction of “Network” from “Background” makes some of these same points (Searle, 2012 in Salice, 2012a, pp. 18–20).

  17. 17.

    As an autobiographical note, I spent several years doing this kind of taxonomic work. I should emphasize that this is an example from vertebrate taxonomy and issues in the classification of many invertebrates, bacteria, viruses and plants raise additional complicating questions that I will not attempt to address in this essay.

  18. 18.

    For an influential statement see Hull (1965). For critical comments on this “essentialism story” see Honenberger (2015a); Winsor (2006).

  19. 19.

    I thank Phillip Honenberger for important comments on this point. Of course, even to do such genetic analyses implies a prior recognition of the forms to be so analyzed.

  20. 20.

    For comments on the needless and related “monist” and “pluralist” dispute see Kitcher (1987).

  21. 21.

    I find Michael Polanyi’s distinction of “focal” and “subsidiary” awareness a useful way to understand these relations between the objects of directed attention and the accepted background assumptions of the life-world in a way that Husserl does not explore (Polanyi, 1964, Chap. 4).

  22. 22.

    For complexities in this see Siewert (2016), Sect. 3.

  23. 23.

    I am developing on this analogy with revisions as employed by Sokolowski (2000, pp. 118–119).

  24. 24.

    I see this to be the point that Michael Polanyi, with an imperfect and often inadequate vocabulary, was trying to articulate with his concept of “personal” knowledge.

  25. 25.

    In drawing together some traditional Aristotelian and Scholastic insights with the project of German philosophical anthropology, I am indebted to the important dissertation of Dylan Belton (2020). I also acknowledge my long-term debt to the many writings of Marjorie Grene (Sloan, 2007).

  26. 26.

    Honenberger (2015a); See also Fischer (2009); Moss (2015 in Honenberger 2015b, 2020), and originally by Grene (1965).

  27. 27.

    See Spiegelberg (1965), I, Chap. 5; (Bernstein, 2019 in Plessner 2019 [1928]; Philipse, 1995 in Smith & Smith 1995).

  28. 28.

    In his June 10, 1931 Berlin lecture, Husserl directly criticized “philosophical anthropology” as “psychologistic,” and specifically identified Wilhelm Dilthey as its main proponent, without mention of Scheler, Plessner and others (Husserl, 1941, trans. McCormick and Elliston, 1981, pp. 315–323). On the Husserl-Dilthey relationship see Tillman (1976).

References

  • Agapow, P. M., Binida-Emonds, O. R., Crandall, K. A., Gittleman, J. L., et al. (2004). The impact of species concepts on biodiversity studies. Quarterly Review of Biology, 79, 161–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. (1977). Husserl’s realism. The Philosophical Review, 86, 498–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Auletta, G., Leclerc, M., & Martinez, R. (Eds.). (2011). Biological evolution: Facts and theories. Gregorian & Biblical Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Auxier, R., & Hahn, L. E. (Eds.). (2002). The philosophy of Marjorie Grene. Open Court Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckermann, A. (1992). Introduction: Reductive and nonreductive physicalism. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr, & J. Kim (Eds.), Emergence or reduction? Essays on the prospects of nonreductive physicalism (pp. 1–22). de Gruyter Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Belton, D. (2020). The sojourning animal: An anthropology of detachment and attunement. Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, Department of Theology, University of Notre Dame.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, J. M. (2019). Introducing Helmuth Plessner’s philosophical anthropology. In H. Plessner (2019 [1928]), Levels of organic life and the human. An introduction to philosophical anthropology (pp. xxxvii–lxv, Trans. M. Hyatt). Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Besoli, S. (2012). The primacy of functioning intentionality in Edmund Husserl. In A. Salice (Ed.), Intentionality: Historical and systematic perspectives (pp. 175–202). Philosophia Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bianco, G., Van de Vijver, G., & Wolfe, C. T. (Eds.). (2023). Canguilhem and continental philosophy of biology. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. Kluwer Academic Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, A., & Gayon, J. (Eds.). (2009). French studies in the philosophy of science: Contemporary research in France. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byers, D. (2002). Intentionality and transcendence: Closure and openness in Husserl’s phenomenology. University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cairns, D., Embree, L., Kersten, F., & Zaner, R. (2001). Husserl’s intentionality. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 32, 116–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Darden, L. (2013). In search of mechanisms: Discoveries across the life sciences. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. (1994). The astonishing hypothesis: The scientific search for the soul. Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1964 [1859]). The origin of species by means of natural selection. Facsimile of 1st ed. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar, R. (2011). How humans came to be so different from monkeys and apes. In G. Auletta, M. Leclerc, & R. Martinez (Eds.), Biological evolution: Facts and theories (pp. 275–289). Gregorian & Biblical Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1999). On the impossibility of a monistic account of species. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: new interdisciplinary essays (pp. 3–22). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddington, A. S. (1929). The nature of the physical world. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (Ed.). (1992). The units of evolution: Essays on the nature of species. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2017). Species. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2017 ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/species/

  • Fischer, J. (2009). Exploring the core identity of philosophical anthropology through the works of Max Scheler, Helmuth Plessner, and Arnold Gehlen. IRIS, 1(1), 153–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2010). Science, history, and transcendental subjectivity in Husserl’s Crisis. In D. Hyder & H.-J. Rheinberger (Eds.), Science and the life-world: Essays on Husserl’s “Crisis of European sciences” (pp. 100–115). Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H. G. (1972). The science of the life world. Analecta Husserliana, 2, 173–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (1992a). L’espèce sans la forme. In J. Gayon & J.-J. Wunenburger (Eds.), Les figures de la forme. Philosophie biologique et théorie esthétique (pp. 49–61). Éditions L’Harmattan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (1992b). L’individualité de l’espèce: une thèse transformiste? In J. Gayon (Ed.), Buffon 1988. Actes du colloque international du bicentenaire de la mort de Buffon, Paris-Montbard-Dijon (pp. 475–489). Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (Ed.). (1992c). Buffon 1988: Actes du colloque international du bicentenaire de la mort de Buffon, Paris-Montbard-Dijon. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (2008). Les espèces et les taxons monophylétiques sont-ils des individus? In P. Ludwig & T. Pradeu (Eds.), L’individu: perspectives contemporaines (pp. 128–150). Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (2009). Philosophy of biology: An historico-critical characterization. In A. Brenner & J. Gayon (Eds.), French studies in philosophy of science. Contemporary perspectives (pp. 201–212). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (2014). Espèce, biologie. In Encyclopaedia universalis, http://www.universalis.fr/encyclopedie/espece-biologie/

  • Gayon, J. & Burian, R. (Eds.). (2007). Conceptions de la science: hier, aujourd’hui, demain: hommage à Marjorie Grene. Ousia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J., & Wunenburger, J.-J. (Eds.). (1992). Les figures de la forme. Philosophie biologique et théorie esthétique. Éditions L’Harmattan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. (1974). A radical solution to the species problem. Systematic Zoology, 23, 536–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. (1997). Metaphysics and the origin of species. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grene, M. (1965). Approaches to a philosophical biology. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grene, M. (1974). The knower and the known. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, G. (Ed.). (2005). Continental philosophy of science. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, L. (2014). Nature’s suit: Husserl’s phenomenological philosophy of the physical sciences. Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (7th ed., J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). SMC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honenberger, P. (2015a). Grene and Hull on types and typological thinking in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 50, 13–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Honenberger, P. (Ed.). (2015b). Naturalism and philosophical anthropology: Between transcendental and empirical perspectives. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honenberger, P. (2021). Natural artificiality, niche construction, and the content-open mediation of human behavior. Biology and Philosophy, 36, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honenberger, P. (2023). All knowing is orientation: Marjorie Grene’s ecological epistemology. In G. Bianco, G. van de Vijver & C. T. Wolfe (Eds.), Canguilhem and continental philosophy of biology (pp. 39–60). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1965). The effect of essentialism on taxonomy: two thousand years of stasis. British journal for the philosophy of science, 15, 314–326, 16, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1999). On the plurality of species: Questioning the party line. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 23–48). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970a [1913]). Logical investigations (2nd ed., J. Findlay, Trans.). Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970b). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology (D. Carr, Trans.). Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1972 [1913]). Ideas: A general introduction to pure phenomenology (W. R. Gibson, Trans.). Collier Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1999 [1931]). Cartesian meditations (D. Cairns, Trans.). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1941). Phänomenologie und Anthropologie. Philosophy and phenomenological research, 2, 1–14. Translated in P. McCormick & F. Elliston (Eds.). (1981). Husserl: shorter works (pp. 315–323). University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyder, D. & Rheinberger, H.-J. (Eds.). (2010). Science and the life-world: Essays on Husserl’s “Crisis of European sciences”. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. (2019), Intentionality. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/intentionality/

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2013, [1777]). Of the different human races. In J. M. Mikkelsen (Ed.), Kant and the concept of race. Late eighteenth-century writings (pp. 55–71). State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). Species. Philosophy of Science, 51, 308–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1987). Ghostly whispers: Mayr, Ghiselin, and the “philosophers” on the ontological status of species. Biology and Philosophy, 2, 184–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Some puzzles about species. In M. Ruse (Ed.), What the philosophy of biology is: Essays dedicated to David Hull (pp. 183–208). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, J. (1966). Phenomenology and physical science. Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krüger, H.-P. (2015). Intentionality and mentality as explanans and explanandum: Michael Tomasello’s research program from the perspective of philosophical anthropology (pp. 183–218). In P. Honenberger (Ed.), Naturalism and philosophical anthropology: Nature, life, and the human between transcendental and empirical perspectives (pp. 183–218). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, P., & Pradeu, T. (Eds.). (2008). L’individu: perspectives contemporaines. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCormick, P., & Elliston, F. (Eds.). (1981). Husserl: Shorter works. University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meincke, A. S., & Dupré, J. (Eds.). (2020). Biological identity: Perspectives from metaphysics and the philosophy of biology. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merlin, F., & Huneman, P. (Eds.). (2018). Philosophie, histoire, biologie: mélanges offerts à Jean Gayon. Éditions Matériologiques.

    Google Scholar 

  • Méthot, P.-O. (2023) Analytic and continental approaches to biology and philosophy: David Hull and Marjorie Grene on ‘What Philosophy of biology is not’. In G. Bianco, G. Van de Vijver, & C. T. Wolfe (Eds.), Canguilhem and Continental philosophy of biology (pp. 13–38). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelsen, J. M. (Ed.). (2013). Kant and the concept of race: Late eighteenth-century writings (J. M. Mikkelsen, Trans.). State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, L. (2015). The hybrid hominin: A renewed point of departure for philosophical anthropology. In P. Honenberger (Ed.), Naturalism and philosophical anthropology (pp. 171–182). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, L. (2020). Normativity, system-integration, natural detachment and the hybrid hominin. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 20, 21–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and cosmos: Why the materialist neo-Darwinian conception of nature is almost certainly false. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Natanson, M. (1969). Philosophy and psychiatry. In E. Straus, M. Natanson, & H. Ely (Eds.), Psychiatry and philosophy (pp. 85–110). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S. (2020). The origins and evolution of animal identity. In A.S. Meincke & J. Dupré (Eds.), Biological identity: perspectives from metaphysics and the philosophy of biology (pp. 128–148). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nye, M.-J. (2014). Michael Polanyi and his generation: Origins of the social construction of science. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. (2007). Real essentialism. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Philipse, H. (1995). Transcendental idealism. In B. Smith & D. W. Smith (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Husserl (pp. 239–322). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliuccci, M. (2003). Species as family resemblance concepts: The (dis)solution to the species problem? BioEssays, 25(6), 596–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plessner, H. (2019 [1928]). Levels of organic life and the human: an introduction to philosophical anthropology (Hyatt, Trans.). Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1964). Personal knowledge: Towards a post-critical philosophy (Rev. ed.). Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reydon, T. A. C. (2005). On the nature of the species problem and the four meanings of ‘species.’ Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 135–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Cytoplasmic Particles in Brussels (Jean Brachet, Hubert Chantrenne, Raymond Jeener) and at Rockefeller (Albert Claude), 1935–1955. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 19(1), 47–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (2010). An epistemology of the concrete: Twentieth-century histories of life. Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. A. (2010). The species problem: A philosophical analysis. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roger, J. & Fischer, J.-L. (Eds.). (1987). Histoire du concept d’espèce dans les sciences de la vie. Fondation Singer-Polignac

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (Ed.). (1989). What the philosophy of biology is: Essays dedicated to David Hull. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M., & Richards, R. J. (Eds.). (2009). The Cambridge companion to the “Origin of species.” Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salice, A. (Ed.). (2012a). Intentionality: Historical and systematic perspectives. Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salice, A. (2012b). Phänomenologische Variationen. Intention and fulfillment in early Phenomenology. In A. Salice (Ed.), Intentionality: Historical and systematic perspectives (pp. 203–242). Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (2012). Foreword. In A. Salice (Ed.), Intentionality: Historical and systematic perspectives (pp. 9–22). Philosophia Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (2016). Consciousness and intentionality. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/consciousness-intentionality.

  • Sloan, P. (1987). From logical universals to historical individuals: Buffon’s conception of biological species In J. Roger & J.-L. Fischer (Eds.), Histoire du concept d’espèce dans les sciences de la vie (pp. 97–136). Fondation Singer-Polignac.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. (2002). Reflections on the species problem: What Marjorie Grene can teach us about a perennial issue. In R. E. Auxier & L. W. Hahn (Eds.), The Philosophy of Marjorie Grene (pp. 225–255). Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. (2007). Télélogie et forme: un réexamen. In J. Gayon & R. Burian (Eds.), Conceptions de la science: hier, aujourd’hui, demain: hommage à Marjorie Grene (pp. 343–67). Ousia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. (2009). Originating species: Darwin on the species problem. In M. Ruse & R. J. Richards (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to the “Origin of species” (pp. 67–86). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. (2013). The species problem and history. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 237–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. (2015). Questioning the zoological gaze. In P. R. Sloan, G. McKenny, & K. Eggleson (Eds.), Darwin in the twenty-first century: Nature, humanity, God (pp. 232–266). University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. (2018). Locating the human in the biological world: A way into the species problem. In F. Merlin & P. Huneman (Eds.), Philosophie, histoire, biologie: mélanges offerts à Jean Gayon (pp. 219–241). Éditions Matériologiques.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. R., McKenny, G., & Eggleson, K. (Eds.). (2015). Darwin in the twenty-first century: Nature, humanity, God. University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. R., & McIntyre, R. (1982). Husserl and intentionality: A study of mind, meaning, and language. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B., & Smith, D. W. (Eds.). (1995). The Cambridge companion to Husserl. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, R. (2000). Introduction to phenomenology. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sparks, J. (2001). Bedotia masoala: A new species of atherinoid rainbowfish (Teleostei: Bedotiiade) from the Masoala peninsula, northeastern Madagascar. Copeia, 2001(2), 482–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1965). The phenomenological movement: a historical introduction (2nd ed., 2 Vols.). The Hague.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamos, D. (2003). The species problem: Biological species, ontology, and the metaphysics of biology. Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Straus, E., Natanson, M., & Ely, H. (Eds.). (1969). Psychiatry and philosophy. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tillman, M. K. (1976). Dilthey and Husserl. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 7, 123–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tymieniecka, A.-T. (Ed.). (1999). Life; Scientific philosophy: phenomenology of life and the sciences of life (2 vols.). Kluwer Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. S. (2009). Species: A history of the idea. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (Ed.). (1999). Species: New interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winsor, M. (2006). The creation of the essentialism story: An exercise in metahistory. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 28, 149–174.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For this revision I am indebted to comments by David Depew, Phillip Honenberger, Vittorio Hösle, Lenny Moss, Dylan Belton, Karl Ameriks, M. Katherine Tillman, and members of the Philosophy of Biology Circle at the University Texas, hosted by Sahotra Sarkar. Responsibility for interpretations is my own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Phillip R. Sloan .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Sloan, P.R. (2023). Phenomenology and the Species Problem: The Need for Dialogue Between Traditions. In: Méthot, PO. (eds) Philosophy, History and Biology: Essays in Honour of Jean Gayon. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 30. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-28157-0_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics