Skip to main content

Statistics in a World Without Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Teaching Biostatistics in Medicine and Allied Health Sciences
  • 437 Accesses

Abstract

There is an accepted framework for producing scientific evidence (the philosophy of science), and another for using random samples from a population to summarize that evidence (statistical inference). Central to the accepted philosophy of science is the idea of falsifiability, which is generally adhered to in randomized controlled trials (RCTs) using the null hypothesis significance testing approach defined by Neyman and Pearson. Beyond the tight control of RCTs, the flexibility of statistical inference means it is relatively easy to overlook falsifiability, thereby undermining the validity of any scientific conclusion. Perhaps the typical example of this is HARKing (hypothesizing after the results are known), where a statistical analysis of sample data reveals a significant effect that has a very convincing explanation only in retrospect and is reported as if hypothesized a priori. Such ‘discoveries’ may well be valid, but the rate at which they might not be is unknown. This is contributing to a crisis of replication in medical research, where results from published studies are often not reproducible.

Science is considered a difficult subject, and it may not be appropriate to teach the philosophy behind it to medical students who have other time commitments, including also the learning of difficult methods of statistics. Under these circumstances, what can be taught to promote the use of statistics within the scientific framework and mitigate the crisis of replication? roposed suggestions range from producing registered study protocols to the abandonment of statistical significance; importantly, both can be implemented without need for expertise in philosophy. Despite this, the replication crisis persists and the implementation of any proposed solution, and perhaps even awareness of them, is the exception. As (if) we move to better scientific practice, it is likely that those who teach statistics will be required to include the suggestions into their courses.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Reproducibility and reliability of biomedical research. The Academy of Medical Sciences [Internet]. [cited 2021 Oct 7]. Available from https://acmedsci.ac.uk/policy/policy-projects/reproducibility-and-reliability-of-biomedical-research.

  2. Stupple A, Singerman D, Celi LA. The reproducibility crisis in the age of digital medicine. NPJ Digit Med. 2019;2(1):1–3.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Baker M. 1,500 scientists lift the lid on reproducibility [Internet]. Nature 2016 [cited 2021 Oct 8]. Available from https://www.nature.com/articles/533452a.

  4. Amrhein V, Korner-Nievergelt F, Roth T. The earth is flat (p > 0.05): significance thresholds and the crisis of unreplicable research. PeerJ. 2017;5:e3544.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  5. Open Science Collaboration. Estimating the reproducibility of psychological science. Science. 2015;349(6251):aac4716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Dixon P, O’reilly T. Scientific versus statistical inference. Can J Exp Psychol. 1999;53(2):133–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Mitra S. An analysis of the falsification criterion of Karl Popper: a critical review. Tattva J Philos. 2020;12(1):1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Simmons JP, Nelson LD, Simonsohn U. False-positive psychology: undisclosed flexibility in data collection and analysis allows presenting anything as significant. Psychol Sci. 2011;22(11):1359–66.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  9. Horton R. Offline: what is medicine’s 5 sigma? Lancet. 2015;385(9976):1380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Kerr NL. HARKing: hypothesizing after the results are known. Personal Soc Psychol Rev. 1998;2(3):196–217.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  11. Dickersin K, Chan S, Chalmersx TC, Sacks HS, Smith H. Publication bias and clinical trials. Control Clin Trials. 1987;8(4):343–53.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Joober R, Schmitz N, Annable L, Boksa P. Publication bias: what are the challenges and can they be overcome? J Psychiatry Neurosci. 2012;37(3):149–52.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  13. Perezgonzalez JD. Fisher, Neyman-Pearson or NHST? A tutorial for teaching data testing. Front Psychol. 2015;6:223.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  14. Cohen J. The earth is round (p < .05). Am Psychol. 1994;49:997–1003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Nosek BA, Ebersole CR, DeHaven AC, Mellor DT. The preregistration revolution. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2018;115(11):2600–6.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  16. Amrhein V, Greenland S, McShane B. Scientists rise up against statistical significance. Nature. 2019;567(7748):305–7.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  17. Wasserstein RL, Schirm AL, Lazar NA. Moving to a World Beyond “ p < 0.05”. Am Stat. 2019;73(sup1):1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Sudlow C, Gallacher J, Allen N, Beral V, Burton P, Danesh J, et al. UK Biobank: an open access resource for identifying the causes of a wide range of complex diseases of middle and old age. PLoS Med. 2015;12(3):e1001779.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  19. Kim J, Bang H. Three common misuses of P values. Dent Hypotheses. 2016;7(3):73–80.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  20. Button KS, Ioannidis JP, Mokrysz C, Nosek BA, Flint J, Robinson ES, et al. Power failure: why small sample size undermines the reliability of neuroscience. Nat Rev Neurosci. 2013;14(5):365–76.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  21. Rencher AC, Pun FC. Inflation of R2 in best subset regression. Technometrics. 1980;22(1):49–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Hawkins DM. The problem of overfitting. J Chem Inf Comput Sci. 2004;44(1):1–12.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  23. Lakens D. The practical alternative to the p value is the correctly used p value. Perspect Psychol Sci J Assoc Psychol Sci. 2021;16(3):639–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Dixon P. The p-value fallacy and how to avoid it. Can J Exp Psychol. 2003;57(3):189–202.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  25. Goodman SN. Toward evidence-based medical statistics. 1: the p value fallacy. Ann Intern Med. 1999;130(12):995–1004.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  26. Koul A, Becchio C, Cavallo A. Cross-validation approaches for replicability in psychology. Front Psychol. 2018;9:1117.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher R. Tench .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Tench, C.R. (2023). Statistics in a World Without Science. In: Farnell, D.J.J., Medeiros Mirra, R. (eds) Teaching Biostatistics in Medicine and Allied Health Sciences. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-26010-0_13

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-26010-0_13

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-26009-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-26010-0

  • eBook Packages: MedicineMedicine (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics