Skip to main content

Patient Autonomy and User Autonomy in the Ecology of Care

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Human-Centered Service Design for Healthcare Transformation
  • 621 Accesses

Abstract

Patient autonomy is the foundational moral principle of healthcare. In this chapter, I review how autonomy has been conceptualized in the medical field and compare that with understandings of autonomy discussed in design. I argue that patient autonomy in healthcare has mainly been understood as negative freedom—independence from the interference of others, especially medical paternalism. Therefore, patient autonomy has been conceptualized as decision-making and has been applied to practice as a procedural means to cure rather than an end in itself. In contrast, user autonomy in design highlights positive freedom—the elevated state of one’s ability to govern one’s own life according to an internal will. Therefore, autonomy in design has been construed more broadly as a concept that encompasses thoughts, decisions, and actions, and has been seen as an end in itself. The collaboration of healthcare professionals and designers allows for productive opportunities to holistically support patients and their caregivers, as this collaboration brings together autonomy as means and autonomy as ends. I conclude the chapter by proposing that the study of autonomy as a guiding principle is essential in expanding healthcare service design to consider diverse agents.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Beauchamp, T. L., & Childress, J. F. (1979). Principles of biomedical ethics. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. (1969). Two concepts of liberty. In I. Berlin (Eds.), Four essays on liberty (pp. 118–172). London, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burkhardt, M. A., & Nathaniel, A. K. (2002). Practice issues related to patient self-determination. In N. Y. Albany (Ed.), Ethics & issues in contemporary nursing (pp. 205–232). Albany, NY: Delmar Thomson Learning Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvo, R. A., Peters, D., Johnson, D. & Rogers, Y. (2014). Autonomy in technology design, In ACM CHI 2014 extended abstracts on human factors in computing systems (pp. 37–40).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davy, L. (2015). Philosophical inclusive design: Intellectual disability and the limits of individual autonomy in moral and political theory. Hypatia, 30(1), 132–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2008). Self-determination theory: A macrotheory of human motivation, development, and health. Canadian Psychology/psychologie Canadienne, 49(3), 182–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Visser, E. J., Pak, R., & Shaw, T. H. (2018). From automation to autonomy: The importance of trust repair in human–machine interaction. Ergonomics, 61(10), 1409–1427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edelstein, L. (1943). The hippocratic oath: Text, translation and interpretation. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Entwistle, V. A., Carter, S. M., Cribb, A., & McCaffery, K. (2010). Supporting patient autonomy: The importance of clinician-patient relationships. Journal of General Internal Medicine, 25(7), 741–745.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishkin, J. S., & Luskin, R. C. (2005). Experimenting with a democratic ideal: Deliberative polling and public opinion. Acta Politica, 40(3), 284–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B. (1996). Value-sensitive design, Interactions3(6), 16–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B. (1998). User autonomy: Who should control what and when? A CHI 96 workshop. ACM SIGCHI Bulletin, 30(1), 26–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. A. (1986). Autonomy and the split-level self. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 24(1), 19–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Güldenpfennig, F., Mayer, P., Panek, P. & Fitzpatrick, G. (2019). An autonomy-perspective on the design of assistive technology experiences of people with multiple sclerosis. In The ACM CHI conference on human factors in computing systems, Glasgow, UK (pp. 1–14), 4–9 May.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jennings, B. (2016). Reconceptualizing autonomy: A relational turn in bioethics. Hastings Center Report, 46(3), 11–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1785/1998). Groundwork for the metaphysics of morals (M. Gregor, Trans.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karpen, I. O., Gemser, G., & Calabretta, G. (2017). A multilevel consideration of service design conditions: Towards a portfolio of organisational capabilities, interactive practices and individual abilities. Journal of Service Theory and Practice, 27(2), 384–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, M. (2021). A study of dignity as a principle of service design. International Journal of Design, 15(3), 87–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, M., Ramdin, V., Pozzar, R., Fombelle, P., Zhou, X., Zhang, Y., & Jiang, M. (2022). Healthy aging adviser: Designing a service to support the life transitions and autonomy of older adults. The Design Journal, 25(2), 143–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Last, J. M. (2007). A dictionary of public health. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1883/2008). Thus spoke Zarathustra: A book for everyone and nobody. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindberg, C., Fagerström, C., Sivberg, B., & Willman, A. (2014). Concept analysis: Patient autonomy in a caring context. Journal of Advanced Nursing, 70(10), 2208–2221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Littlewood, W. (1996). Autonomy: An anatomy and a framework. System, 24(4), 427–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C., & Stoljar, N. (Eds.). (2000). Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency, and the social self. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millar, J. (2015). Technology as moral proxy: Autonomy and paternalism by design. IEEE Technology and Society Magazine, 34(2), 47–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perkins, M. M., Ball, M. M., Whittington, F. J., & Hollingsworth, C. (2012). Relational autonomy in assisted living: A focus on diverse care settings for older adults. Journal of Aging Studies, 26(2), 214–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato, P. (1995). Translated by A. Nehamas and P. Woodruff. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pugh, J. (2020). Autonomy, rationality, and contemporary bioethics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rotter, J. B. (1966). Generalized expectancies for internal versus external control of reinforcement. Psychological Monographs: General and Applied, 80(1), 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J. J. (1762/2018). The social contract and other later political writings. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rozenblit, J. W. (1992). Design for autonomy: An overview, Applied Artificial Intelligence an International Journal. 6(1), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sangiorgi, D. (2011). Transformative services and transformation design. International Journal of Design, 5(2), 29–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schermer, M. (2002). The different faces of autonomy: Patient autonomy in ethical theory and hospital practice (Vol. 13). Berlin, Germany: Springer Science & Business Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherwin, S., & Winsby, M. (2011). A relational perspective on autonomy for older adults residing in nursing homes. Health Expectations, 14(2), 182–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tauber, A. I. (2001). Historical and philosophical reflections on patient autonomy. Health Care Analysis, 9(3), 299–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varelius, J. (2006). The value of autonomy in medical ethics. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 9(3), 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker, M. U. (2000). Getting out of line: Alternatives to life as, Mother time: Women, aging, and ethics (pp. 97–111).

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, L., Zhang, S. & Lu, Z. (2020). Respect for autonomy: Seeking the roles of healthcare design from the principle of biomedical ethics, HERD: Health Environments Research & Design Journal13(3), 230–244.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miso Kim .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kim, M. (2023). Patient Autonomy and User Autonomy in the Ecology of Care. In: Pfannstiel, M.A. (eds) Human-Centered Service Design for Healthcare Transformation. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-20168-4_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics