Skip to main content

Ratio via Machina: Three Standards of Mechanistic Explanation in Sociology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Sociology as a Human Science

Part of the book series: Cultural Sociology ((CULTSOC))

  • 184 Accesses

Abstract

Recently, sociologists have expended much effort in attempts to define social mechanisms. We intervene in these debates by proposing that sociologists in fact have a choice to make between three standards of what constitutes a good mechanistic explanation: substantial, formal, and metaphorical mechanistic explanation. All three standards are active in the field, and we suggest that a more complete theory of mechanistic explanation in sociology must parse these three approaches to draw out the implicit evaluative criteria appropriate to each. Doing so will reveal quite different preferences for explanatory scope and nuance hidden under the ubiquitous term ‘social mechanism.’ Finally, moving beyond extensive debates about realism and anti-realism, we argue prescriptively against ‘mechanistic fundamentalism’ for sociology, and advocate for a more pluralistic understanding of social causality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We use the term “substantial” because this standard includes mechanisms that posit causal capacities inherent to particular substances or entities.

  2. 2.

    We have selected Cartwright’s theory of mechanisms because it is the most comprehensive, synthesizing prominent structuralist, process, and interventionist positions on mechanistic causation, represented separately by philosophers like Bechtel and Richardson (1993), Machamer et al. (2000), and Menzies (2012), into a coherent ontological position with clear epistemological implications for causal explanation.

  3. 3.

    Cartwright herself tests the uncertain construct of social capacities by analyzing economic models, such as game-theoretic simulations. She finds that, to the extent these models meet the substantial standard, they do so by sacrificing external validity (1999: 149). Ultimately, Cartwright finds that social capacities are extremely difficult to pin down, in part because they are constituted and reconstituted by human agents reacting to historical circumstances, individual impulses, and any number of other irregular or impermanent factors (cf. Crespo 2013).

  4. 4.

    While Cartwright by no means dismisses sociologists’ ability to construct causal explanations, she is generically skeptical about social scientists’ ability to convincingly construct mechanisms that reveal real social capacities. This is due in part to a lack of plausible general principles from which social scientists can work to isolate the tendencies of social capacities by eliminating extraneous forces and bracketing structural assumptions built into their models (Cartwright 2009: 50).

  5. 5.

    The philosophical reference point here is C.S. Peirce’s concept of the community of inquiry. For discussions of the concept see Peirce 1992/1877; Talisse 2004; Lichterman and Reed 2015.

  6. 6.

    Though initially a strong proponent of a purely analytical approach to social mechanisms, Hedström’s subsequent research around the desires-beliefs-opportunities (DBO) model can be interpreted as presuming a substantialist basis for the DBOs it postulates. Hedström’s ontological drift highlights how the potential for slippage between substantial and formal approaches bedevils many efforts to define a single standard for mechanistic explanation, a problem that further justifies the need to self-consciously parse the different explanatory standards of each approach.

  7. 7.

    An early forerunner was Stephen Pepper (1961), who considered mechanism to be a prime example of a “root metaphor,” the basic framework that generates comprehensive “world hypotheses”—grand and all-encompassing schemes that guide cognition in science and philosophy. For Pepper, metaphor pre-sorts the kinds of processes that can be imagined as ontological furniture of the world in the first place.

  8. 8.

    This talk was delivered at New York University, December 9, 2013.

  9. 9.

    In the same text wherein she developed her understanding of nomological machines, Cartwright developed her criticism of standard philosophy of science in a new direction. “It is not realism,” she wrote, “but fundamentalism that we need to combat” (Cartwright 1999: 23, emphasis in original). Fundamentalism holds that the things described in laws or models are not only true, but true everywhere. In application, the fundamentalist position posits that every observable instance of any given phenomenon can ultimately be reduced to one of a few basic laws. For Cartwright, the problematic fundamentalism which drives to reduce the world to the laws of physics has as its preferable counterpoint her notion of the “dappled world.” The dappled world is one where those purportedly universal, fundamental laws of physics describe only a limited range of phenomena and only under certain conditions; the rest of the world as we know it is populated by various “natures” which we know to tend toward certain activities but cannot hope to predict in the same way we can those few nomological machines that are described in natural law. Those situations not governed by universal laws can be subsumed under these laws “only by distortion, whereas they can often be described fairly correctly by concepts from more phenomenological laws” (1999: 31). Where natures can be described more accurately in phenomenological terms, they should “be admitted into the body of knowledge on their own merit” (1999: 24). It is important for understanding our argument that Cartwright’s notion of “natures” or “capacities” that make up nomological machines is part of her dappled world hypothesis—in other words, the world of causality has to be understood as dappled because different things in the world have different natures. This is why Cartwright calls her position one of “metaphysical nomological pluralism”—it does not abandon general causes and assumes that our descriptions of causes can get very close to describing the real world. However, it assumes that there are many species of cause, and that the task of the (physical, natural, and social) sciences is to catalog the great variety of causes in ways that help us explain our world.

    Our argument is that a metaphorical understanding of mechanisms aids in doubling down on this “dappled world” hypothesis. In the human sciences, the construal of the world is such that even within the set of causes that concern “sociology,” the world is extraordinarily dappled, because objects, kinds, and processes are formed and then unformed in a world of cultural and historical variation of ontology (see Chap. 3). In this context, there is a parallel to the fundamentalism in the philosophy of science that attempts to reduce all causal natures to the laws of physics.

  10. 10.

    This argument is based on our own affinity for the metaphorical standard. However, a more pluralistic approach to mechanisms is possible for sociologists who are not inclined toward the metaphorical standard and do not wish to extend the group of causal metaphors beyond mechanism. Particularly from within the formal standard, one could posit “sundry mechanisms of different kinds.” We thank anonymous reviewer 1 of the chapter for pointing this out.

References

  • Abbott, Andrew. 2007. Mechanisms and Relations. Sociologica 1 (2): 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, Jeffrey. 1982–1983. Theoretical Logic in Sociology. Vol. 1–4. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, William, and Robert C. Richardson. 1993. Discovering Complexity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biernacki, Richard. 1995. The Fabrication of Labor: Germany and Britain, 1640–1914. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, Nancy. 1999. The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Causation: One Word, Many Things. Philosophy of Science 71 (5): 805–820.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. If No Capacities Then No Credible Worlds. But Can Models Reveal Capacities? Erkenntnis 70 (1): 45–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, James S. 1990. Foundations of Social Theory. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crespo, Ricardo F. 2013. Theoretical and Practical Reason in Economics: Capacities and Capabilities. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gerhart, Mary, and Allan M. Russell. 1984. Metaphoric Process: The Creation of Scientific and Religious Understanding. Fort Worth, TX: TCU Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldthorpe, John H. 2007. On Sociology. 2nd ed. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorski, Philip. 2003. The Disciplinary Revolution: Calvinism and the Rise of the State in Early Modern Europe. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Social ‘Mechanisms’ and Comparative-historical Sociology: A Critical Realist Proposal. In Frontiers of Sociology, ed. P. Hedström and B. Wittrock, 147–194. Leiden: Brill.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, Neil. 2009. A Pragmatist Theory of Social Mechanisms. American Sociological Review 74 (3): 358–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, Peter. 1998. Rational Imitation. In Social Mechanisms: An Analytical Approach to Social Theory, ed. Peter Hedström and Richard Swedberg. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Dissecting the Social: On the Principles of Analytical Sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, Peter, and Richard Swedberg, eds. 1998. Social Mechanisms: An Analytical Approach to Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, Peter, and Petri Ylikoski. 2010. Causal Mechanisms in the Social Sciences. Annual Review of Sociology 36 (1): 49–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman, Daniel, and Isaac Ariail Reed. 2014. Formation Stories and Causality in Sociology. Sociological Theory 32 (4): 259–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lichterman, Paul, and Isaac Ariail Reed. 2015. Theory and Contrastive Explanation in Ethnography. Sociological Methods and Research 44 (4): 585–635.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, Daniel. 2012. Explanatory Autonomy and Coleman’s Boat. Theoria 27 (2): 137–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, Peter, Lindley Darden, and Carl F. Craver. 2000. Thinking About Mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67 (1): 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, John Levi. 2003. What Is Field Theory? American Journal of Sociology 109 (1): 1–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, Peter. 2012. The Causal Structure of Mechanisms. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43 (4): 796–805.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, Stephen L., and Christopher Winship. 2015. Counterfactuals and Causal Inference: Methods and Principles for Social Research. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, Charles S. 1992/1877. The Fixation of Belief. In The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings, Vol. 1, ed. Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel, 109–123. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pepper, Stephen C. 1961. World Hypotheses. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, Isaac Ariail. 2011. Interpretation and Social Knowledge: On the Use of Theory in the Human Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, Paul. 2003/1975. The Rule of Metaphor: The Creation of Meaning in Language. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salzinger, Leslie. 2003. Genders in Production: Making Workers in Mexico’s Global Factories. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seidman, Steven. 1991. The End of Sociological Theory: The Postmodern Hope. Sociological Theory 9 (2): 131–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Christian. 2010. What is a Person? Rethinking Humanity, Social Life, and the Moral Good from the Person Up. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Talisse, Robert. 2004. Towards a Peircean Politics of Inquiry. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society XL (1): 21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaidyanathan, Brandon, Michael Strand, Austin Choi-Fitzpatrick, Thomas Buschman, Meghan Davis, and Amanda Varela. 2015. Causality in Contemporary American Sociology: An Empirical Assessment and Critique. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour. Published Online February 11, 2015. https://doi.org/10.1111/jtsb.12081, 1–24.

  • Wilson, Nicholas Hoover. 2011. From Reflection to Refraction: State Administration in British India, Circa 1770–1855. American Journal of Sociology 116 (5): 1437–1477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Natalie B. Aviles .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Aviles, N.B., Ariail Reed, I. (2023). Ratio via Machina: Three Standards of Mechanistic Explanation in Sociology. In: Sociology as a Human Science . Cultural Sociology. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-18357-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-18357-7_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-18356-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-18357-7

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics