Skip to main content

Democratic Republicanism in the French Revolution

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Republicanism and Democracy

Part of the book series: Contributions to Political Science ((CPS))

  • 277 Accesses

Abstract

Representation belongs to the history of republics, yet is missing in contemporary theories of republicanism. According to the prevailing narrative, representation is not part of the democratic tradition, and its emergence in modern politics coincided with the neutralization of the people in the decision-making process. This story has veiled the existence of a lesser known history, of a democratic republicanism that sought to contain the absolute power of the crowd without resorting to a liberal-elitist form of representative government. This chapter goes back to that history. It analyzes the contributions of Thomas Paine and the Marquis de Condorcet to the merging of democracy and republicanism. They wanted to make representative government democratic by overcoming the polarization between representation and participation, and instead making them related forms of political action along the continuum of decision-making and opinion formation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Pierre Rosanvallon attributes the paternity of the term “representative democracy” to Hamilton, who used it in a 1777 letter to Governor Morris (2000, 11–12). Its implementation as a form of government began at the local level—township government in New England and, after 1789, municipal government in Paris. Since the beginning, it was perceived as peculiarly modern and either prized as an alternative to democracy or criticized as a mockery of government by the people. Although we do not know for sure who first spoke of “representative democracy,” the Marquis d’Argenson, a foreign minister under Louis XV, was among the first who described the characteristics of this form of government and judged them favorably in his Considérations sur le gouvernement ancien et present de la France (1765).

  2. 2.

    Of course, the argument of representation as expediency can and actually did serve the cause of the sovereignty of the parliament because the idea that the people could act for themselves may help “to sustain the authority of the few” since it suggests a resemblance between people directly assembled and people assembled symbolically through their representatives (Morgan, 1988, 209–211).

  3. 3.

    Although the “‘people’ is certainly a much larger entity today than in the eighteenth-century…, there has been no significant change in the institutions regulating the selection of representatives and the influence of the popular will on their decisions once in office” (Manin, 1997, 236).

  4. 4.

    The conceptual distinction between “will” and “judgment”—attributed to the legislative power and the government (executive and judging functions), respectively—has proceeded along with distinction of state functions. Historians of political ideas and institutions have located its origins in the Roman and medieval juristic tradition and its acme in modern theories of the sovereign territorial state. Thomas Aquinas devised a clear separation between promulgation and counseling (or interpretation) and ascribed the former to the legislator and the latter to ministers. The same distinction returned in Marsilius of Padua’s Defensor Pacis, which identified promulgation with the solemn ratification of the law by the “multitude,” the only legitimate sovereign, without even distinguishing between the directly assembled multitude and the assembly of the representatives of the multitude (Urbinati, 2006, 72).

  5. 5.

    Bodin’s Six livres de la république (1576), one of Rousseau’s seminal sources of inspiration, identified the supreme power of the state with the unitary source of legal obligation and located it in the “moral person” of the sovereign, be it individual or collective. This principle also applied to modern parliaments, which either exercised delegated power (imperative mandate) or were themselves sovereign. Parliaments hold power in trust because “their resolution would be of no effect without her [the queen of England’s] will…the Estates have no power of deciding, commanding, or determining anything, seeing that they cannot meet or dissolve without an express command” (Bodin, 1992, 20–21, 23).

  6. 6.

    To paraphrase De Ruggiero (1959, 72–73), the political trajectory from Sieyes to Paine and to Condorcet mirrored the three revolutions France went through: a revolution sensu stricto liberal, a democratic revolution, and a social revolution. On Sieyes’ proposal of linking eligibility for the National Assembly to taxation (the value of a marc of silver), see Aulard (1913, 73–75), Kates (1985, 44–45), and Gueniffey (1994, 86–106).

  7. 7.

    The comparison of Paine with Sieyes is novel; much more familiar is his comparison with Madison in order to stress the former’s more genuine republicanism (Kalyvas & Katznelson, 2008) or the latter’s more genuine liberal constitutionalism (Holmes, 1988).

  8. 8.

    The putting any individual as a figure for a nation is improper. “This is why the oath of allegiance was improper unless taken ‘to the nation only,’ but it ‘ought not to be obfuscated by being figuratively taken to, or in the name of, any person’” (Paine, 1989, 191).

  9. 9.

    On the transition, beginning in 1792, from a model inspired by a monarchical sovereignty to one inspired by an acephalous sovereignty, see De Francesco (1992) and Viola (1989).

  10. 10.

    Paine’s description of democracy was close to James Wilson’s, which called it a “species” of government in which the “supreme power” is “inherent in the people, and is either exercised by themselves or by their representatives” (Bailyn, 1993, vol. 1, 802).

  11. 11.

    Sieyes “Variétés” (Le Moniteur, July 6, 1791, in Sieyes 1989, vol. 2, Doc. No. 29).

  12. 12.

    Here is a curious comment on Sieyes’ attempt to mediate between monarchists and republicans, by Paine’s first biographer: “... he had a superstitious faith in individual executive, which, as an opportunist, he proposed to vest in the reigning house. This class of ‘revival’ in the constitution were the work of Sieyes, who was the brain of the Jacobins, now led by Robespierre, and with him ignoring republicanism” (Conway, 1969, 127).

  13. 13.

    Sieyes, “Pour ma dispute avec Payne” (in Sieyes, 1999, 445). “Thus, monarchy... is established in order to preserve a kind of equality that cannot be obtained in the republics; it is a true limit on inequality because it tells you that no matter how high the social position you have reached, you will always have the interest of society above you. There is but one legal inequality, that of all over each; this is represented by the person of the prince. Itis not the superiority of the magistrate, but a true personal inequality, the only one. ‘We want a prince in order to avoid the risk and evil of having a master,’ repeated Sieyes with Rousseau” (Sieyes, 1999, 421).

  14. 14.

    Sieyes’ answer to Paine’s letter of July 8, 1791 in Sieyes (1989, vol. 2, Doc. No. 30).

  15. 15.

    Reasoning from the same premises, Fisher Ames had argued a few years before that it was incorrect to think of representation in terms of a “copy” or even an “image” because the representatives did not “reflect” the opinions of the delegates as if they were a mirror. “The representation of the people is something more than the people” because it puts into motion something that does not exist. It is the filtering work of social interests thanks to which nobody votes “for their own indemnity” or decides “by surprise” or the opinion of the moment (Bailyn, 1993, vol. 1, 892).

  16. 16.

    Paine’s position resembles closely that of Spinoza in his Political Treatise. Paine certainly knew Spinoza’s works, which in the eighteenth century were the texts of the religious skeptics, and shared with Spinoza the libertine culture which made both of them a target of religion intolerance and persecution. Paine cited Spinoza’s biblical hermeneutics in The Age of Reason (Paine, 1995, 767).

  17. 17.

    Representative government is mixed-regime mélange of “ce qu’il y a de bon dans la démocratie, dans l’aristocratie, et dans la monarchie” (Sieyes “Bases de l’ordres social” in Pasquino, 1998, 186).

  18. 18.

    “Ce projet est le dernier mot du système social girondin” (Buchez & Roux, 1836, vol. 24, 101). Although Condorcet was not a party man, Brissot’s party backed his plan when the two wings of the Convention split and the Montagnards’ hostility to Condorcet’s plan became radical (Badinter, 1991, 351–366). On the independence of Condorcet from political parties, and particularly the Girondins see Dorigny (1989, 333–340); on Condorcet’s authorship of the plan, see Alengry (1973, 189–193) and Galy (1932, 167–168).

  19. 19.

    For an excellent depiction of the political environment within which the Convention was elected and the constitution written and discussed, see Badinter and Badinter (1988, 483–540); on the collaboration between Condorcet and Sieyes in the common project of advancing the political culture of indirect government, see Guilhaumou (1997, 223–234).

  20. 20.

    Carl Schmitt (1994, 38) situated Condorcet between Kant’s “belief in the progress of publicity” and Bentham’s “fanaticism” in “liberal rationality.”

  21. 21.

    Condorcet’s plan was composed of an “Exposition des principes et des motifs du plan de constitution,” of the “Projet de Déclaration des droits naturels, civils et politiques des hommes,” and of the “Projet de constitution franç aise.” The English translation of the “Exposition” and some parts of the two “Projets” is in McLean and Hewitt (1994). Hereafter I shall cite the English texts and omit reference to volume 12 of Condorcet’s Oeuvres.

  22. 22.

    See footnote n. 13.

  23. 23.

    According to Sieyes, “pure” democracy meant “raw” (brute) democracy since it resembled raw materials before human labor transformed and refined them. It meant direct rule, but also an inferior or less perfect way of ruling. It was a system that fit societies that were not yet “civilized” because they were unfamiliar with the division of labor and a work ethic, still attracted by “passe-tempts agréables” and not appreciative of industry and the abundance of artificial goods stimulated by commerce; Emmanuel-Joseph Sieyes, “Observations sur le rapport du comité de constitution, concernant la nouvelle organization de la France” (2 Oct. 1789) in Sieyes (1999, Doc. No. 25, 262).

  24. 24.

    “L’intérêt commun, l’amélioration de l’état social lui-même, nous crient de faire du gouvernement une profession particulière” (Sieyes, 1999, Doc. No. 26, 262).

  25. 25.

    It is well known that Sieyes applied to politics Adam Smith’s social philosophy and in particular the criterion of the division of labor (Pasquino, 1998). However, in the context of politics, the concept of “function” has inegalitarian implications because it means “separation” among and hierarchy within the “profession” of the electors and that of the elected, and results into an asymmetry of power; it implies, as Sieyes himself wrote, the distinction between active and passive citizenship (Bastid, 1970, 370).

  26. 26.

    Condorcet used the term “droit negative” in Lettres d’un bourgeois de New-Haven à un citoyen de Virginie (1787–1789) in Condorcet (1968, vol. 9, 78).

  27. 27.

    Condorcet’s model was the Constitution of Pennsylvania (whose text was drafted by two of his friends, Paine and Benjamin Franklin) which instituted the council of the censors (Art. 47). The procedure of constitutional revision in ordinary times was, however, indirect in the sense that the citizen formulated the question so as to check whether the majority thought there was agreement on the proposal of having an amendment.

  28. 28.

    Cesare Beccaria based his justification of habeas corpus and fair trial on two crucial premises: the delimitation within the legal domain of the spheres of legislation, application, and enforcement of the laws, respectively; and the depersonalization of the act of judgment. The principle of depersonalization in relation to the “preferences” and “emotions” of the judge (hence the claim that forensic cases must be based on verifiable facts and testimonies) led Beccaria to conceptualize judgment in the court in terms of a syllogism of the first figure: “In ogni delitto si deve fare dal giudice un sillogismo perfetto: la maggiore dev’essere la legge generale, la minore l’azione conforme o no alla legge, la conseguenza la libertá o la pena” (Beccaria, 2016, 22). On the role of Beccaria in the evolution of the theory of punishment as part of the theory of right and the rule of law in Condorcet’s thought see Baker (1975, 230–233) and Magrin (2001, 56–59).

  29. 29.

    In the Exposition of the constitutional plan, he submitted to the assembly three methods for constraining the power of a mono-assembly system, all of them based on time delay or constraint over urgency: Dividing up the time of discussion by requiring that “all legislative acts... will be debated twice,” the first time in order to see whether the issue is to be accepted for consideration; dividing up the assembly into two “big committees” so that each of them discusses, but does not vote on, the proposal separately; the third way consisted in requiring two-thirds of the votes in a named ballot “to declare a matter urgent and to dispense with the legally prescribed intervals” (Condorcet, 1994, 202–203).

  30. 30.

    From a manuscript annotation written by Condorcet during his chairmanship of the comité de constitution, quoted in Magrin (2001, 145).

  31. 31.

    The idea of the two registers of politics, constitutional and ordinary, the former qualitatively superior to the latter, derives from a notion of political autonomy as absolute creation of the will, in Rousseau’s sense. For a “liberal” rendering of this dualism (Elster, 1996, 93–94).

  32. 32.

    On the educational and egalitarian function of the primary assemblies see the sympathetic description of one of the first of Condorcet’s biographers, Léon Cahen (1904).

  33. 33.

    An analysis of the difference between Condorcet and Sieyes based on this speech of Sieyes was first proposed by Alengry (1973, 194, 482–483) and Bastid (1939, 59–60).

  34. 34.

    By 1789, Sieyes had expressed his strong disagreement with the admirers of the Unites States and accused them of attempting to make France into “une infinité de petites démocraties, qui ne s’uniroient ensuite que par les liens d’une confédération générale...Le peuple ou la nation ne peut avoir qu’une voix, celle de la législature nationale” (Sieyes, 1985, 234, 238). The most informative work on Sieyes in English language is by Forsyth (1987), Chapters 7, 8, and 9 on Sieyes’s theory of representation and his project of representative government.

  35. 35.

    “Voici son [Condorcet’s] plan: une représentation fedérative qui fait les lois, un conseil représentatif qui les exécute. Une représentation générale, formée des representations particulières de chacun des départements, n’est plus une représentation, mais un congrès” (Saint-Just, 1976, 190).

  36. 36.

    Like Robespierre, Jaume wrote, Sieyes used ‘des propos de Rousseau tournés contre la Représentation, pour affirmer que “‘la volonté générale” est... dans le “pouvoir législatif” élu!” (Jaume, 1989, 296).

  37. 37.

    “Dans cette politique de la raison, la contradiction entre inaliénabilité et indivisibilité peut en principe être résolue: en définitive, Condorcet est...le seul à y parvenir” (Jaume, 1989, 311).

  38. 38.

    This seems to confirm Papadopoulos’ opinion according to which both the right to veto a law by citizens and the right to formulate new laws by citizens have a kind of legitimation character rather than a destabilization effect (1995, 433).

References

  • Aldridge, A. O. (1984). Tom Paine’s American ideology. University of Delaware Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alengry, F. (1973 [1904]). Condorcet: Guide de la Révolution française, théoricien du droit constitutionnel et précurseur de la science sociale. Burt Franklin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aulard, F. A. (1913). Histoire politique de la Révolution francçise: Origines et développement de la démocratie et de la république, 1789–1804. Librairie A. Colin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Badinter, R. (1991). Condorcet et les Girondins. In F. Furet & M. Ozouf (Eds.), La Gironde et les Girondins (pp. 351–366). Payot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Badinter, E., & Badinter, R. (1988). Condorcet: Un intellectuel en politique. Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, K. M. (1975). Condorcet: From natural philosophy to social mathematics. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailyn, B. (Ed.) (1993). The debate on the constitution: Federalist and antifederalist speeches, articles, and letters during the struggle over ratification (2 Vols.). Library of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bastid, P. (1939). Les Discours de Sieyès dans les débats constitutionnels de l’An III (2 et 18 Thermidor): Édition critique avec une introduction et des notes. Librairie Hachette.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bastid, P. (1970). Sieyès et sa pensée. Hachette.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beccaria, C. (2016). Dei delitti e delle pene. Newton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodin, J. (1992). On sovereignty: Four chapters from the six books of the Commonwealth (J. Franklin, Ed.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brissot de Warville, J.-P. (1789). Plan de conduite pour les députés aux États Généraux. N. p.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchez, P.-J.-B., & Roux, P.-C. (1836). Histoire parlementaire de la Révolution française,ou Journal des assemblées nationales depuis 1789 jusqu’en 1815 (Volumes 24 and 26). Pau-lin Libraire.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carré de Malberg, R. (1922). Contribution à la Théorie générale de l’État (2 Vols.). Librairie Recueil Sirey.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero, M. T. (2008). On the laws. In On the commonwealth and on the laws (J. G. Zetzel, Ed., pp. 105–175). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cahen, L. (1904). Condorcet et la Révolution française. Félix Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cochin, A. (1979). L’Esprit du jacobinisme: Une interprétation sociologique de la Révolution française. Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Condorcet, M. J. A. N. C., Marquis de. (1786). Vie de Monsieur Turgot. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Condorcet, M. J. A. N. C., Marquis de. (1968). Oeuvres: Nouvelle impression en fac-similé de l’édition Paris, 1847–1849 (12 Vols., M. F. Arago & A. Condorcet-O’Connor, Eds.). Friedrich Frommann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Condorcet, M. J. A. N. C., Marquis de. (1986). Sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des déecisions rendues à la pluralité des voix: Discours préliminaire. In M. J. A. N. C., Marquis de Condorcet (Ed.), Sur les élections et autres texts (pp. 7–177). Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Condorcet, M. J. A. N. C., Marquis de. (1994). Foundations of social choice and political theory (I. McLean & F. Hewitt, Trans. and Ed.). Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Constant, B. (1998). The liberty of the ancients compared with that of the moderns. In Political writings (B. Fontana, Trans. and ed.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conway, M. D. (1969). The life of Thomas Paine. Benjamin Blom.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, R. A. (1956). A preface to democratic theory. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Francesco, A. (1992). Il governo senza testa. Movimento democratico e federalismo nella Francia rivoluzionaria, 1789–1795. Morano.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Ruggiero, G. (1959). The history of European liberalism (R.G. Collingwood, Trans.). Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Saint-Just, L-A. (1976). Discours sur la Constitution de la France (23 April 1793). In A. Liénard (Ed.), Théorie politique. Éditions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorigny, M. (1989). Condorcet, libèral et girondin. In P. Crépel & C. Gilain (Eds.), Condorcet, mathématicien, économiste, philosophe, homme politique (pp. 333–340). Minerve.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1996). Ulysses and the Sirens: Studies in rationality and irrationality. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forsyth, M. (1987). Reason and revolution: The political thought of the Abbé Sieyes. Leicester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galy, F. (1932). La notion de constitution dans les projets de 1793. Mechelinck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grofman, B. N., & Feld, S. L. (1988). Rousseau’s general will: A condorcetian perspective. American Political Science Review, 82, 567–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gueniffey, P. (1993). Le nombre et la raison: La Révolution française et les élections. Edi-tions de l’Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gueniffey, P. (1994). Cordeliers and Girondins: The prehistory of the Republic? In B. Fontana (Ed.), The invention of the modern republic (pp. 86–106). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guilhaumou, J. (1997). Condorcet-Sieyès: Une amitié intellectuelle. In A.-M. Chouillet & P. Crépel (Eds.), Condorcet: Homme des Lumières et de Révolution (pp. 223–234). ENS ́Éditions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, S. (1988). Precommitment and the paradox of democracy. In J. Elster & R. Slagstad (Eds.), Constitutionalism and democracy (pp. 195–240). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaume, L. (1989). Le discours jacobin et la democratie. Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaume, L. (1990). Échec au libéralisme. Éditions Kimé.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalyvas, A., & Katznelson, I. (2008). Liberal beginnings: Making a republic for the moderns. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1991). The metaphysics of morals (M. Gregor, Trans.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kates, G. (1985). The Cercle social, the Girondins, and the French revolution. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kintzler, C. (1984). Condorcet: L’instruction publique et la naissance du citoyen. Le Sycomore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magrin, G. (2001). Condorcet: Un costituzionalismo democratico. Franco Angeli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manin, B. (1997). The principles of representative government. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLean, I., & Hewitt, F. (Eds.). (1994). Introduction to Foundations of social choice and political theory (pp. 3–90). Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montesquieu, C. L. de Secondat, Baron de. (1989). The Spirit of the Laws (1748) (A. M. Choler, B. C. Miller, & H. S. Stone, Trans.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, E. S. (1988). Inventing the people: The rise of popular sovereignty in England and America. Morton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paine, T. (1989). The Rights of Man (1792). In B. Kuklick (Ed.), Political writings (pp. 49–203). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paine, T. (1995). To the authors of ‘The Republican’ (July 2, 1791). In E. Foner (Ed.), Collected writings. Library of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papadopoulos, Y. (1995). Analysis of functions and dysfunctions of direct democracy: Top-down and bottom-up perspectives. Politics & Society, 23, 421–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pasquino, P. (1998). Sieyes et l’invention de la constitution en France. Odile Jacob.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pedullà, G. (2018). Machiavelli in Tumult: The discourse on Livy and the origins of political conflictualism. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pertué, M. (1989). La censure du peuple dans le projet de Constitution de Condorcet. In P. Crépel & C. Gilain (Eds.), Condorcet, mathématicien, economiste, philosophe, homme politique (pp. 322–332). Minerve.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1997). Republicanism: A theory of freedom and government. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosanvallon, P. (1998). Le peuple introuvable: Histoire de la représentation démocratique en France. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosanvallon, P. (2000). La démocratie inachevée: Histoire de la souveraineté du peuple en France. Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (1987). The social contract. Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. (1994). The crisis of parliamentary democracy. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieyes, J.-E. (1985). Ecrits politiques (R. Zapperi, Ed.). Editions des archives contem-poraines.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieyes, J.-E. (1989). Oeuvres (3 Vols., M. Dorigny, Ed.). Edhis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieyes, J.-E. (1999). Des manuscrits de Sieyès: 1773–1799 (C. Fauré, Ed.). Honoré Champion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urbinati, N. (2005). Continuity and rupture: Political judgment in democratic representation. Constellations, 12(1), 194–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Urbinati, N. (2006). Representative democracy: Principles and genealogy. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urbinati, N. (2012). Competing for liberty: The republican critique of democracy. American Political Science Review, 105(1), 607–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viola, P. (1989). Il trono vuoto: La transizione della sovranità nella rivoluzione francese. Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolin, S. (1989). The presence of the past: Essays on the state and the constitution. Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, G. S. (1969). The creation of the American Republic 1776–1787. University of North Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, G. S. (2009). Empire of liberty: A history of the early republic. 1785–1815. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nadia Urbinati .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Urbinati, N. (2023). Democratic Republicanism in the French Revolution. In: Krause, S.S., Jörke, D. (eds) Republicanism and Democracy. Contributions to Political Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-15780-6_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics