Skip to main content

A Post-Reductionist Buddhism?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Reasons and Empty Persons: Mind, Metaphysics, and Morality
  • 292 Accesses

Abstract

Perhaps more than any other contemporary scholar, Mark Siderits has illuminated the deep connections between ontology, explanation, epistemology, and philosophy of language in Indian Buddhist philosophy. His ground-breaking interpretations of Abhidharma and Madhyamaka—particularly concerning reductionism, emptiness, and the two truths—have largely set the terms of debate in Anglophone Buddhist philosophy. This chapter is very much in the spirit of Siderits’ work, though it will reach conclusions somewhat at odds with his own. The first part of the chapter will examine the ontological and explanatory reductionism of much Abhidharma thought. The thorough-going reductionism of Abhidharma yields a two-tiered ontology of ultimately real and (merely) conventionally real entities, and a correspondingly two-tiered account of ultimate and conventional truth. The second part of the chapter will take up the Madhyamaka critique of Buddhist reductionism and the philosophical consequences of the view that all things are empty (śūnya) of inherent existence (svabhāva). If all things are empty, then arguably Abhidharma reductionism is undermined. That is, if everything is empty of inherent existence, then the project of reducing things to that which exists inherently is doomed. Moreover, as Sidertis has so forcefully argued, the Madhyamaka view of emptiness undermines the Abhidharma distinction between two truths. As he provocatively puts it, for the Mādhyamika, “the ultimate truth is that there is no ultimate truth” (Siderits and Katsura 2013, p. 273). Hence, if all things are empty, all real entities are conventionally real, and all truths are conventionally true. Yet, as discussed in part three of the chapter, this raises the specter of the ‘dismal slough’—a pernicious ontological and epistemic flattening that threatens to undermine the critical and revisionist force Buddhist philosophy. How might a Mādhyamika avoid the dismal slough? One approach, explored in Siderits’ more recent work, is to, as it were, transpose Buddhist reductionism into a Mādhyamika key. Here the strategy is to show that while Buddhist reductionism cannot provide an account of ultimate reality, it still offers the best account of conventional reality. It will be argued that recent work in the philosophy of science gives reasons to doubt this approach. Finally, section four of the chapter will explore an alternative, post-reductionist strategy for avoiding the dismal slough. This alternative is based on three key ideas:

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    More specifically, Buddhist Reductionist ideas are developed in the Sarvāstivāda and Sautrāntika Abhidharma schools.

  2. 2.

    ‘yatra bhinnena tadbuddhir anyāpohe dhiyā ca tat | ghaṭārthavat saṃvṛtisat paramārthasad anyathā ||’ AK 6.4.

  3. 3.

    Something along these lines is developed in Ganeri (2007) Ch. 6.

  4. 4.

    I include regularity theories of causation among accounts of real causation here.

  5. 5.

    Of course, it is well known that Putnam eventually abandoned the internal realism he defending in the 1980’s.

  6. 6.

    Though it is worth emphasizing again that there is an alternative reading of Madhyamaka as offering a kind of global error-theory (Tillemans 2011).

  7. 7.

    I will leave aside here the complex question of non-discursive, non-conceptual (niṣprapañca) truths.

  8. 8.

    For more on the notion of ontological deflationism in this context see my (2008).

  9. 9.

    Of course, it would be fair for the quietist to reply that the whole point of quietism is to eschew the misguided desire for metaphysically deep explanation. In that case, we may say that there is a trade-off between quietist anti-skepticism and explanatory power.

  10. 10.

    See pp. 175–178 of Sidertis (2011) for a fuller discussion of the role of intrinsic natures in this account.

  11. 11.

    One might, of course, adopt some other form of ontological grounding, such as realization.

  12. 12.

    This claim about the ubiquity of dependent arising does not imply that everything is connected to everything else, but only that each phenomenon is related to at least one other phenomenon. See Sidertis (2011) for further discussion of this point.

  13. 13.

    That my hypothetical post-reductionist Mādhyamika would agree with Garfeld here, does not, of course, entail that Garfield would in turn agree with my overall account.

  14. 14.

    Both John Dunne (2004) and Laura Guerrero (2013) have interpreted Dharmakīrti’s notion of arthakriyā in similarly pragmatist terms.

References

  • Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, Paul. 1986. Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind-brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, Lindley, and Nancy Maull. 1977. Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science 44: 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunne, John. 2004. Foundations of Dharmakīrti’s philosophy. Somerville: Wisdom Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupre, John. 1993. The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganeri, Jonardon. 2007. The concealed art of the soul: Theories of self and practices of truth in Indian ethics and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, Jay. 2002. Empty words: Buddhist philosophy and cross-cultural interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerrero, Laura. 2013. Truth for the rest of us: Conventional truth in the work of Dharmakīrti. Dissertation. ProQuest.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horst, Steven. 2007. Beyond reduction: Philosophy of mind and post-reductionist philosophy of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Beyond reduction: From naturalism to cognitive pluralism. Mind & Matter 12: 197–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, Richard. 1983. Biological determinism. Tanner lectures on human values. Vol. 4. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie, Matthew. 2008. Ontological deflationism in Madhyamaka. Contemporary Buddhism 9: 197–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, Paul, and Hilary Putnam. 1958. The unity of science as a working hypothesis. In Concepts, theories and the mind-body problem. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science II, ed. H. Fiegel, M. Scriven, and G. Maxwell, 3–36. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradhan, Prahlad. 1975. Abhidharmakośabhāṣyam of Vasubandhu. Tibetan Sanskrit works 8. Patna: K. P. Jayaswal Research Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, Graham, Mark Siderits, and Tom Tillemans. 2011. The (two) truths about truth. In Moonshadows: Conventional truth in Buddhist philosophy, ed. Cowherds, 131–150. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 1981. Reason, truth, and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Renewing philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, Robert. 1991. Life itself. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siderits, Mark, and Shoryu Katsura. 2013. Nāgārjuna’s middle way: Mūlamadhyamakakārika. Somerville: Wisdom Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidertis, Mark. 1997. Buddhist reductionism. Philosophy East and West 47: 455–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Buddhism as philosophy: An introduction. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Is everything connected to everything else? What the Gopīs know. In Moonshadows: Conventional truth in Buddhist philosophy, ed. Cowherds, 167–180. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Personal identity and Buddhist philosophy: Empty persons. 2nd ed. London: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Studies in Buddhist philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, Michael. 2002. Reduction, emergence, and explanation. In Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science, ed. P. Machaner and M. Silberstein, 80–107. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tillemans, Tom. 2011. How far can a Mādhyamika Buddhist reform conventional truth? Dismal relativism, fictionalism, easy-easy truth, and the alternatives. In Moonshadows: Conventional truth in Buddhist philosophy, ed. Cowherds, 151–166. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen. 1974. The structure of scientific theories. In The structure of scientific theories, ed. F. Suppe, 127–134. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westerhoff. 2009. Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka: A philosophical introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew MacKenzie .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

MacKenzie, M. (2023). A Post-Reductionist Buddhism?. In: Coseru, C. (eds) Reasons and Empty Persons: Mind, Metaphysics, and Morality. Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures, vol 36. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-13995-6_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics