Skip to main content

Direct Benefit, Equipoise, and Research on the Non-consenting

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Medical Research Ethics: Challenges in the 21st Century

Part of the book series: Philosophy and Medicine ((PHME,volume 132))

  • 400 Accesses

Abstract

Research on human subjects aims to obtain knowledge of vital importance for human health and functioning. Neuroscientific research specifically is understood as oriented towards three goals: the maintenance of neurological health, the treatment of neurological diseases or syndromes, and the enhancement of neurological functioning. Most guidelines or regulations for pediatric research (whether in the U.S. or elsewhere) require that if a research intervention exposes subjects to more than minimal risk, a prospect of direct benefit is required—along with some other important criteria. It is also required for any research project, that the methods and design will yield scientifically valid knowledge. This is typically met via placebo-controlled trials. This chapter presents an argument to the effect that more than minimal risk research on pediatric subjects cannot meet both ethical requirements. The basic idea is that either the subjects in the control or experimental arm will receive a prospect of direct benefit, but not both. This chapter also argues that the ethical weight or importance of this dilemma is very acute for neuroscientific research given the complexity of the brain’s functioning and the correlated difficulty of judging whether there is a “prospect” of direct benefit. The second half responds to this argument via a case study in neuroscientific research. The solution recapitulates a type of component analysis according to which different ethical principles apply to different activities of a research study.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The problem I highlight in this paper should not be confused with the problem of justifying a placebo control in the setting of active treatments. Whether such studies can satisfy clinical equipoise is a different question from the one I address here. My question is this: if clinical equipoise is satisfied, can a study promise a prospect of direct benefit?

  2. 2.

    The applicability of the moral justification is, in this case, broader than its regulatory applicability since sub-part -D governs pediatric subjects alone, not psychiatric subjects, adults suffering from neurodegenerative diseases, or mentally disabled adults, etc.

  3. 3.

    If the evidence on the therapeutic misconception is correct, neither do adults understand the complexities of RCTs. But that fact would only argue for added protections for adults, not for taking away the subpart D protections for pediatric subjects.

  4. 4.

    I thank an anonymous reviewer for prompting me to address these terms.

  5. 5.

    Freedman (1987, 120) seems to think that disagreement and no consensus are synonymous as he mentions both as characterizing clinical equipoise. They are different. As I am using the term, non-consensus occurs if there is an absence of evidence to determine one way or the other, which arm of a study is better or worse overall. This can occur if the trial is a first-in-human trial or the preliminary data is based on poorly controlled pilot studies. Expert disagreement occurs if evidence exists to support differing opinions on the overall merits of the respective arms of the study. The distinction can be understood as tracking the distinction between having no evidence at all, and having ambiguous evidence.

  6. 6.

    Potential conflict of interest disclosure: I worked for an IRB at the time it approved this study, though I was not a voting member.

  7. 7.

    Neither the authors of the study (Marcus et al. 2013) nor commentators on it (Witmans and Shafazand 2013) mention the fact that A-T can deleteriously affect one’s immune system since the adenoids and tonsils are lymphatic organs. A-Ts are associated with a 17% increase risk for infectious diseases, and a 2–threefold increased risk for respiratory infections (Byars et al. 2018). In fairness to the CHAT researchers, these numbers were not published until 2018. However, it was known that the adenoids and tonsils make up the lymphatic organ system. It should have been anticipated that the immune system might be compromised. In any case, the facts of the Byars study place added burdens on the A-T side and brings into equilibrium the relative benefit-harm ratio between A-T and waiting.

  8. 8.

    The reason is that moral discourse cannot proceed all the way “down” to assessing concrete actions unless the interlocutors see or feel for themselves the moral values at stake with those actions.

  9. 9.

    The reader might find oxymoronic the idea that a researcher can expect unanticipated risks. The tension is resolved once we consider how an intellectually humble researcher would approach, for example, doing a first in-human trial.

  10. 10.

    In a very careful and informative study, Rid and Wendler (2011) critique component analysis. They state, “The fundamental problem with different ethical requirements for therapeutic and nontherapeutic interventions is that they introduce different thresholds of acceptable net risk in biomedical research and thereby render risk-benefit evaluations incoherent. For example, “component analysis” allows competent participants to consent to sometimes significant risks without any compensating potential clinical benefits, as long as the risks result from a nontherapeutic intervention…” (2011, 148). If this is what component analysis allows, then Rid and Wendler are correct to abandon it. However, I do not think that component analysis has such consequences. As explained in the text, component analysis is measuring the various action types that take place within a research protocol against their respective moral principles. By respective moral principles I mean that certain action types are best analyzed only against certain ethical principles. For example, a person's arrogance cannot be assessed with reference to the principle of autonomy. We think arrogance is bad, yet if someone harbors supremacist views about oneself but never shares them or acts on them, no one’s autonomy is violated. The more fitting principle to assess the moral deficiency of arrogance is the principle of justice or better yet, the virtue of humility. Responding more directly to Rid and Wendler’s concerns, component analysis does not justify participants taking on significant risks without any compensating benefit. The reason is that component analysis doesn’t tell you which principles to select. It just tells you that you must select the most fitting ones. If one selects the virtue of commutative justice, component analysis does not allow competent participants to take on significant risks without any benefit (see Napier, 2019, chapter 11 for further discussion).

  11. 11.

    Observations such as these might be where the notion of disadvantage might be useful as a marker or indicator for unjust treatment. Children who, no fault of their own, suffer from diseases with few clinical options are exposed to research projects that tolerate a higher risk than research projects on subjects with clinical options. Of course, the reason why this treatment is wrong is because it fails to treat all children as persons, and instead treats them in light of accidental features.

  12. 12.

    Currently, whatever therapeutic modalities are being tested none of them can reverse the damage done by the progression of the disease at the time they received the modality.

  13. 13.

    I harbor the opinion, however, that this claim is wrongheaded—which is why I title these “case based complications.” I do not think children who are at a clinical dead end can be subjects of research with a risk–benefit ratio “skewed in favor of risk” (Deakin op. cit.). That would treat children differently depending on accidental features, i.e., whether they have clinical options or not.

  14. 14.

    The argument in this paragraph is only to the point that desolate treatment options for a small subject population is not a reason for not controlling the proposed study. There are other reasons noted above that do justify not controlling the study, namely, if the route of administration requires neurosurgery, and thus a sham control.

  15. 15.

    I thank two anonymous referees for comments on a previous draft.

References

  • Augustine, E.F., H.R. Adams, and J.W. Mink. 2013. Clinical trials in rare disease: Challenges and opportunities. Journal of Child Neurology 28 (9): 1142–1150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Augustine, E.F., C.A. Beck, H.R. Adams, S. Defendorf, A. Vierhile, D. Timm, J.M. Weimer, J.W. Mink, F.J. Marshall. 2018. Short-term administration of mycophenolate is well-tolerated in CLN3 disease (juvenile neuronal ceroid lipofuscinosis). JIMD Reports 43: 117–124. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berry-Kravis, Elizabeth, et al. 2020. A double-blind, randomized, placebo-controlled clinical study of trofinetide in the treatment of fragile X syndrome. Pediatric Neurology 110: 30–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brody, Howard. 2012. ‘A critique of clinical equipoise: Therapeutic misconception in the ethics of clinical trials. In The ethical challenges of human research: Selected Essays, ed. Miller, Franklin G. New York: Oxford Scholarship Online (Published online May 2015). https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:osobl/9780199896202.003.0015. Accessed Sept 02, 2020.

  • Byars, S.G., S.C. Stearns, and J.J. Boomsma. 2018. Association of long-term risk of respiratory, allergic, and infectious diseases with removal of adenoids and tonsils in childhood. JAMA Otolaryngology-Head & Neck Surgery. 144 (7): 594–603.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartagena, C.M., K.L. Phillips, G.L. Williams, et al. 2013. Mechanism of action for NNZ-2566 anti-inflammatory effects following PBBI involves upregulation of immunomodulator ATF3. Neuromolecular Medicine 15: 504–514. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12017-013-8236-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deakin, C.T., I.E. Alexander, C.A. Hooker, and I.H. Kerridge. 2013. Gene therapy researchers’ assessments of risks and perceptions of risk acceptability in clinical trials. Molecular Therapy 21 (4): 806–815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descotes, J. 2005. Immunotoxicology: Role in the safety assessment of drugs. Drug Safety. 28 (2): 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emanuel, E.J., D. Wendler, and C. Grady. 2000. What makes clinical research ethical? JAMA 283 (20): 2701–2711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emanuel, E.J., and F.G. Miller. 2001. The ethics of placebo-controlled trials—A middle ground. New England Journal of Medicine 345 (12): 915–918.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, M.J., and R.W. Behrman, eds. 2004. Ethical Conduct of clinical research involving children. Washington DC: Institute of Medicine of the National Academies, The National Academies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, A., E. Robbins, and D. Wendler. 2012. Which benefits of research participation count as ‘direct’? Bioethics 26 (2): 60–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freedman, B. 1987. Equipoise and the ethics of clinical research. New England Journal of Medicine 317: 141–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glaze, Daniel G., et al. 2017. A double-blind, randomized, placebo-controlled clinical study of trofinetide in the treatment of Rett syndrome. Pediatric Neurology 76: 37–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. 1969. Philosophical reflections on experimenting with human subjects. Daedalus 219–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kimmelman, J. 2013. Biologics, ethics and the human brain. In Neuroethics in practice, ed. M. Farah and A. Chatterjee, 251–264. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kimmelman J. 2018. Better to be in the placebo arm for trials of neurological therapies? Cell Transplantation April: 677–681. https://doi.org/10.1177/0963689718755708

  • King, N.M. 2000. Defining and describing benefit appropriately in clinical trials. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 28 (4): 332–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, Robert J. 1986. Ethics and regulation of clinical research, 2nd ed. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lew, C.D. 2017. What do new neuroscience discoveries in children mean for their open future? In Neuroethics: Anticipating the future, ed. J. Illes, 159–179. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahant, Sanjay, et al. 2015. Association of national guidelines with tonsillectomy perioperative care and outcomes. Pediatrics 136 (1): 53–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcus, C.L., R.H. Moore, C.L. Rosen, B. Giordani, S.L. Garetz, H.G. Taylor, R.B. Mitchell, R. Amin, E.S. Katz, R. Arens, S. Paruthi. 2013. Childhood adenotonsillectomy trial (CHAT). A randomized trial of adenotonsillectomy for childhood sleep apnea. New England Journal of Medicine. 368 (25): 2366–2376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathews, D.J., J. Sugarman, H. Bok, D.M. Blass, J.T. Coyle, P. Duggan, et al. 2008. Cell-based interventions for neurologic conditions: Ethical challenges for early human trials. Neurology 71 (4): 288–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Napier, Stephen. 2019. Uncertain bioethics: Moral risk and human dignity. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Redline, S., R. Amin, D. Beebe, R.D. Chervin, S.L. Garetz, B. Giordani, C.L. Marcus, R.H. Moore, C.L. Rosen, R. Arens, and D. Gozal. 2011. The Childhood adenotonsillectomy trial (CHAT): Rationale, design, and challenges of a randomized controlled trial evaluating a standard surgical procedure in a pediatric population. Sleep 34 (11): 1509–1517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rid, A., and D. Wendler. 2011. A framework for risk-benefit evaluations in biomedical research. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 21 (2): 141–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, K. (2009). Ethical principles of pediatric research and drug development: A guide through national and international frameworks and applications to a worldwide perspective. In Pediatric drug development: Concepts and Applications, eds. A. E. Mulberg, S. A. Silber and J. N. van den Anker, 115–132. Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sardiello, Marco. 2017. Research reveals strategy to potentially treat juvenile Batten disease. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=qPzIqtKXCPo. Accessed September 9, 2020.

  • Selden, N.R., A. Al-Uzri, S.L. Huhn, et al. 2013. Central nervous system stem cell transplantation for children with neuronal ceroid lipofuscinosis. Journal of Neurosurgery Pediatrics 11 (6): 643–652. https://doi.org/10.3171/2013.3.PEDS12397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unguru, Y. 2015. Ethical challenges in early-phase pediatric research for life-limiting illness. Seminars in Pediatric Neurology 22: 177–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • United States Food and Drug Administration. 2001 Guidance for industry E 10 choice of control group and related issues in clinical trials. https://www.fda.gov/media/71349/download. Accessed November 9, 2020.

  • Weijer, C. 2000. The ethical analysis of risk. Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 28: 344–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witmans, M., and S. Shafazand. 2013. Adenotonsillectomy or watchful waiting in the management of childhood obstructive sleep apnea. Journal of Clinical Sleep Medicine 9 (11): 1225–1227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worgall, S., D. Sondhi, N.R. Hackett, et al. 2008. Treatment of late infantile neuronal ceroid lipofuscinosis by CNS administration of a serotype 2 adeno-associated virus expressing CLN2 cDNA. Human Gene Therapy 19 (5): 463–474. https://doi.org/10.1089/hum.2008.022.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephen Napier .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Napier, S. (2023). Direct Benefit, Equipoise, and Research on the Non-consenting. In: Zima, T., Weisstub, D.N. (eds) Medical Research Ethics: Challenges in the 21st Century. Philosophy and Medicine, vol 132. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-12692-5_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics