Skip to main content

Ψcat alive and Ψcat dead Are not Cats! Ontology and Statistics in “Realist” Versions of Quantum Mechanics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Quantum Mechanics and Fundamentality

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 460))

  • 471 Accesses

Abstract

It is often claimed that there are three “realist” versions of quantum mechanics: the de Broglie-Bohm theory or Bohmian mechanics, the spontaneous collapse theories and the many worlds interpretation.

We will explain why the two latter proposals suffer from serious defects coming from their ontology (or lack thereof) and that the many worlds interpretation is unable to account for the statistics encoded in the Born rule. The de Broglie-Bohm theory, on the other hand, has no problem of ontology and accounts naturally for the Born rule.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Unless the wave function happens to be an eigenstate of some operator.

  2. 2.

    Technically, it means that the operators associated to those properties or “observables” commute., More precisely, the Bell-Kochen-Specker result implies that, if \(\mathcal H\) is a Hilbert space of dimension at least four, and if \({\mathcal A}\) is the set of self-adjoint operators on \(\mathcal {H}\), there does not exist a map \(v: {\mathcal A} \to R\) such that:

    1. (1)

      \(\forall O \in { {\mathcal A}}\),

      $$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} v(O) \;\;\mbox{is an eigenvalue of} \;\;O. \end{aligned}$$
    2. (2)

      \(\forall O, O' \in { {\mathcal A}}\) with [O, O′] = OO′− O′O = 0,

      $$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} v(O O')=v(O) v(O'). \end{aligned}$$

    Obviously, there cannot be a statistical distribution of maps that do not exist.

  3. 3.

    This idea is emphasized in Tumulka (2018) Sect. 5.1.

  4. 4.

    Superposition refers to sums such (17.1) (Note of J.B.).

  5. 5.

    See Freire (2015) for an historical perspective on Everett (and other “dissidents” with respect to the quantum orthodoxy) and Barrett (2018) for a discussion of various interpretations of Everett’s ideas, many of which depart from the original ones.

  6. 6.

    I develop these objections in Bricmont (2016) (Sect. 6.1). See also Norsen (2017) (Chap. 10) and Maudlin (2019) (Chap. 6).

  7. 7.

    For more on all this, see e.g. Maudlin (2019) (Chap. 6).

  8. 8.

    The famous quote “The Lord God is subtle, but malicious he is not” is due to Einstein.

  9. 9.

    This problem is similar to the one posed by postulating a lower degree of existence for low probability worlds, see Sect. 17.2.1.

  10. 10.

    For a more detailed discussion, see the section on what is called GRW0 in Allori et al. (2008), and also Maudlin (2012) and Norsen (2014).

  11. 11.

    In Norsen (2014), the author explains why the pure wave function ontology is solipsism “for all practical purposes” because the world of the pure wave function ontology has a status similar to the idea that we are just brains in a vat, with our brains manipulated from the outside in just such a way as to make our illusory conscious experiences what they are. For more discussion of this ontology, see the collection of essays edited by Ney and Albert (2013).

  12. 12.

    For reviews and further discussions of those theories, see Ghirardi (2011), Ghirardi et al. (1995), Allori et al. (2008), Goldstein et al. (2012), Norsen (2017) (Chap. 9), Maudlin (2019) (Chap. 4).

  13. 13.

    In actual fact, in GRW theories, wave functions do not collapses exactly to 0, but to a very small value. This raises additional problems but we will not discuss them.

  14. 14.

    Our presentation of the de Broglie-Bohm theory follows the one of Bell (2004) and of Dürr et al. (2013) rather than the one of Bohm (1952a,b). This approach is actually close to the original one of de Broglie, see Bacciagaluppi and Valentini (2009).

    Many expositions of the de Broglie–Bohm theory are available, see, e.g., Albert (1994) or Tumulka (2004) for elementary introductions and Bacciagaluppi and Valentini (2009), Bohm and Hiley (1993), Bricmont (2016), Dürr and Teufel (2009), Dürr et al. (2013), Goldstein (2013), Towler (2009) for more advanced ones. There are also pedagogical videos made by students in Munich, available at: https://cast.itunes.uni-muenchen.de/vod/playlists/URqb5J7RBr.html.

  15. 15.

    For example, one could “measure” the spin of a particle in a given direction, with a Stern-Gerlach apparatus, starting with exactly the same initial wave function and initial position for the particle, but with two different orientations of the gradient of the magnetic field in the apparatus, and obtain two opposite results; thus no “spin property” of the particle has been measured; see Daumer et al. (1996), Bricmont et al. (2019) for more details.

  16. 16.

    See Maudlin (2011) (Chap. 10) for a similar discussion of the GRWm and GRWf ontologies, as opposed to the de Broglie–Bohm ontology.

  17. 17.

    Some people might argue that cutting the box in two already collapses the wave function. Since we discuss here gedanken experiments, it is not easy to determine what happens. But here is a modification of that experiment that avoids this objection: imagine that the box is inside a long cylinder, stretching from New York to Tokyo if you wish, and that we remove the two sides of the box perpendicular to the long side of the cylinder. Then the wave function will spread itself in the cylinder and the particle can be detected later on one side or the other of the cylinder.

  18. 18.

    For other criticisms of the GRWf theory, in particular in what sense is it really Lorentz invariant, see Esfeld and Gisin (2014).

References

  • Albert, D. (1994, May). Bohm’s alternative to quantum mechanics. Scientific American, 270, 32–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allori, V., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., & Zanghì, N. (2008). On the common structure of Bohmian mechanics and the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 353–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allori, V., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., & Zanghì, N. (2011). Many-worlds and Schrödinger’s first quantum theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bacciagaluppi, G., & Valentini, A. (2009). Quantum Mechanics at the Crossroads. Reconsidering the 1927 Solvay Conference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J. (2018). Everett’s relative-state formulation of quantum mechanics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (1966). On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics, 38, 447–452. Reprinted as Chap. 1 in Bell (2004).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (1984). Beables for quantum field theory. CERN-TH 4035/84. Reprinted as Chap. 19 in Bell (2004).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (1987). Are there quantum jumps? In C. W. Kilmister (Ed.), Schrödinger. Centenary celebration of a polymath (pp. 41–52). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted as Chap. 22 in Bell (2004).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (2004). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. Collected papers on quantum philosophy (2nd ed.). With an introduction by Alain Aspect. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1st ed., 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1952a). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. I. Physical Review, 85(2), 166–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1952b). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. II. Physical Review, 85(2), 180–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D., & Hiley, B. J. (1993). The undivided universe. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bricmont, J. (2016). Making sense of quantum mechanics. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bricmont, J., Goldstein, S., & Hemmick, D. (2019). Schrödinger’s paradox and proofs of nonlocality using only perfect correlation. Journal of Statistical Physics, 180, 74–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damour, T. (2006). Once upon Einstein. Wellesley, MA: A.K. Peters.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Daumer, M., Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (1996). Naive realism about operators. Erkenntnis, 45, 379–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, D. (1999). Quantum theory of probability and decisions. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A, 455, 3129–3137.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeWitt, B. S, & Graham, R. (Eds.) (1973). The many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (2013). Quantum physics without quantum philosophy. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., & Teufel, S. (2009). Bohmian mechanics. The physics and mathematics of quantum theory. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M., & Gisin, N. (2014). The GRW flash theory: a relativistic quantum ontology of matter in space-time? Philosophy of Science, 81, 248–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everett, H. (1957). ‘Relative state’ formulation of quantum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics, 29, 454–462 (1957). Reprinted in DeWitt and Graham (1973) (pp. 141–149).

    Google Scholar 

  • Freire, O. J. (2015). The quantum dissidents. Rebuilding the foundations of quantum mechanics (1950-1990). Berlin: Springer..

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G. C., Rimini, A., & Weber, T. (1986). Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Physical Review D, 34, 470–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G. C., Grassi, R., & Benatti, F. (1995). Describing the macroscopic world: closing the circle within the dynamical reduction program. Foundations of Physics, 25, 5–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G. C. (2011). Collapse theories. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2011 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-collapse/

  • Goldstein, S. (2013). Bohmian mechanics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2013 ed.). Available on plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/qm-bohm/

  • Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., & Zanghì, N. (2012). The quantum formalism and the GRW formalism. Journal of Statistical Physics, 149, 142–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kochen, S., & Specker, E. P. (1967). The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics, 17, 59–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2011). Quantum non-locality and relativity: Metaphysical intimations of modern physics (3rd ed.). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2012). Can the world be only wavefunction? In S. Saunders et al. (Eds.), Many Worlds?: Everett, quantum theory, and reality (Chap. 4). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2014). Critical study. D. Wallace, The emergent multiverse: Quantum Theory according to the Everett interpretation, Oxford University Press, 2012. Noûs, 48, 794–808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2019). Philosophy of physics. Quantum theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mermin, N. D. (1993). Hidden variables and the two theorems of John Bell. Reviews of Modern Physics, 65, 803–815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A., & Albert, D. (Eds.) (2013). The wave function: Essays on the metaphysics of quantum mechanics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norsen, T. (2005). Einstein’s boxes. American Journal of Physics, 73, 164–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norsen, T. (2014). Quantum solipsism and nonlocality. International Journal of Quantum Foundations (electronic journal). Available at www.ijqf.org/archives/1548

  • Norsen, T. (2017). Foundations of quantum mechanics: An exploration of the physical meaning of quantum theory. Cham: Springer International Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Struyve, W. (2010). Pilot-wave theory and quantum fields. Reports on Progress in Physics, 73, 106001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Towler, M. (2009). De Broglie–Bohm pilot-wave theory and the foundations of quantum mechanics. Lectures, available at www.tcm.phy.cam.ac.uk/~mdt26/

  • Tumulka, R. (2004). Understanding Bohmian mechanics — A dialogue. American Journal of Physics, 72, 1220–1226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tumulka, R. (2018). Paradoxes and primitive ontology in collapse theories of quantum mechanics. In S. Gao (Ed.), Collapse of the wave function (pp. 134–153). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaidman, L. (1998). On schizophrenic experiences of the neutron or why we should believe in the many-worlds interpretation of quantum theory. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 12, 245–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, A. (2012). de Broglie–Bohm pilot-wave theory: Many worlds in denial? In S. Saunders et al. (Eds.), Many Worlds?: Everett, quantum theory, and reality (pp. 476–509). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2003). Everett and structure. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 34, 87–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2007). Quantum probability from subjective likelihood: Improving on Deutsch’s proof of the probability rule. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38, 311–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank two referees for useful comments, Sheldon Goldstein and Tim Maudlin for many discussions on Bohmian mechanics and the many-worlds theories, and specially Valia Allori for illuminating exchanges on the topics discussed here.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jean Bricmont .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bricmont, J. (2022). Ψcat alive and Ψcat dead Are not Cats! Ontology and Statistics in “Realist” Versions of Quantum Mechanics. In: Allori, V. (eds) Quantum Mechanics and Fundamentality . Synthese Library, vol 460. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-99642-0_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics