Skip to main content

Are Euclid’s Diagrams ‘Representations’? On an Argument by Ken Manders

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Research in History and Philosophy of Mathematics

Abstract

In his well-known paper on Euclid’s geometry, Ken Manders sketches an argument against conceiving the diagrams of the Elements in ‘semantic’ terms, that is, against treating them as representations—resting his case on Euclid’s striking use of ‘impossible’ diagrams in some proofs by contradiction. This paper spells out, clarifies and assesses Manders’s argument, showing that it only succeeds against a particular semantic view of diagrams and can be evaded by adopting others, but arguing that Manders nevertheless makes a compelling case that semantic analyses ought to be relegated to a secondary role for the study of mathematical practices.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    ‘Artifacts in a practice that gives us a grip on life are sometimes thought of in semantic terms—say, as representing something in life. There is, of course, an age-old debate on how geometrical diagrams are to be treated in this regard.’ (Manders, 2008, 84).

  2. 2.

    Manders (2008, 84); my emphasis.

  3. 3.

    Manders (2008, 84).

  4. 4.

    See Heath (1908, II: 12) = Vitrac (1990, I: 399–400) = Heiberg (1883, I: 176–177).

  5. 5.

    A few elements of context about this choice are in order. As recently shown by Ken Saito, Byzantine manuscripts of Euclid—which, save for isolated fragments, are the oldest we have—typically display diagrams that differ significantly from those of modern editions, including critical ones. (For an introduction, see Saito and Sidoli, 2012, Saito, 2009, 817–825 or Saito, 2012—the latter discussing the very Proposition III.5 taken as an example here. For a fuller overview of diagrams in manuscript sources of the first books of Euclid’s Elements, see Saito, 2006, 2011.) The difference is of particular interest in the case of reductio proofs, as the manuscript diagrams are often much more blatantly ‘wrong’ or ‘impossible’ than those of modern editions. This is why I have chosen, in this paper, to reproduce the diagrams from ‘Codex B’, a 888 C.E. manuscript, which, though removed from Euclid himself by almost 1200 years, is one of the oldest still extant. (The letters standardly used to refer to manuscripts of the Elements go back to Heiberg’s authoritative nineteenth-century critical edition of the Greek text; for a list, see Heiberg, 1883, I: V–X or Saito, 2006, 95–96.)

  6. 6.

    Manders (2008, 85–86).

  7. 7.

    For a survey of the role of Euclid’s diagrams in his proofs, see for instance Netz (1999, 175–182).

  8. 8.

    Heath (1908, I: 241–242) = Vitrac (1990, I: 194–195) = Heiberg (1883, I: 10–13).

  9. 9.

    In general, Manders calls ‘co-exact’ those properties that can be read off from diagrams in Euclid; as for Panza, the fact that diagrams of Euclidean geometry allow attributing some of their properties to the corresponding geometrical objects is what he calls their ‘local role’, and those properties that geometrical objects are taken to inherit from their diagrammatic representations are what he calls ‘diagrammatic attributes’ (see Panza 2012, in part. 72–82).

  10. 10.

    Trans. from Heath (1908, II: 12), where (for consistency with the Codex B diagram) I have replaced Heath’s Roman letters with Heiberg’s Greek letters. See also Vitrac (1990, I: 400) = Heiberg (1883, I: 177).

  11. 11.

    Manders (2008, 85); KM’s emphasis. The claims ‘in force’ within a reductio context refer to the hypotheses under which one arrives at a contradiction; the terminology here comes from an analogy with natural deduction, in which inferences are relative to a context defined by the undischarged assumptions under which it is made.

  12. 12.

    Heath (1908, II: 8–9) = Vitrac (1990, I: 394–395) = Heiberg (1883, I: 168–171).

  13. 13.

    Heath (1908, II: 23–24) = Vitrac (1990, I: 412–413) = Heiberg (1883, I: 192–195).

  14. 14.

    As Rabouin (2015, 115–118, 126–131) shows, the kinds of distortions that reductio proofs require easily produce incorrect results in other situations: some form of selective control over diagram distortions is clearly going on; see Manders (2008, 109–118) for further discussion.

  15. 15.

    Manders (2008, 86).

  16. 16.

    Manders (1996, 391). (This quotes comes, not from his most famous 2008 paper, but from a previous publication on the topic; his view on this did not change, however.)

  17. 17.

    See, in particular, the collective volume Allwein and Barwise (1996).

  18. 18.

    The original version of Mumma’s system did not define a formal semantics for its diagrams, but this is possible and is done in Mumma (2019).

  19. 19.

    As a matter of fact, the propositions from Euclid’s arithmetical books also contain diagrams of sorts, which represent by way of lines the numbers discussed in the text; but, in contrast to the geometrical case, these diagrams do not play much of a role in proofs. See, e.g., Mueller (1981, 67).

  20. 20.

    Heath (1908, II: 323–324) = Vitrac (1990, II: 328) = Heiberg (1883, II: 234–237). In modern terms, if two integers A and B are such that there are no smaller integers C and D such that \(\frac {C}{D} = \frac {A}{B}\), then A and B are relatively prime.

  21. 21.

    Manders (2008, 86).

References

  • Allwein G, Barwise J (ed) (1996) Logical Reasoning with Diagrams. OUP

    Google Scholar 

  • Vitrac B (ed) (1990–2001) Euclide d’Alexandrie, Les Éléments, 3 vol. PUF, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath T L (ed) (1908) The Thirteen Books of Euclid’s Elements, 3 vol. CUP

    Google Scholar 

  • Heiberg J L (ed) (1883–1888) Euclidis Elementa, 5 vol. Teubner, Leipzig

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Manders K (1996) Diagram contents and representational granularity. In: Seligman J, Westerståhl D (ed) Logic, Language and Computation, 389–404. CSLI Publications, Stanford

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Manders K (2008) The Euclidean Diagram (1995). In: Mancosu P (ed) The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice, 80–133. OUP

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller N (2007) Euclid and His Twentieth Century Rivals. CSLI Publications, Stanford

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Mueller I (1981) Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure in Euclid’s Elements. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumma, J (2006) Intuition Formalized. PhD thesis, Carnegie Mellon University. http://johnmumma.org/Writings_files/Thesis.pdf

  • Mumma, J (2019) The Eu approach to formalizing Euclid. Notre-Dame J Form Log 60(3)

    Google Scholar 

  • Netz, R (1999) The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics. CUP

    Google Scholar 

  • Panza, M (2012) The twofold role of diagrams in Euclid’s plane geometry. Synthese 186(1):55–102

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Rabouin, D (2015) Proclus’ Conception of Geometric Space and Its Actuality. In: De Risi V (ed) Mathematizing Space, 105–142. Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Saito K (2006) A preliminary study in the critical assessment of diagrams in Greek mathematical works. SCIAMVS 7:81–144

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Saito K (2009) Reading Ancient Greek Mathematics. In: Robson E, Stedall J (ed) The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics, 801–826. OUP

    Google Scholar 

  • Saito K (2011) The diagrams of book II and III of the Elements in Greek manuscripts. In: Saito K (ed) Diagrams in Greek Mathematical Texts, 39–80. http://greekmath.org/diagrams/Diagrams_in_Greek_Mathematical_Texts_Report_Ver_2_03_20110403.pdf

  • Saito K (2012) Traditions of the diagram, tradition of the text. Synthese 186(1):7–20

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Saito K and Sidoli N (2012) Diagrams and arguments in ancient Greek mathematics. In Chemla K (ed) The History of Mathematical Proof in Ancient Traditions, 135–162. CUP

    Google Scholar 

  • Shin S-J (1994) The Logical Status of Diagrams. CUP

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Without David Rabouin, who initially drew my attention to this issue and discussed it with me on numerous occasions, this paper would not exist. I would also like to thank Marco Panza, Jeremy Avigad, Ken Manders, and Dirk Schlimm for useful discussions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Waszek .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Waszek, D. (2022). Are Euclid’s Diagrams ‘Representations’? On an Argument by Ken Manders. In: Zack, M., Schlimm, D. (eds) Research in History and Philosophy of Mathematics. Annals of the Canadian Society for History and Philosophy of Mathematics/ Société canadienne d’histoire et de philosophie des mathématiques. Birkhäuser, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-95201-3_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics