Skip to main content

Demystifying Mysteries. How Metaphors and Analogies Extend the Reach of the Human Mind

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Metaphors and Analogies in Sciences and Humanities

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 453))

Abstract

Some philosophers have argued that, owing to our humble evolutionary origins, some mysteries of the universe will forever remain beyond our ken. But what exactly does it mean to say that humans are ‘cognitively closed’ to some parts of the universe, or that some problems will forever remain ‘mysteries’? First, we distinguish between representational access (the ability to develop accurate scientific representations of reality) and imaginative understanding (immediate, intuitive comprehension of those representations), as well as between different modalities of cognitive limitation. Next, we look at tried-and-tested strategies for overcoming our innate cognitive limitations. In particular, we consider how metaphors and analogies can extend the reach of the human mind, by allowing us to make sense of bizarre and counterintuitive things in terms of more familiar things. Finally, we argue that this collection of mind-extension devices is combinatorial and open-ended, and that therefore pronouncements about cognitive closure and about the limits of human inquiry are premature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This chapter is based on an earlier paper published in Biology & Philosophy: Boudry, M., Vlerick, M., & Edis, T. (2020). The end of science? On human cognitive limitations and how to overcome them. Biology & Philosophy, 35(1), 1–16.

  2. 2.

    To a large extent, the epistemic pessimism of the new mysterians recapitulates arguments developed by German naturphilosophen and Victorian scientists in the nineteenth century, in particular during the so-called Ignorabimusstreit (Tennant, 2007).

  3. 3.

    In our previous work (Vlerick and Boudry 2017) we called these predicaments, respectively, “representational closure” and “psychological closure”. We have now decided to opt for a slightly different terminology, because the adjective “psychological” was too broad for our purposes.

  4. 4.

    In his original formulation, McGinn wrote that “A type of mind M is cognitively closed with respect to a property P (or theory T) if and only if the concept-forming procedures at M’s disposal cannot extend to a grasp of P (or an understanding of T)?” (McGinn, 1989, p. 350). By adding these parenthetical asides, McGinn suggests some rough equivalence, or a mere terminological difference. But there is a crucial difference between the claim that we cannot form a representation of some property P, and the claim that we cannot understand or grasp the representation itself.

  5. 5.

    According to the “extended mind” hypothesis in philosophy of mind (Clark and Chalmers 1998), the human mind literally extends beyond the skin/skull boundary, encompassing notebooks, computer screens, maps, file drawers, and so forth. But one does not need to embrace this radical philosophical view to appreciate how artefacts “extend” the reach of our minds.

  6. 6.

    Letter to Robert Hooke, February 5, 1675: https://bit.ly/2hIzhIe

  7. 7.

    This thought experiment was earlier used in an essay for The Conversation (Boudry 2019).

  8. 8.

    It is curious that mysterians have not explored quantum mechanics as a possible example of a domain to which we are cognitively closed. This might perhaps be attributed to the fact that quantum mechanics is notoriously demanding, to the extent that even confidence about its status as a mystery might be hard to come by.

  9. 9.

    ΔxΔp ≥ ℏ/2 is really ΔxΔk ≥ ½ for waves in general, combined with the de Broglie relationship of p = ℏk.

  10. 10.

    In this respect, a more consistent (and radical) form of mysterianism can be found in Kriegel (2003), who maintains a strict second-order ignorance about the reasons for our sense of mystery.

Bibliography

  • Bao, L., & Redish, E. F. (2002). Understanding probabilistic interpretations of physical systems: A prerequisite to learning quantum physics. American Journal of Physics, 70(3), 210–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M. (2019). Human intelligence: Have we reached the limit of knowledge? The Conversation, October 11, 2019. bit.ly/32KodQ6

  • Boudry, M., & Pigliucci, M. (2013). The mismeasure of machine: Synthetic biology and the trouble with engineering metaphors. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44(4), 660–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M., & Pigliucci, M. (2016). Vindicating science – By bringing it down. In K. Rutten, S. Blancke, & R. Soetaert (Eds.), The culture of science: Scientific understanding & cultural representation (pp. 243–258). Purdue University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M., Vlerick, M., & Edis, T. (2020). The end of science? On human cognitive limitations and how to overcome them. Biology and Philosophy, 35(1), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, P., & Barrett, H. C. (2005). Domain specificity and intuitive ontology. In D. M. Buss (Ed.), The handbook of evolutionary psychology (pp. 96–118). Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, T. L. (2003). Making truth: Metaphor in science. University of Illinois press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1997). From evolutionary epistemology via selection theory to a sociology of scientific validity. Evolution and cognition, 3(1), 5–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S., & Spelke, E. (1994). Domain-specific knowledge and conceptual change. In L. Hirschfeld & S. A. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the mind domain specificity in cognition and culture. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1988). Language and problems of knowledge: The Managua lectures (Vol. 16). The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2000). New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2014). Science, mind, and limits of understanding. Paper presented at the The Science and Faith Foundation (STOQ). From https://chomsky.info/201401__/

  • Clark A and Chalmers D (1998) The extended mind. Analysis:7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Condit, C. M., Bates, B. R., Galloway, R., et al. (2002). Recipes or blueprints for our genes? How contexts selectively activate the multiple meanings of metaphors. Quarterly Journal of Speech, 88(3), 303–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H., & De Smedt, J. (2010a). Paley’s iPod. The cognitive basis of the design argument within natural theology. Zygon. Journal of Religion and Science, 45(3), 665–684. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9744.2010.01120.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H., & De Smedt, J. (2010b). Science as structured imagination. The Journal of Creative Behavior, 44(1), 29–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2009). Darwin’s “strange inversion of reasoning”. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 106(Supplement 1), 10061–10065.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2017). From bacteria to Bach and Back: The evolution of minds. Penguin Books, Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. (2017). The character of physical law. MIT press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. J. (1992). Consciousness reconsidered. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S. A. (2003). The essential child. Origins of essentialism in everyday thought. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S. A., & Rhodes, M. (2012). Two-thousand years of stasis: How psychological essentialism impedes evolutionary understanding. In K. S. Rosengren, S. K. Brem, M. E. Evans, & G. M. Sinatra (Eds.), Evolution challenges. Integrating research and practice in teaching and learning about evolution (pp. 3–21). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2002). Scientific cognition as distributed cognition. In P. Carruthers, S. P. Stich, & M. Siegal (Eds.), The cognitive basis of science (pp. 285–299). Cambridge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, S. (1984). Understanding relativity.Birkhauser Verlag

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1999). Knowledge in a social world. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (1999). Holism and nonseparability in physics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/physics-holism/

  • Henrich, J. (2015). The secret of our success: How culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D., & Rosset, E. (2009). The human function compunction: Teleological explanation in adults. Cognition, 111(1), 138–143. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2009.01.001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2003). The new mysterianism and the thesis of cognitive closure. Acta Analytica, 18(30–31), 177–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2015). The social dimensions of scientific knowledge. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, R. N. (2000). The naturalness of religion and the unnaturalness of science. In F. Keil & R. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 61–85). Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1989). Can we solve the Mind--Body problem? Mind, 98(391), 349–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1993). Problems in philosophy: The limits of inquiry. Blackwell Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1994). The problem of philosophy. Philosophical Studies, 76(2), 133–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (2000). The mysterious flame: Conscious minds in a material world. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mermin, N. D. (2009). It’s about time: Understanding Einstein’s relativity. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. (2001). Molecular metaphors: The gene in popular discourse. Nature Reviews. Genetics, 2(7), 555–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I., & Cohen, I. B. (2004). A treatise of the system of the world. Courier Corporation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, M. J. (2009). The relationship between evolutionary biology and religion. Evolution, 63(7), 1934–1941. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1558-5646.2009.00714.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (2006). Epistemetrics. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, N. (2004). God, the devil, and Darwin : A critique of intelligent design theory. Oxford university press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Singh, C., Belloni, M., et al. (2006). Improving students’ understanding of quantum mechanics. Physics Today, 59(8), 43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, H. (2003). Beyond the postmodern mind: The place of meaning in a global civilization. Quest Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. P. (1990). The fragmentation of reason : Preface to a pragmatic theory of cognitive evaluation. MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tennant, N. (2007). Mind, mathematics and the Ignorabimusstreit. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 15(4), 745–773.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2012). The cognitive science of science: Explanation, discovery, and conceptual change. Mit Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2001). Cultural transmission a view from chimpanzees and human infants. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 32(2), 135–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vlerick, M., & Boudry, M. (2017). Psychological closure does not entail cognitive closure. Dialectia, 71(1), 101–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, L. (1992). The unnatural nature of science. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, L., & Skinner, D. (1993). The triumph of the embryo. Oxford university press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zachos, C. K., Fairlie, D. B., et al. (2005). Quantum mechanics in phase space: An overview with selected papers. World Scientific.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Manvir Singh, Daniel Dennett, Stefaan Blancke and several participants during a seminar at the Centre for Logic and Philosophy of Science at Leuven University, for offering useful feedback on earlier versions of our argument.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Boudry, M., Vlerick, M., Edis, T. (2022). Demystifying Mysteries. How Metaphors and Analogies Extend the Reach of the Human Mind. In: Wuppuluri, S., Grayling, A.C. (eds) Metaphors and Analogies in Sciences and Humanities. Synthese Library, vol 453. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-90688-7_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics