Skip to main content

Hofweber’s Nominalist Naturalism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Objects, Structures, and Logics

Abstract

In this paper, we outline and critically evaluate Thomas Hofweber’s solution to a semantic puzzle he calls Frege’s Other Puzzle. After sketching the Puzzle and two traditional responses to it—the Substantival Strategy and the Adjectival Strategy—we outline Hofweber’s proposed version of Adjectivalism. We argue that two key components—the syntactic and semantic components—of Hofweber’s analysis both suffer from serious empirical difficulties. Ultimately, this suggests that an altogether different solution to Frege’s Other Puzzle is required.

This publication was funded by LMU Munich’s Institutional Strategy LMU excellent within the framework of the German Excellence Initiative.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This follows a referentiality test due originally to Kratzer and Heim (1998).

  2. 2.

    The label “Adjectivalism” is due to Dummett (1991). It is somewhat unfortunate, however, because it suggests that what Frege calls “attributive uses” like (1a) must be adjectives. However, the intended view is that “attributive uses” are non-referential expressions, and this is consistent with ‘four’ in (1a) being an adjective or a determiner. Despite this, we follow the literature in retaining the label “Adjectivalism”.

  3. 3.

    (17) is in fact the denotation of ‘four’ assumed by Breheny (2008). In GQT, cardinal determiners are actually given lower-bounded truth conditions, so that ‘four’ denotes a relation between sets whose intersection has a cardinality of at least four:

    (i)

    [[four]] = {<S,S’>: S,S’ ⊆ U and |S ∩ S| ≥ 4}

    The reason for adopting a two-sided analysis instead will become apparent in the next section, when we consider paraphrases of basic arithmetic equations like ‘three and two is five’.

  4. 4.

    See Landman (2003).

  5. 5.

    The same applies to Wright (1983) and Hale (1987).

  6. 6.

    See e.g. Balcerak-Jackson (2013) and Snyder (2017).

  7. 7.

    The details are complex and beyond the scope of a single paper. But see Hofweber (2016).

  8. 8.

    Roughly, fictionalism is the view that numerals in arithmetic discourse genuinely have the function of naming numbers, but since numbers do not exist, all arithmetic discourse is either false or else involves widespread presupposition failure. See e.g. Hodes (1984), Yablo (2005), and Leng (2010).

  9. 9.

    See e.g. Kennedy and McNally (2010), McNally (2011), and McNally and de Swart (2011).

  10. 10.

    See Snyder (2017).

  11. 11.

    See Moltmann (2013), Felka (2014), and Snyder (2017).

  12. 12.

    See Mikkelsen (2005).

  13. 13.

    See Schlenker (2003).

  14. 14.

    See Partee (1986b) and Romero (2005).

  15. 15.

    To a first approximation, intransitive counting consists in reciting the numerals in their canonical order –“1, 2, 3,...” In contrast, transitive counting consists in the counting of things. That is, when transitively counting we use the numerals to answer ‘how many’-questions, roughly by establishing a one-to-one correspondence between an initial segment of those numerals and a collection of objects being counted.

  16. 16.

    See especially Partee (1986a).

  17. 17.

    See Snyder et al. (2021).

  18. 18.

    This presupposes type-shifting. See e.g. Rothstein (2017), and Snyder (2017).

  19. 19.

    Cf. Geurts (2006) and Rothstein (2013).

  20. 20.

    See Snyder (2017).

  21. 21.

    For one thing, unlike all prototypical determiners, ‘many’ has a comparative and superlative form – ‘more’ and ‘most’, respectively – and is gradable – cf. ‘very/so/how many’.

  22. 22.

    In fact, the only counterexample we are aware of, which happens to be directly informed by, and formulated partially in response to, Hofweber (2005), is Ionin and Matushansky (2006). Incidentally, this also happens to be the target of the semantic arguments mentioned in Sect. 3.4.3.

  23. 23.

    See Barwise and Cooper (1981).

  24. 24.

    An anonymous reviewer observes that the same argument would extend to sets, which should be just as objectionable from a nominalist perspective, but that this kind of commitment might be avoided by appealing to a pluralist metalanguage, perhaps following Boolos (1985). As far as we know, whether all of GQT can be recovered within a pluralist metalanguage is an open question, though McKay (2006) makes progress in this direction. Even so, the question would remain as to whether an empirically adequate, nominalist-friendly pluralist semantics for number expressions could be formulated, something which some of us have cast doubt on in other work (e.g Snyder and Shapiro 2021).

  25. 25.

    See e.g. Scontras (2014) for measure phrases, and Chierchia (1998) for bare nouns.

  26. 26.

    Contra Moltmann (2013).

References

  • Abels, K. 2017. Displacement in syntax. In Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics, ed. M. Aronoff. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balcerak-Jackson, B. 2013. Defusing easy arguments for numbers. Linguistics and Philosophy 36: 447–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., and R. Cooper. 1981. Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy 1: 413–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. 1965. What numbers could not be. The Philosophical Review 74: 47–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. 1985. Nominalist platonism. The Philosophical Review 94: 327–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breheny, R. 2008. A new look at the semantics and pragmatics of numerically quantified noun phrases. Journal of Semantics 25: 93–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. 2007. Number words and ontological commitment. Philosophical Quarterly 57: 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G. 1998. Reference to kinds across language. Natural Language Semantics 6: 339–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. 1991. Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felka, K. 2014. Number words and reference to numbers. Philosophical Studies 168: 261–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1884. Grundlagen der Arithmetik.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B. 2006. Take ‘five’. In Non-Definiteness and Plurality, ed. S. Vogleer and L. Tasmowski, 311–329. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. 1987. Abstract Objects. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higgins, R.F. 1973. The Pseudo-cleft Construction in English, Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodes, H. 1984. Logicism and the ontological commitments of arithmetic. The Journal of Philosophy 81: 123–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber, T. 2005. Number determiners, numbers, and arithmetic. The Philosophical Review 114: 179–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Innocent statements and their metaphysically loaded counterparts. Philosopher’s Imprint 7: 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Extraction, displacement, and focus. Linguistics and Philosophy 37: 263–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics. Oxford University Press, New York.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. 1972. On the Semantic Properties of Logical Operators. PhD thesis, University of California, Los Angeles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ionin, T., and O. Matushansky. 2006. The composition of complex cardinals. Journal of Semantics 23: 315–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C. 2015. A “de-Fregean” semantics (and neo-Gricean pragmatics) for modified and unmodified numerals. Semantics and Pragmatics 10: 1–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C., and L. McNally. 2010. Color, context, and compositionality. Synthese 174: 79–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A., and I. Heim. 1998. Semantics in Generative Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. 1990. Boolean and non-boolean and. In Papers from the Second Symposium on Logic and Language, ed. L. Kalman and L. Polos. Budapest: Akademmiai Kiado.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. 1999. At least some determiners aren’t determiners. In The Semantics/Pragmatics Interface from Different Points of View, 1, 257–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. 2003. Predicate-argument mismatches and the adjectival theory of indefinites. In NP to DP, ed. M. Coene and Y. D’hulst. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Indefinites and the Type of Sets. Malden: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leng, M. 2010. Mathematics and Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Link, G. 1983. The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice-theoretical approach. In Formal Semantics: The Essential Readings, ed. P. Portner and B. Partee, 127–146. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, T. 2006. Plural Predication. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McNally, L. 2011. Color terms: A case study in natural language ontology. In Workshop on the Syntax and Semantics of Nounhood and Adjectivehood. Barcelona.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNally, L., and H. de Swart. 2011. Inflection and derivation: How adjectives and nouns refer to abstract objects. In Proceedings of the 18th Amsterdam Colloquium, 425–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelsen, L. 2005. Copular Clauses: Specification, Predication, and Equation. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. 2013. Reference to numbers in natural language. Philosophical Studies 162: 499–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. 1986a. Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In Studies in Discourse Representation Theory and the Theory of Generalized Quantifiers, ed. J. Groenendijk, D. de Jongh, and M. Stokhof. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986b. Ambiguous pseudoclefts with unambiguous be. In Proceedings of NELS 16, ed. S. Berman, J. Choe, and J. McDonough, 354–366. Amherst: GLSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rett, J. 2008. Degree Modification in Natural Language, PhD dissertation, Rutgers University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romero, M. 2005. Concealed questions and specificational subjects. Linguistics and Philosophy 28: 687–737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, S. 2013. A Fregean semantics for number words. In Proceedings of the 19th Amsterdam Colloquium, 179–186. Amsterdam: Universiteit van Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Semantics for Counting and Measuring. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, P. 2003. Clausal equations. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 21: 157–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scontras, G. 2014. The semantics of measurement. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. 1991. Foundations Without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-Order Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, E. 2017. Numbers and cardinalities: What’s really wrong with the easy argument? Linguistics and Philosophy 40: 373–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. Counting, measuring, and the fractional cardinalities puzzle. Linguistics and Philosophy. 44: 513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, Eric, Richard Samuels, and Stewart Shapiro 2021. Resolving Frege’s other puzzle, Philosophia Mathematica, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, Eric and Stewart Shapiro. 2021. Groups, sets, and paradox. Linguistics and Philosophy, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solt, S. 2009. The Semantics of Adjectives of Quantity, PhD dissertation, City University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellwood, A. 2018. Structure preservation in comparatives. Semantics and Linguistic Theory 28: 78–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. 1983. Frege’s Conception of Numbers as Objects. Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. 2005. The myth of the seven. In Fictionalist Approaches to Metaphysics, ed. M. Kalderon, 90–115. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stewart Shapiro .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Snyder, E., Samuels, R., Shapiro, S. (2022). Hofweber’s Nominalist Naturalism. In: Oliveri, G., Ternullo, C., Boscolo, S. (eds) Objects, Structures, and Logics. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 339. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-84706-7_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics