Skip to main content

Abstract Generality, Simplicity, Forgetting, and Discovery

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Axiomatic Thinking II

Abstract

The paper contrasts two ways of generalizing and gives examples: probably most people think of examples like generalizing Cartesian coordinate geometry to differential manifolds. One kind of structure is replaced by another more complicated but more flexible kind. Call this articulating generalization as it articulates some general assumptions behind an earlier concept. On the other hand, by unifying generalization, I mean simply dropping some assumptions from an earlier concept or theorem. Hilbert, Noether, and Grothendieck were all known for highly non-trivial unifying generalizations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The very fruitfully simplifying work of Fields Medalist Peter Scholz might be an argument against this claim. The reader may want to explore that possibility.

  2. 2.

    The other candidate for his most influential generalization is his derived functor cohomology, which is sketched from the same viewpoint as this article in [14].

  3. 3.

    Existing historical data are too thin to support or refute this parable as a historical conjecture. For the extant Greek sources on this theorem, see [7, vol. 1, p. 252ff.].

  4. 4.

    For a fuller treatment, see [13].

  5. 5.

    A concise history from this viewpoint is [4, pp. 21–26].

  6. 6.

    A quick introduction is in [11].

  7. 7.

    [9, p. 13] correctly says “Noether’s proofs [...] were (and remain) startling in their simplicity”. Compare [15].

  8. 8.

    See, e.g. [19, Chap. 7].

  9. 9.

    The Weil conjectures are much discussed elsewhere. See [12] and references there.

  10. 10.

    Hilbert found it when he went to work replying to Gordan’s objections to Hilbert’s original non-constructive solution of Gordan’s problem.

  11. 11.

    This includes Emmy Noether’s school following van der Waerden, plus Weil and all the leading Parisian algebraic geometers, as documented in [12, p. 313ff.].

  12. 12.

    Pierre has explained some of the reasons behind this absence [1, p. 398].

References

  1. Cartier, P. (2001). A mad day’s work: from Grothendieck to Connes and Kontsevich. The evolution of concepts of space and symmetry. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 38:389–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Dedekind, R. (1996). Theory of Algebraic Integers. Cambridge University. Originally published in French 1877.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Deligne, P. (1998). Quelques idées maîtresses de l’œuvre de A. Grothendieck. In Matériaux pour l’Histoire des Mathématiques au \(XX^{\rm e}\) Siècle (Nice, 1996), pages 11–19. Soc. Math. France.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Eisenbud, D. (1995). Commutative Algebra. Springer-Verlag, New York.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  5. Grothendieck, A. (1985–1987). Récoltes et Semailles. Université des Sciences et Techniques du Languedoc, Montpellier. Published in several successive volumes.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Grothendieck, A. and Dieudonné, J. (1971). Éléments de Géométrie Algébrique I. Springer-Verlag.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Heath, T. (1956). The thirteen books of Euclid’s Elements translated from the text of Heiberg, with introduction and commentary. Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Hilbert, D. (1900). Mathematische Probleme. Göttinger Nachrichten, pages 253–97. Reprinted in many places in many languages.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Jacobson, N. (1983). Introduction. In Jacobson, N., editor, E. Noether: Gesammelte Abhandlungen, pages 12–26. Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Kobayashi, S. and Nomizu, K. (1996). Foundations of Differential Geometry, Volume 1. Wiley.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Mazur, B. (2008). Algebraic numbers. In Gowers, T., editor, Princeton Companion to Mathematics, pp. 315–331 Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. McLarty, C. (2007). The rising sea: Grothendieck on simplicity and generality I. In Gray, J. and Parshall, K., editors, Episodes in the History of Recent Algebra, pages pp. 301–26. American Mathematical Society.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. McLarty, C. (2012). Theology and its discontents: David Hilbert’s foundation myth for modern mathematics. In Doxiadis, A. and Mazur, B., editors, Mathematics and Narrative, pages 105–129. Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  14. McLarty, C. (2018a). Grothendieck’s unifying vision of geometry. In Kouneiher, J., editor, Foundations of Mathematics and Physics one Century After Hilbert, pages 107–27. Springer-Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  15. McLarty, C. (2018b). The two mathematical careers of Emmy Noether. In Beery, J., editor, Women in Mathematics: 100 Years and Counting, pages 231–52. Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Misner, C., John Archibald Wheeler, C., Misner, U., Thorne, K., Wheeler, J., Freeman, W., and Company (1973). Gravitation. W. H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Mumford, D. (1988). The Red Book of Varieties and Schemes. Springer-Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  18. Reid, M. (1990). Undergraduate Algebraic Geometry. Cambridge University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Reid, M. (1995). Undergraduate Commutative Algebra. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  20. Riemann, B. (1867). Über die Hypothesen welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen. Abhandlungen der Königlichen Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, 13:133–52. Originally an 1854 lecture, this is widely reprinted and translated, for example in M. Spivak 1979, A Comprehensive Introduction to Differential Geometry, Berkeley, Publish or Perish Inc, vol. II: 135–153.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Smith, K. et al. (2000). An Invitation to Algebraic Geometry. Springer-Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  22. Spivak, M. (1971). A Comprehensive Introduction to Differential Geometry. Publish or Perish.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: Naive Algebraic Geometry over the Integers

Appendix: Naive Algebraic Geometry over the Integers

Let \(y^2-x^3+x=0\) define a “curve” of integer points:

$$C_{\mathbb {Z}}\ =\ \{\langle x,y \rangle \in \mathbb {Z}\times \mathbb {Z}\ |\ y^2-x^3+x=0\}.$$

Efficient use of prime factorization, given below, shows \(C_{\mathbb {Z}}\) has exactly three points:

$$\begin{aligned} C_{\mathbb {Z}}\ =\ \{\langle -1,0 \rangle , \langle 0,0 \rangle , \langle 1,0 \rangle \}. \end{aligned}$$

All these points have \(y=0\) so the polynomials y and 0 give the same regular function on \(C_{\mathbb {Z}}\) by criterion VALUES. Yet their difference y is obviously not divisible by the defining polynomial \(y^2-x^3+x\) so they are not the same by criterion FACTORS. To study \(C_{\mathbb {Z}}\) by tools of algebraic geometry, we must restore the role of FACTORS.

There are two ways to do this: 1) find new kinds of points for the “curve” \(C_{\mathbb {Z}}\) so that the polynomials y and 0 do not agree at all these points or 2) give up the idea that a function is determined by its values at points. Scheme theory actually does both.

To keep the argument grounded in some mathematics, here is a proof that \(C_{\mathbb {Z}}\) has just the three integer points.

Theorem 6.1

The curve \(C_{\mathbb {Z}}\) has just three integer points: \(\langle -1,0 \rangle \), \(\langle 0,0 \rangle \), \(\langle 1,0\rangle \).

Proof

Setting \(y=0\) gives three trivial solutions to \(y^2=0=x^3-x\), namely:

$$\begin{aligned} x=0,\ y=0\quad \text {or}\quad x=1,\ y=0\quad \text {or}\quad x=-1,\ y=0. \end{aligned}$$

This follows from factoring \(x^3-x\) as \(x\cdot (x-1)\cdot (x+1)\).

There are no solutions with \(y\ne 0\). To see this, suppose \(x^3-x\) is a non-zero square. Then \(x\ne 0\) and \(x\ne \pm 1\). And notice a prime factor of x cannot also be a prime factor of \(x^2-1\). So, since their product \(x^3-x\) is a square, both x and \(x^2-1\) must be squares. (This is where the proof uses unique prime factorization of non-zero integers.) But then the successive integers \(x^2-1\) and \(x^2\) would both be squares. And this contradicts \(x\ne \pm 1\) since the only successive integer squares are 0, 1.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

McLarty, C. (2022). Abstract Generality, Simplicity, Forgetting, and Discovery. In: Ferreira, F., Kahle, R., Sommaruga, G. (eds) Axiomatic Thinking II. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-77799-9_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics