Skip to main content

Wolff on Monadology and “Materialisterey”

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Force of an Idea

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 50))

  • 360 Accesses

Abstract

Christian Wolff discusses the so-called three systems of mind–body interaction (which are actually five systems including materialist and idealist monism) at quite some length in the Psychologia rationalis, without arriving at a conclusion, however, that he himself considers satisfactory. He does support pre-established harmony eventually, but only as the lesser evil. In a similar vein, he officially endorses Leibnizian monadology but adds the caveat that it applies only to minds, thus in fact rejecting the monistic panpsychism that is characteristic at least of Leibniz’s mature metaphysics. The aim of this chapter is to disentangle some of the complexities of Wolff’s view of the mind–body problem and thus shed some light on what his view of it and of related metaphysical issues actually amounts to.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    A preliminary version of this chapter was presented at the conference “Christian Wolffs Deutsche Metaphysik/Christan Wolff’s German Metaphysics” at Martin-Luther-Universität Halle-Wittenberg. I would like to thank the participants of this conference for their helpful comments, as well as Eric Watkins for his detailed and thorough comments on a later draft.

  2. 2.

    See also Fabian (1925, pp. 34–40) who notes Wolff’s hesitation concerning the powers of simple substances and holds that Wolff eventually advances a form of dualism. On Wolff’s doctrine of soul and his relation to Leibniz compare also Blackwell (1961), Corr (1975) and École (1986).

  3. 3.

    Watkins would agree thus far, I take it that the main point of disagreement here is whether this is primarily an agnostic thesis about the ultimate constituents of the world, or an actual, positive claim about them.

  4. 4.

    Leduc (2018) argues that Wolff introduces the concept of element to designate the first constituents of bodies in the first place (i.e. without mental attributes at all) and mentions Leibniz just as one example of such a theory among others.

  5. 5.

    Wolff (1751/1983, §.583) makes it clear that the internal power of simple things is not to be confused with an inner motion, i.e. a kind of physical motion, as that would require real parts, which a simple thing obviously does not have.

  6. 6.

    I will analyze this peculiar argument in Sect. 7.3 in more detail.

  7. 7.

    For an overview of the discussions of Leibniz’s “idealism” or “panpsychism”, see Smith (2011, pp. 101–105).

  8. 8.

    I take this reference to More from Leduc (2018, p. 46).

  9. 9.

    On this, see Reid (2012, pp. 44–51), in particular p. 51.

  10. 10.

    Compare Leibniz’ Monadology (1714/1885, p. 609).

  11. 11.

    Wolff discusses various empirical cases of harmony between mind and body in the section on empirical psychology in Deutsche Metaphysik (Wolff, 1751/1983, §§.527–539).

  12. 12.

    This criticism of Malebranche is neither original (i.e. adopted from Leibniz) nor fair, because in Malebranche, God acts through natural laws and not by miraculous intervention (see Perler & Rudolph, 2000, pp. 229–234).

  13. 13.

    On this aspect, compare Wunderlich (2016) and Wunderlich (forthcoming). On Leibniz as a potential resource for materialism see also Wolfe (2014, pp. 96–99, in particular p. 97f.) on Leibnizian influences on Diderot and Montpellier vitalism.

  14. 14.

    A case in point would be John Toland (1670–1722) who appropriated and modified Leibnizian theorems into a partly Spinozistic, materialistic doctrine; compare, for instance, Leask (2012) and the literature quoted there.

  15. 15.

    For a detailed reconstruction of the contents of this pamphlet and its publication history, see Mulsow (2002) and Mulsow (2018, vol. 2, pp. 11–96). Bucher apparently discussed the manuscript with his teacher Johann Baptist Roeschel (1652–1712). It was found in Roeschel’s estate and then later published by an unknown editor (see Mulsow, 2018, vol. 2, pp. 27, 37f).

  16. 16.

    For details of the reception of Bucher’s pamphlet, see Mulsow (2018, vol. 2, pp. 73–77).

  17. 17.

    Compare, for instance, Lennon and Stainton (2008).

  18. 18.

    Compare Wolfe and van Esveld (2014).

  19. 19.

    Recent contributions to this debate are Stuart (2013) and Jolley (2015).

  20. 20.

    For this use of substance concepts, see Olson (1997, pp. 27–31). Thanks to Eric Watkins for pointing me to this problem.

References

  • Blackwell, R. (1961). Christian Wolff’s doctrine of the soul. Journal of the History of Ideas, 22(3), 339–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bucher, U. G. (1713). Zweyer Guten Freunde vertrauter Brief-Wechsel vom Wesen der Seelen. Peter von der Aa (forged publisher).

    Google Scholar 

  • Corr, C. (1975). Christian Wolff and Leibniz. Journal of the History of Ideas, 36(2), 241–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • École, J. (1986). Des différentes parties de la métaphysique selon Wolff. In W. Schneiders (Ed.), Christian Wolff 1679–1754 (pp. 121–128). Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabian, G. (1925). Beitrag zur Geschichte des Leib-Seele-Problems. Hermann Beyer und Söhne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jolley, N. (2015). Locke’s touchy subjects: Materialism and immortality. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leask, I. (2012). Unholy force: Toland’s Leibnizian ‘consummation’ of Spinozism. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 20(3), 499–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leduc, C. (2018). Sources of Wolff’s philosophy: Scholastics/Leibniz. In R. Theis & A. Aichele (Eds.), Handbuch Christian Wolff (pp. 35–53). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1885). Principia philosophiae, Seu Theses in gratiam Principis Eugenii &c. [Monadology]. In C. Gerhardt (Ed.), Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (Vol. 6, pp. 607–623). Weidmann. (Original work published 1714).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennon, T., & Stainton, R. (2008). The Achilles of rationalist psychology. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1975). An essay concerning human understanding. Clarendon Press. (Original work published 1690).

    Google Scholar 

  • Look, B. (2013). Simplicity of substance in Leibniz, Wolff and Baumgarten. Studia Leibnitiana, 45(2), 191–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorini, G. (2016). Receptions of Leibniz’s pre-established harmony. Wolff and Baumgarten. In M. Camposampiero, M. Geretto, & L. Perissinotto (Eds.), Theodicy and reason: Logic, metaphysics, and theology in Leibniz’s Essais de Théodicée (1710) (pp. 163–179). Edizioni Ca’ Foscari.

    Google Scholar 

  • Middell, K., & Neumann, H.-P. (Eds.) (2019). Briefwechsel zwischen Christian Wolff und Ernst Christoph von Manteuffel. 1738–1748 (3 Vols.). Olms.

    Google Scholar 

  • More, H. (1671). Enchiridion metaphysicum. Flesher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulsow, M. (2002). Säkularisierung der Seelenlehre? Biblizismus und Materialismus in Urban Gottfried Buchers Brief-Wechsel vom Wesen der Seelen (1713). In L. Danneberg, S. Pott, J. Schönert, & F. Vollhardt (Eds.), Säkularisierung in den Wissenschaften seit der frühen Neuzeit (Vol. 2, pp. 145–173). De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulsow, M. (2018). Radikale Frühaufklärung in Deutschland 1680–1720 (2 Vols.). Wallstein.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. T. (1997). The human animal. Personal identity without psychology. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perler, D., & Rudolph, U. (2000). Occasionalismus. Theorien der Kausalität im arabisch-islamischen und im europäischen Denken. Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, J. (2012). The metaphysics of Henry More. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. E. H. (2011). Divine machines. Leibniz and the sciences of life. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stuart, M. (2013). Locke’s metaphysics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, E. (2006). On the necessity and nature of simples: Leibniz, Wolff, Baumgarten, and the pre-critical Kant. Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, 3, 261–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, C. (2014). Materialism. In A. Garrett (Ed.), The Routledge companion to 18th century philosophy (pp. 91–118). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, C., & van Esveld, M. (2014). The material soul: Strategies for naturalising the soul in an early modern Epicurean context. In D. Kambaskovic (Ed.), Conjunctions of mind, soul and body from Plato to the enlightenment (pp. 371–421). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, C. (1724). Der vernünfftigen Gedancken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt, anderer Theil, bestehend in ausführlichen Anmerkungen. Andreae.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, C. (1977a). Philosophia prima, sive Ontologia, methodo scientifica pertractata, qua omnis cognitiones humanae principia continentur. In J. École (Ed.), Christian Wolff: Gesammelte Werke (Prima philosophia sive Ontologia) (Vol. 3, Pt. II, 2nd ed.). Olms. (Original work published 1736).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, C. (1977b). Cosmologia generalis, methodo scientifica pertractata, qua ad solidam, inprimis die atque naturae, cognitionem via sternitur. In J. École (Ed.), Christian Wolff: Gesammelte Werke (Cosmologia generalis) (Vol. 4, Pt. II). Olms. (Original work published 1737).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, C. (1983). Vernünfftige Gedancken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt. In C. Corr (Ed.), Christian Wolff: Gesammelte Werke (Deutsche Metaphysik) (Vol. 2, Pt. I, 11th ed.). Olms. (Original work published 1751).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, C. (1994). Psychologia rationalis, methodo scientifica pertractata, qua ea, quae de anima humana indubia experientiae fide innotescunt, per essentiam et naturam animae explicantur, et ad intimiorem naturae ejusque autoris cognitionem profutura proponuntur. In J. École (Ed.), Christian Wolff: Gesammelte Werke (Psychologia rationalis) (Vol. 6, Pt. II, 2nd ed.). Olms. (Original work published 1740).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wunderlich, F. (2016). Varieties of early modern materialism. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 24(5), 797–813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wunderlich, F. (forthcoming). Materialism. In D. Jalobeanu & C. Wolfe (Eds.), Encyclopedia of early modern philosophy and sciences. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yolton, J. (1983). Thinking matter: Materialism in eighteenth-century Britain. University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Falk Wunderlich .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Wunderlich, F. (2021). Wolff on Monadology and “Materialisterey”. In: Araujo, S.d.F., Pereira, T.C.R., Sturm, T. (eds) The Force of an Idea. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 50. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-74435-9_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics