Skip to main content

Ethos and Moral Education: Critical Comments on Virtue Ethics and Virtue Education

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The International Handbook of Teacher Ethos

Abstract

This chapter is about one single question: What reasons could there be to make use of the concept of “ethos” in a pedagogical context? What difficulties would we encounter? And what would we gain with it? Ethos has two meanings: (a) a collective one in the sense of the community spirit and the generally accepted norms in a group or an institution; (b) an individual one, as the modes of behaviour of a person considered to be virtuous. Ethos in the collective sense has in school-research proofed to be the central trait that turns a school into a good school. Virtue education respectively Character education, however, must be regarded as a failure for moral-philosophical and for empirical reasons. Virtues do not help when it comes to the question of what we should do in a particular situation, and virtue education cannot begin until the question of the right action has already been answered. However, also an education based solely on action and aimed at promoting moral judgment is in turn insufficient. It is dependent on a lived-in collective ethos and must itself have such an ethos as its goal. The model for this is still Kohlberg’s just-community approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Aristoteles, Eth. Nic. 1103 a 32ff.

  2. 2.

    cf. Cicero, De orat. II, 201

  3. 3.

    In particular, the professional ethos of teachers has attracted attention in recent pedagogical research. (cf. Oser, 1998)

  4. 4.

    See, for example, the relevant publications of Fend (1977); (1980), S. 372 ff.; (1998), S. 202.

  5. 5.

    v. Hentig, H. in: Rutter (1980), S. 23.

  6. 6.

    Cf. Hügli (2004), Sp. 603–605

  7. 7.

    Benner u.a. (1978), S. VIII f.

  8. 8.

    Brumlik (2002).

  9. 9.

    cf. for example Slote (2001), Dawall (2003), Swanton (2003), Taylor (2002), Gill (2005)

  10. 10.

    The anthology by Klaus Peter Rippe and Peter Schaber (1998) provides a good insight into this debate.

  11. 11.

    Schleiermacher (1957), S. 428

  12. 12.

    A helpful phenomenological approach to the concept of virtue as Haltung is still Bollnow (1958). From the language-analytical point of view von Wright (1963), pp. 136–154

  13. 13.

    This distinction runs along the line drawn by G. Ryle (1949), p. 42, with his distinction between “habits” and “intelligent capacities”.

  14. 14.

    Aristoteles, Eth. Nic. 1106 b 36–1107 b 3.

  15. 15.

    Thus, if Aristotle says about justice that within the rights of a polis (to politikon dikaion) there is not only a conventional (nomikon), but also a “natural” (physikon) part, which “has the same authority everywhere and does not depend on the opinion of the people” (Eth. Nic. 1134 b 18–20).

  16. 16.

    Aristoteles, Eth. Nic. 1105 b 9–18

  17. 17.

    Here Philippa Foot claims that good virtue in itself can turn into something bad in certain persons, much like a remedy that under certain circumstances can be poison (Foot (1978), pp. 16–18).

  18. 18.

    Here lies the notorious weak point not only with the Aristotelian (see Aristotle, Eth., Nic., 1105 b 5–7), but also with every other virtue ethic. (Cf. Horster (2005), p. 649)

  19. 19.

    A way out might be to attribute to the virtues not an external, but an internal, a “spiritual” action, as Plato seems to do with respect to the righteousness of the soul as an internal balance of the soul-parts. The unsolved problem is merely: How do we recognize – be it from the outside or the inside perspective – the correctness of these inner actions. See also on this problem Louden (1998). Also, more in the text.

  20. 20.

    Kant (1907), S. 23, Anm. 2

  21. 21.

    a.O. S. 24, Anm.

  22. 22.

    Kant (1903), A 551, B 579, Note. Kant meets here with the equally decided skepticism of Thomas Aquinas: “The motions of the interior, however, which remain hidden, are not subject to the judgment of man, but only the outer actions that appear visibly. And yet to complete the virtues it is required that man ought to be right in both kinds of actions.” (Thomas v. Aquin, Summa Theologica I–II, q.91, a. 4)

  23. 23.

    In order to be able to secure this hypothesis, which is not further substantiated here for reasons of space, a more detailed discussion of further possible alternatives would be required, in particular the Value Clarification Approach, which emerged from the “Romantic educational philosophy” and its psychological theories (see the overview in Hügli (2004), Sp. 602–605). The weakness of all these programs is their inherent ethical relativism, which is morally untenable and in the way of any meaningful action orientation.

  24. 24.

    See, for example, the knowledgeable study by Lutz Koch (2003)

  25. 25.

    On the problem of a teacher training aimed at teachers’ virtues, cf. Hügli (1999), S. 132–138.

  26. 26.

    See for examlpe Gertrud Nunner-Winkler (1998)

  27. 27.

    A good exposition of this dilemma, related to Kohlberg’s program of development of moral judgment, is given by Peters (1981)

  28. 28.

    Rousseau, for example, with his idealization of ancient Sparta, or Hegel, who – well Aristotelian – sees the best path of “pedagogy” as the “art of making people moral”, in making them “citizens of a state of good laws.”, i.e. to insert them into the moral substantiality of “a world of the objective mind”, and thus to ensure that “this spiritual (Geistige)” becomes “habitual” in them (Hegel (1928), § 153, S. 303, § 151, supplement, S. 302.)

  29. 29.

    Habermas (1971), S. 107–126.

  30. 30.

    v. Hentig (1993), S. 224.

  31. 31.

    cf. Hare (1981), pp. 107–116.

  32. 32.

    Cf. in an elaborate form Hare (l981), p. 44–64.

  33. 33.

    However, such internalized rules are nothing other than what in the old tradition were called virtues: To be just or fair is to follow the principle of justice or fairness (see Peters (1981), p. 313).

  34. 34.

    Kohlberg (1987), S. 40.

References

  • Benner, D., Brüggen, F., Butterhof, H.-W., von Hentig, H., & Kemper, H. (1978). Entgegnungen zum Bonner Forum ‘Mut zur Erziehung’. Urban& Schwarzenberg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bollnow, F. O. (1958). Wesen und Wandel der Tugenden. Ullstein.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brumlik, M. (2002). Bildung und Glück: Versuch einer Theorie der Tugenden. Philo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derwall, S. (Ed.). (2003). Virtue ethics. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fend, H. (1977). Schulklima. Soziale Einflussprozesse in der Schule. Beltz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fend, H. (1980). Theorie der Schule. Urban & Schwarzenberg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fend, H. (1998). Qualität im Bildungswesen. Schulforschung zu Systembedingungen, Schulprofilen und Lehrerleistung. Juventa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1978). Virtues and vices. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, C. (2005). Virtue, norms, and objectivity. Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1971). Philosophisch-politische profile. Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking. Its levels, method and point. Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, H., & May, M. A. (1928). Studies in the nature of character. Vol.1: Studies in deceit. Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, H., May, M. A., & Maller, J. R. (1929). Studies in the nature of character. Vol. 2: Studies in service and self-control. Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, H., May, M. A., & Shuttleworth, F. K. (1930). Studies in the nature of character. Vol. 3: Studies in the organization of character. Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1928). Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts (1821). Jub. Ausg. hg. H. Glockner, Bd. 7, Stuttgart: Fromann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horster, D. (2005). Schwachstellen der Tugendethik. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 4, 647–650.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hügli, A. (1999). Philosophie und Pädagogik. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hügli, A. (2004). Art. „Werterziehung“. In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, Bd. 12, Sp. 591–609). Basel: Schwabe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1903). Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Akad. Ausg. Bd. 4, S. 1–252. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1907). Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft. Akad. Ausg. Bd. 6, S. 1–202. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koch, L. (2003). Kants ethische Didaktik. Ergon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1987). Moralische Entwicklung und demokratische Erziehung. In G. Lind, und, J. Raschert (Hg.): Moralische Urteilsfähigkeit. Eine Auseinandersetzung mit L. Kohlberg. S. 25–43. Weinheim und Basel: Beltz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Louden, R.B. (1998). Einige Laster der Tugendethik. In K. P. Rippe, P. Schaber (Hg.) (1998): Tugendethik. S. 185–212. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunner-Winkler, G. (1998). Zum Verständnis von Moral-Entwicklungen in der Kindheit. In F. E. Weinert (Hg.): Entwicklung im Kindesalter. S. 133–152. Weinheim: Beltz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oser, F. (1998). Ethos – die Vermenschlichung des Erfolgs. Zur Psychologie der Berufsmoral von Lehrpersonen. Leske & Budrich.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R. S. (1981). Moral development and moral education. G. Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rippe, K.P., & Schaber, P. (Hg.) (1998). Tugendethik. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutter, M. u. a. (1980). Fünzehntausend Stunden. Schulen und ihre Wirkung auf die Kinder. Weinheim/Basel: Beltz. (Englisch (1979): Fifteen thousand hours: Secondary schools and their effects on children. London: Open Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schleiermacher, Fr. D. E. (1957). Pädagogische Schriften. Hg. E. Weniger & Th. Schulze. Bd. 1. Düsseldorf/München: Küpper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (2001). Morals from motives. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swanton, C. (2003). Virtue ethics. A pluralistic view. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, R. (2002). Virtue ethics. Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urmson, J. O. (1953). The interpretation of the moral philosophy of J.S. Mill. The Philosophical Quarterly, 3, 33–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Hentig, H. (1993). Die Schule neu denken. Carl Hanser.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H. (1963). The varieties of goodness. Routledge and Kegan.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anton Hügli .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hügli, A. (2021). Ethos and Moral Education: Critical Comments on Virtue Ethics and Virtue Education. In: Oser, F., Heinrichs, K., Bauer, J., Lovat, T. (eds) The International Handbook of Teacher Ethos. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-73644-6_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-73644-6_7

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-73643-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-73644-6

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics