Skip to main content

Consciousness: Philosophy’s Great White Whale

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Mind-Technology Problem

Part of the book series: Studies in Brain and Mind ((SIBM,volume 18))

  • 660 Accesses

Abstract

On the assumption that phenomenal consciousness (the what-it-is-like) is real, and ruling out Cartesian isolation from the non-mental world, we have two choices for its introduction: either it comes about in the course of the development of the non-conscious realm or it was there from the beginning. The latter comprises versions of panpsychism, a recently trending view in some quarters. In their view the former are broadly taken to be versions of emergentism, embracing even non-eliminatiivist materialisms. After producing what seem to me to be powerful objections to panpsychism, I defend emergentism against pansychist attacks on it. As I explain, my version is also dualist. Finally, with respect to both outlooks I briefly review the prospects of a rapidly advancing AI for expanding (or replacing!) the current population of natural mental subjects.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    My thanks to Phil Atkins for bringing this to my attention.

  2. 2.

    See Seager and Allen-Hermanson (2010) and Van Gulick (2001). (In Philip Goff’s substantial revision of the Seagar and Allen-Hermanson entry, this dichotomy is no longer part of the exposition, but it is not repudiated, and panpsychists widely regard the options this way although their titles for the non-panpsychist alternative may vary.)

  3. 3.

    And not them alone. This is a staple of non-radical emergentists of every stripe. For example, (non-monist) Colin McGinn writes “It is implausible to take these correlations as ultimate and inexplicable facts, as simply brute. And we do not want to acknowledge radical emergence for the conscious with respect to the cerebral.. ..” (McGinn 1989, p. 353).

  4. 4.

    (b) marks yet another difference from Cartesianism.

  5. 5.

    The eventual combined law PV/T = k, with T as temperature in kelvins and k a constant of units of energy divided by temperature.

  6. 6.

    Questions have been raised about each of these ways of characterizing the things themselves. For present purposes as long as we agree that there are also non-relational properties/things, we can bypass disputes over the best way to explicate intrinsicality.

  7. 7.

    As George Theiner and Mark Bickhard brought to my attention, this isn’t a problem for process theories. But that view opens up a host of much wider issues that aren’t factors in the views currently under consideration.

  8. 8.

    On the other hand, Galen Strawson (2008) holds that this makes CAs themselves material. For more on this see below.

  9. 9.

    Cf. Carl Hempel (1965, p. 260).

  10. 10.

    This notion comes out of Chalmers’s two dimensional semantics, demanding that the designator be rigid both epistemically and metaphysically. We need not say more about that refinement. I mention it here simply to bring out the epistemic – that is, a priori – part of the appeal to a priori entailment. It plays no further role in the points under consideration.

  11. 11.

    None of this speaks against (or for) monist proposals that are not attempts to support (ii).

  12. 12.

    However, in this section’s last two paragraphs I shall comment briefly on the respective debating positions of emergentism’s physicalist and dualist forms.

  13. 13.

    This term is employed by the hesitant panpsychist William Seager (1995).

  14. 14.

    Widespread disparagement of brute relations is discussed in Vision (2018). Much of the discussion of the next few pages summarizes that more detailed treatment.

  15. 15.

    Nothing novel here. In a celebrated passage John Tyndall wrote “Granted that a definite thought and a definite molecular action in the brain occur simultaneously: we do not possess the intellectual organ, nor apparently any rudiment of the organ, which would enable us to pass, by a process of reasoning, from one to the other” (1897, p. 87).

  16. 16.

    Cf. Chomsky’s (1968, p. 98) prescient observation that we call any explanation “physical” just because it has become established in the domain. For a move of that sort see, e.g., Strawson (2008).

  17. 17.

    Turing (1950) may be suggesting either that behavior delivers the answer or that a less ambitious question about behavior should replace it with the only real (or intelligible) one. (I take the original question to be kosher, but don’t try to answer it behaviorally.) This doesn’t prevent Turing from hypothesizing that conscious experience is only a matter of storage capacity, which would make him an emergentist.

  18. 18.

    Given the trove, we may ask why those who have undergone cataract surgery, replacing their organic lens with a plastic one, are having genuine, rather than ersatz visual experiences. Given trove of empirical data at hand, why has this sort of case been near-universally ignored in these debates?

References

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2002). Consciousness and its place in nature. In Philosophy of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2012). Constructing the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2015). Panpsychism and panprotpsychism. In Alter, T. and Nagasawa, Y. (Eds.), Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian monism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1968). Language and mind (enlarged edition). New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Studies in the logic of explanation. In Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739). A treatise of human nature.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology (Vol. 1). Henry Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2000). Mind in a physical world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan humility. In D. Braddon-Mictchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1700). An essay concerning human understanding (4th ed.).

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1989). Can we solve the mind-body problem? Mind, 98, 349–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. G. (2015). Russellian physicalism. In Alter, T. and Nagasawa, Y. (Eds.), Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian monism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What it is like to be a bat. The Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1918). On the notion of cause. In Mysticism and logic (pp. 171–196). London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1927). The analysis of matter. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, S. (2017). Idealism or something near enough. In K. Pearce & T. Goldschmidt (Eds.), Idealism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (1995). Consciousness, information and panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2, 272–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W., & Allen-Hermanson, S. (2010). Panpsychism. In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism/.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2001). Two conceptions of the physical. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62, 253–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2008). Real materialism and other essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tyndall, J. (1897). Fragments of science,: A series of detached essays, addresses, and reviews (Vol. 2). New York: D. Appleton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gulick, R. (2001). Reduction, emergence and other recent options on the mind-body problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(9–10), 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vision, G. (2018). The provenance of consciousness. In E. Vitaliadis & C. Mekos (Eds.), Brute facts (pp. 155–176). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerald Vision .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Vision, G. (2021). Consciousness: Philosophy’s Great White Whale. In: Clowes, R.W., Gärtner, K., Hipólito, I. (eds) The Mind-Technology Problem . Studies in Brain and Mind, vol 18. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-72644-7_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics