Skip to main content

Common Law Precedent and the Logic of Reasons

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
New Developments in Legal Reasoning and Logic

Part of the book series: Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning ((LARI,volume 23))

  • 431 Accesses

Abstract

I deal with the concept of precedential constraint in the common law via the concept of (practical) reason. After presenting and critically discussing John Horty’s influential reasons-as-defaults model, I introduce and defend a justification-based model, expanding on the framework developed by Faroldi and Protopopescu (All-things-considered oughts, ms, 2018; Logic Journal of the IGPL, 2019), by showing how to account for precedential constraint.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We ignore here further equally well-known tools a court has to distance itself from previous decisions of other courts or of the same courts. We ignore what has been called the persuasive force of precedent (see for instance Rigoni (2015) for a similar choice in a formal setting). Finally, we ignore the power of (some) higher courts to reaffirm or create precedent, such as, most famously, the U.S. Supreme Court decision to reverse the precedent of “separate but equal” doctrine (established by the Supreme Court itself in Plessy v. Ferguson (1896)) that legitimated racial segregation in Brown v. Board of education of Topeka (1954). In fact, some of the highest courts in common law systems hold themselves unable to overrule their own decisions—this was the official policy of the House of Lords (in its jurisdictional composition the highest court in the UK until very recently) until 1966, for instance.

  2. 2.

    Obviously, there are many criticisms one can raise from a philosophical standpoint. See Lamond (2016) for an introduction to such questions.

  3. 3.

    In the course of this work I will mostly refer to Horty (2012, 2014, 2015) and Horty (2016).

  4. 4.

    There is a third model of precedent: precedents as application of underlying principles, i.e. what is binding is the justification of the previous decision. Following Horty, we won’t consider this model in what follows.

  5. 5.

    For extended arguments for such a thesis, see Cf. Faroldi (2019, Ch. 7), Faroldi and Protopopescu (2018) and Dietrich and List (2017b).

  6. 6.

    Bonevac’s own proposal is to identify reasons with the true antecedents of true practical conditionals, i.e. conditionals with an ought in their consequent: \(A > \mathcal {O}B\). The conditional here is common-sense entailment, for which see Pelletier and Asher (1997) and Asher and Bonevac (1997), whereas the deontic modality is the usual standard deontic logic obligation. There is a quite troublesome problem for Bonevac’s approach, however, which is inherited by Pelletier and Asher’s framework: it allows substitution of logical equivalents, which is problematic for a theory of reasons that wants to pay attention to relevance, as it was argued at length in Faroldi (2019).

  7. 7.

    This is already recognized in part of the literature, although mostly (but not completely) informally. Without mentioning the vast literature on value and good (cf. for instance Kagan (1988)), Additive fallacy) and considering only reasons, see Bader (2016), Dietrich and List (2017a,b) and Schroeder (2007).

  8. 8.

    And indeed, if one could define some notion of equivalence for reasons, ≡, given t ≡ s and t : ϕ, it would not follow that s : ϕ, as shown in Faroldi, Truthmaker Semantics for Justification Logic, ms.

  9. 9.

    The application operation encodes the idea of applying one term to another to obtain a complex one, in a sort of step of applying modus ponens to the formulas justified by certain terms.

  10. 10.

    In case we have +: s ∪ t ⊆ (s + t).

  11. 11.

    With an abuse of notation we are now using ∪ in the object language to refer to an operation of aggregation. We do not employ +  because we wish to stay non-committal about the aggregation, leaving its properties up to the user, perhaps also with reference to different provisions in different legal systems.

  12. 12.

    For atomism and holism in the formal theory of reasons, see Bader (2016), for instance.

  13. 13.

    For an explanatory semantics, cf. Faroldi, Truthmaker Semantics for Justification Logic, ms.

References

  • Artemov, S. (2001). Explicit provability and constructive semantics. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 7(1), 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artemov, S. (2008). The logic of justification. Review of Symbolic Logic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Artemov, S. (2012). The ontology of justifications in the logical setting. Studia Logica, 1–14. 10.1007/s11225-012-9387-x.

  • Artemov, S. (2017). Epistemic modeling with justifications. arXiv: 1703.07028v2 [cs.LO].

  • Artemov, S., & Fitting, M. (2012). Justification logic. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Fall 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Bonevac, D. (1997). Common sense obligation. In D. Nute (Ed.), Defeasible deontic logic (pp. 159–203). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bader, R. (2016). Conditions, modifiers, and holism. In E. Lord, B. Maguire (Eds.), Weighing reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonevac, D. (2016). Defaulting on reasons. Noûs, 50, 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, F., & List, C. (2017a). Choice-theoretic deontic logic. ms.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, F., & List, C. (2017b). What matters and how it matters: A choice-theoretic representation of moral theories. The Philosophical Review.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faroldi, F. L. G. (2019). Hyperintensionality and normativity. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Faroldi, F. L. G. & Protopopescu, T. (2018). All-things-considered oughts. ms.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faroldi, F. L. G. & Protopopescu, T. (2019). Hyperintensional logics of reasons. Logic Journal of the IGPL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. (2014). Possible world semantics for first-order logic of proofs. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 165(1), 225–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. F. (2012). Reasons as defaults. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. F. (2014). Norm change in the common law. In S.O. Hansson (Ed.), David Makinson on classical methods for non-classical problems, vol. 3, Outstanding contributions to logic (pp. 335–355). Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. F. (2015). Constraint and freedom in the common law. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15, 25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. F. (2016). Reasoning with precedents as constrained natural reasoning. In E. Lord, B. Maguire (Eds.) Weighing reasons (pp. 193–212). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1988). The additive fallacy. Ethics, 99, 5–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuznets, R., & Studer, T. (2012). Justifications, ontology, and conservativity. In T. Bolander, T. Braner, S. Ghilardi, L. Moss (Eds.), Advances in modal logic, vol. 9 Advances in modal logic. College Publications

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamond, G. (2005). Do precedents create rules? Legal Theory, 15, 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamond, G. (2016). Precedent and analogy in legal reasoning. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Spring 2016. Metaphysics Research Lab. Stanford: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelletier, F. J., & Asher, N. (1997). Generics and defaults. In J. Van Benthem, A. ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and language (pp. 1125–1177). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rigoni, A. (2015). An improved factor based approach to precedential constraint. Artificial Intelligence and Law, 23. 1703.07028v2 [cs.LO].

  • Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the passions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Federico L. G. Faroldi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Faroldi, F.L.G. (2022). Common Law Precedent and the Logic of Reasons. In: Rahman, S., Armgardt, M., Kvernenes, H.C.N. (eds) New Developments in Legal Reasoning and Logic. Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-70084-3_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics