Skip to main content

Karl Popper: His Philosophy and Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Karl Popper's Science and Philosophy

Abstract

Karl Popper is one of the few philosophers of science who is well-known to scientists and respected by them. Apart from the direct influence of his views on science it is his methodology that most appeals to scientists. He earned the highest accolades for his emphasis on criticism as the essence of progress in science. His methodological principle of criticism is the core of a dynamic epistemology, requiring an adventurous spirit and expressing the high-risk nature of the cognitive process. Via the falsification of proposed hypotheses, the positive role of erring is exploited to further the discovery of new problems, leading to the growth of knowledge. Despite various criticisms of his imperative of falsification I claim that Popper proposes an original model of rationality rid of all justificationist ingredients, in which he divorces reason from positive reasons, truth from certainty and argument from belief. In this challenging philosophical vision Popper defines reason in negative terms, as an agent of destruction of knowledge claims, and views all knowledge as conjectural, hypothetical and provisional.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Popper, however, sometimes compromises this imperative by claiming that a certain amount of dogmatism in the initial phase of assessing a new hypothesis is necessary—a theory should show its mettle before it is submitted to the destructive effect of criticism; “a critical attitude needs for its raw material, as it were, theories or beliefs which are held more or less dogmatically” (Popper 1985, 50). I see this claim as dangerous. Any declaration of the legitimacy or even rationality of dogmatism—however limited it may be—tames criticism. However, in critical rationalism a methodological norm must not tame criticism or it consequently loses its regulative appeal. In the whole context of Popper´s writing I regard it as a lapse, in which Popper overlooks his own arguments concerning the primordial power of dogmatism (Parusniková 2017, 27–39).

  2. 2.

    The need of cultivating an open-minded atmosphere in scientific community is discussed for instance by Agassi and Jarvie (1987): scientific workshop provides the ideal environment in which “critical debate about open questions, employing tentative answers which are accepted either as grounds for action or as agenda for further debate or both” (44).

  3. 3.

    References to logical positivism take into account neither the differences between individual philosophers nor the changes in their views over time. I present only the constitutive features defining their positions.

  4. 4.

    In full, Hume´s copy principle goes as follows: “All our simple ideas in their first appearance are deriv’d from simple impressions, which are correspondent to them, and which they exactly represent ” (Hume 1981 [1739], 4).

  5. 5.

    For instance, in seeking to prove the principle of induction, Russell tries to avoid this deadlock as follows: “we shall nevertheless hold some knowledge is a priori in the sense that experience which makes us think of it does not suffice to prove it, but merely so directs our attention that we see its truth without requiring any proof from experience” (1912, 116).

  6. 6.

    I leave out Popper´s controversial concept of the degrees of corroboration as linked to the degrees of verisimilitude; this is discussed in Part II of this book.

  7. 7.

    Fragment 34 from Sextus Empiricus; the first line (sometimes added) is fragment 18 from Stobaeus.

  8. 8.

    Popper gives Einstein as an example of such a critical attitude, specifically his prediction of the redshift in the spectrum of the satellites of Sirius; if this prediction was wrong, Einstein claimed, the general theory of relativity would be untenable.

References

  • Agassi, J., Jarvie, I.C. (eds.): Rationality: the critical view. Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S.: Kuhn vs Popper. Icon Books, Cambridge (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D.: A treatise of human nature. In: Ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge, revised by P.H. Nidditch. Second edition. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1981[1739])

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D.: An enquiry concerning human understanding. In: Ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge, revised P.H. Nidditch. Third edition. Clarendon Press, Oxford (2005[1748])

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S.: The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago University Press, Chicago (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S.: Logic of discovery or psychology of research? In: Lakatos, I., Musgrave, A. (eds.) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 1–25. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D.: Critical rationalism: a restatement and defence. Open Court, Chicago and La Salle, Illinois (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton-Smith, W.H.: The rationality of science. Routledge and Kegan Paul (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Hear, A.: Karl Popper. Routledge and Kegan Paul (1980)

    Google Scholar 

  • Parusniková, Z.: Horror Dogmatis. In: Bar-Am, N., Gattei, S. (eds.) Encouraging Openness: Essays for Joseph Agassi on the Occasion of his 90th Birthday. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science. Springer Verlag, pp. 27–39 (2017)

    Google Scholar 

  • Parusniková, Z.: Two cheers for Karl Popper. In: O´Hear, A. (ed.) Karl Popper: Critical Assessments of Leading Philosophers. Routledge, London, pp. 79–99 (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R.: The logic of scientific discovery. Harper and Row, New York (1965 [1959])

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R.: Objective knowledge: an evolutionary approach. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1979 [1972])

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R.: Unended quest. Fontana, Glasgow (1982a [1974])

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R.: Normal science and its dangers. In: Lakatos, I., Musgrave, A. (eds.) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 51–59. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1982b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R.: Conjectures and refutations: the growth of scientific knowledge. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London (1985 [1963])

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R.: Realism and the aim of science: postscript to the logic of scientific discovery. In: Bartley III, W.W. (ed.). Hutchinson, London (1988 [1983])

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B.A.W.: The problems of philosophy. Williams and Norgate, London (1912)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B.A.W.: A history of western philosophy. George Allen & Unwin Ltd. Repaginated Classics edition (2004). Routledge, Abingdon (1946)

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W.C.: The justification of inductive rules of inference. In: Lakatos, I. (ed.) The problem of inductive logic, pp. 24–43. North-Holland Publishing, Amsterdam (1968)

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J.: Against ‘normal science.’ In: Lakatos, I., Musgrave, A. (eds.) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 25–39. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J.: Science and scepticism. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1984)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J.: Revolution in permanence: Popper on theory-change in science. In: O’Hear, A. (ed.) Karl Popper: philosophy and problems, pp. 75–103. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1996)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank David Miller for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zuzana Parusniková .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Parusniková, Z. (2021). Karl Popper: His Philosophy and Science. In: Parusniková, Z., Merritt, D. (eds) Karl Popper's Science and Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-67036-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics