Skip to main content

Edith Stein on a Different Motive that Led Husserl to Transcendental Idealism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Idealism-Realism Debate Among Edmund Husserl’s Early Followers and Critics

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 112))

Abstract

In the following paper we will attempt to analyze and reconstruct Edith Stein’s interpretation of Husserl’s “transcendental idealism,” notably, the reason why, in her opinion, the latter ended up embracing that specific philosophical position. As will soon become apparent, according to Stein, Husserl misunderstands the peculiar ontological structure of individual essences and, in particular, the specific connection with reality that they carry within themselves. Without raising the question of whether Stein’s own understanding of transcendental idealism perfectly corresponds with Husserl’s, we will confine ourselves to discussing, first, the wider context within which she tackles it and, second, the relation between Husserl’s idealism and the formal-ontological issue of how to characterize the internal content of individual essences. No matter what we think of Stein’s critical assessment, her approach has the great and undeniable merit of forcing the “interpreter” to face the problem of the tight connection between the transcendental dimension and the eidetic dimension of Husserl’s thought.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Ingarden 1976.

  2. 2.

    For Dietrich von Hildebrand, for example, there is no substantial distinction between (i) and (iii). “[Phenomenology] signifies in fact the most outspoken objectivism and realism. It is this meaning of phenomenology which we find in the writings of Adolf Reinach, Alexander Pfänder, myself, and several others, and which we, at least, identified with the meaning of phenomenology in the first edition of Husserl’s Logische Untersuchungen” (Hildebrand 1991, p. 273)

  3. 3.

    This seems to be Jean Hering’s interpretation in Phénoménologie et philosophie religieuse (Hering 1926). Moritz Geiger distinguishes between the turn to the object [Wendung zum Objekt] and the turn to the subject [Wendung ins Subjektive]. And yet he remarks that: “From the beginning this meant a ‘turn to the subjective’, which, of course, did not abrogate (rather, it presupposed) the turn to the object, nor must it have been interpreted from the outset in an idealistic way.” (Geiger 1933, p. 15)

  4. 4.

    Stein (2014, p. 164) argues that there is no “absolute break” (Bruch) between Ideas I and the Logical Investigations.

  5. 5.

    Bald fanden sich andere dazu. Alle hatten dieselbe Frage auf dem Herzen.” (Stein 2010, p. 200)

  6. 6.

    An indirect reference to this question can be found in Husserl’s Phenomenology and the Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas. “In fact, in the years following the publication of Ideas I, in which Husserl first spoke of <his ‘idealism’>, the main arguments against this point, against this much discussed ‘idealism’, were addressed. Again and again, this question was discussed in conversation with eager disciples, without it coming to a conclusion. In such conversations, the trains of thought which were crucial for Husserl proved ineffective to convince his opponents. And if one of them declared victory in the moment, he would sooner or later come back with his old objections or with new ones.” (Stein 1929, pp. 327–328. Emphasis added.)

  7. 7.

    Stein 2010, p. 200.

  8. 8.

    See Stein 2014, pp. 119–142, and pp. 159–162, where she writes that the Logical Investigations accomplished a return, not to “realism,” but to the traditional idea of a philosophia perennis et universalis.

  9. 9.

    For a brief historical discussion of Stein’s position in the phenomenological movement, see Sepp 1998.

  10. 10.

    “I have turned over a new leaf when it comes to idealism and believe it can be understood in such a way that is metaphysically satisfying. But it seems to me that much of what is in Ideas has to be comprehended differently, though in Husserl’s sense, if only he brings together what he has, and in a decisive moment does not leave out of consideration something that necessarily belongs to the subject matter at stake.” (Stein 2003, p. 87.)

  11. 11.

    For an analysis of Stein’s theory of knowledge, see Volk 2003.

  12. 12.

    See the “Einführung des Bearbeiters” in Stein 2005 (pp. xi-xxxvii). See also Fritz Kaufmann, who speaks indeed of “a monumental metaphysical system.” (Kaufmann 1952, p. 572)

  13. 13.

    For an important presentation and discussion of this topic, see Tommasi 2003.

  14. 14.

    For an overall presentation, see Fetz 1993.

  15. 15.

    For an interpretation of the Excursus that also includes Kant see Ales Bello 2005, pp. 82–87.

  16. 16.

    Sepp (2003, p. 21) talks of a “genealogy of a possible encounter between the two ontological spheres of the objectual world and consciousness” (einer möglichen Begegnung der beiden Seinssphäre von Gegenstandswelt und Bewußtsein.)

  17. 17.

    Stein 2005, pp. 240–241.

  18. 18.

    Stein 2005, p. 241.

  19. 19.

    Though without any specific textual reference, the German title of the book is explicitly mentioned in Stein 2005, page 243.

  20. 20.

    In other words, the relation between the human subject and the world as it is for us.

  21. 21.

    This critical position had already been made explicit in Stein 2014, p. 96.

  22. 22.

    For an analysis of the practical dimension of the essence see Lebech 2019, pp. 31–33.

  23. 23.

    This is what Hering labels the “principle of the essence”. For a critical discussion of Hering’s principle, see De Santis 2016b.

  24. 24.

    Aristotle would not agree with this construal of the πoιεῖν καὶ πάσχειν, since they are both considered as “figures of categories” (σχήματα τῆς κατηγoρίας) of “being in itself” (καθ’αὑτó) and not κατὰ συμβεβηκóς (see Metaphysics , Δ, 1017a 22–23). We cannot forget that Stein’s reading rests on Hering’s interpretation of the πoιεῖν καὶ πάσχειν (Hering 1921, pp. 499–500,) which he translates with the German word Schicksal (“Schicksale belong not to the domain of the πoῖoν εἷναι, but rather to that of the πoιεῖν καὶ πάσχειν”).

  25. 25.

    Stein 1962, p. 73.

  26. 26.

    Three elements have been intentionally left out of the analysis and thus of the diagram: the notion of “essential core” (Wesenskern,) the πoιεῖν καὶ πάσχειν, and the distinction between what “belongs to the essence ” and what, even without belonging to it, “necessarily follows from the essence.” For these latter problems, see De Santis 2015.

  27. 27.

    For a detailed analysis of this notion and its significance in early phenomenology, see De Santis 2014.

  28. 28.

    See the entire analysis developed in Chapter III, §2, of Stein 1962, pp. 61–67: “Here we encounter one of those formations which Plato had in mind when he discussed the nature of Ideas (ἰδεα, εἶδoς).” As Kaufmann (1952, p. 572) puts it, “In the wake of Jean Hering’s essay in the fourth volume of Husserl’s Jahrbuch, she attempts at an integration of Plato’s self-subsistent ideas (Wesenheiten) with Aristotle’s immanent substantial forms (Wesensformen) which, ultimately individual themselves (Duns Scotus), unfold in the growth of individual and real things. This conformity of the ideal and sensory worlds is accounted for by the Neo-Platonic conception of the ideas in God.”

  29. 29.

    “to the essence of a particular thing belongs not only its being red, its being soft, its being fragrant, but also its being a rose or its being a bud, which provides the answer to the question: What is it?” “It pertains to the rose as a physical object to have form, size, Color, and a number of other qualities, etc. We say, ‘The rose is red,’ and ‘red’ thus belongs to the πoῖoν of the rose. We may also say, ‘The Color of the rose is red’ (or some shade of red, for red is not an ultimate determination). In speaking of Color, red does not designate the πoῖoν of the rose, but rather relates its τί.” (Stein 1962, p. 84)

References

  • Ales Bello, Angela. 2005. The Sense of Things. Towards a Phenomenological Realism. Trans. A. Calcagno. Dordrecht: Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1959. Die transzendentale und die ontologische Phänomenologie. In Edmund Husserl. Recueil commémoratif publié à l’occasion du centenaire de la naissance du philosophe, 175–184. La Haye: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, Daniele. 2014. L’idea della fenomenologia come fenomenologia delle Idee. Su di un peri ideon tra Gottinga e Monaco. In Di Idee ed essenze. Un dibattito su fenomenologia e ontologia (1921–1930), ed. D. De Santis. Milan: Mimesis: 7–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, Daniele. 2015. Wesen, Eidos, Idea. Remarks on the “Platonism” of Jean Hering and Roman Ingarden. Studia Phaenomenologica 15: 133–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, Daniele. 2016a. Notes on Husserl’s Idealismus in the Logische Untersuchungen (Via Lotze’s Interpretation of Plato). Research in Phenomenology 46 (2): 221–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, Daniele. 2016b. Jean Hering on Eidos, Gegenstand and Methexis. Phenomenological Adventures and Misadventures of “Participation.” Discipline Filosofiche 26 (1): 145–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetz, Reto Luzius. 1993. Ich, Seele, Selbst. Edith Steins Theorie personaler Identität. In Studien zur Philosophie von Edith Stein, ed. M. Rath, P. Schultz, 286–319. Freiburg, München: Karl Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geiger, Moritz. 1933. Alexander Pfänders methodische Stellung. In Neue Münchner Abhandlungen. Festschrift für Alexander Pfänder, ed. E. Heller, F. Löw, 1–16. Leipzig: Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, Jean. 1921. Bemerkungen über das Wesen, die Wesenheit und die Idee. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 4: 495–543.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, Jean. 1926. Phénoménologie et philosophie religieuse. Paris: Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrand, Dietrich von. 1991. What is Philosophy? London-New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1950. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch. Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie. Husserliana 3. Den Haag: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1984. Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band. Erster Teil. Husserliana 19.1. Den Haag: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, Roman. 1976. On the Motives which led Husserl to Transcendental Idealism. Den Haag: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, Fritz. 1952. Endliches und ewiges Sein. Versuch eines Aufstiegs zum Sinn des Seins by Edith Stein; Teresia Benedicta. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12 (4): 572–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lebech, Mette. 2019. Essence, eidos, and Dialogue in Stein’s “Husserl and Aquinas. A Comparison”. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Research, XVII: 22–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Natorp, Paul. 1901. Zur Frage der logischen Methode. Mit Beziehung auf E. Husserls ‘Prolegomena zur reinen Logik. Kant Studien 6: 270–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sepp, Hans-Reiner. 1998. La postura de Edith Stein dentro del movimiento fenomenológico. Anuario Filosófico 1: 709–729.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sepp, Hans-Reiner. 2003. Edith Steins Position in der Idealismus-Realismus-Debatte. In Edith Stein. Themen—Bezüge—Dokumente, ed. B. Beckmann, H.-B. Gerl-Falkovitz, 13–21. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Edith. 1929. Husserls Phänomenologie und die Philosophie des hl. Thomas von Aquino, Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung. E. Husserl zum 70. Geburtstag gewidmet 10 (Special Issue): 315–338.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Edith. 1962. Endliches und ewiges Sein. Versuch eines Aufstieges zum Sinn des Seins. ESGA 11/12. Freiburg: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Edith. 2003. Briefe an Roman Ingarden. ESGA 4. Freiburg, Basel, Wien: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Edith. 2005. Potenz und Akt. Studien zu einer Philosophie des Seins. ESGA 10. Freiburg: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Edith. 2010. Aus dem Leben einer jüdischen Familie und weitere autobiographische Beiträge. ESGA 1. Freiburg: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Edith. 2014. Freiheit und Gnade und weitere Beiträge zu Phänomenologie und Ontologie. ESGA 9. Freiburg, Basel, Wien: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tommasi, Francesco Valerio. 2003. “…verschiedene Sprachen redeten…” Ein Dialog zwischen Phänomenologie und mittelalterlichen Scholastik im Werk Edith Steins. In Edith Stein. Themen—Bezüge—Dokumente, ed. B. Beckmann, H.-B. Gerl-Falkovitz, 107–133. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Volk, Peter. 2003. Erkenntnistheorie bei Edith Stein. In Edith Stein. Themen—Bezüge—Dokumente, ed. B. Beckmann, H.-B. Gerl-Falkovitz, 81–95. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by the Czech Science Foundation, financing the project “Intentionality and Person in Medieval Philosophy and Phenomenology” (GAČR 21-08256S).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniele De Santis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

De Santis, D. (2021). Edith Stein on a Different Motive that Led Husserl to Transcendental Idealism. In: Parker, R.K.B. (eds) The Idealism-Realism Debate Among Edmund Husserl’s Early Followers and Critics. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 112. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-62159-9_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics