Skip to main content

Rational Golems: Collective Agents as Players in the Reasoning Game

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Groups, Norms and Practices

Abstract

We ordinarily attribute beliefs and other intentional states to collective entities. These attributions can be vindicated from a theoretical perspective that holds that: (i) collective entities can behave as rational agents in our argumentative practices of giving and asking for reasons; and (ii) attributions of beliefs are interpretative tools aiming to make sense of the behaviors and perspectives of agents, and to keep track of their commitments. However, it is not immediately clear that groups have attitudes that play the same role in our argumentative and interpretative practices as the beliefs of individuals. It seems that the belief-like attitudes attributed to collective agents lack some of the distinctive features of the beliefs of individuals. More specifically, collective (but not individual) agents seem to be able to form beliefs against the available evidence at will, moved by rewards or other practical considerations. This has made some authors (Wray, Synthese 129(3): 319–333, 2001; Wray PRO 18: 363–376, 2003; Meijers, ProtoSociology 16: 70–85, 2002; Meijers, PRO 18: 377–388, 2003; Hakli, Cogn Syst Res, 7(2–3): 286–297, 2006) argue that the belief-like attitudes of collectives are actually some form of acceptance (which does not involve the commitment to truth characteristic of belief). On our view, this proposal is misguided. We shall argue that the belief-like attitudes of collectives are actually subject to the norms that govern belief, even if these norms can be broken more blatantly in the case of groups than in the case of individuals. In order to explain why this is so, we appeal to the fact that doxastic deliberation in groups is mediated by the deliberative actions of the relevant members, which may be rationally motivated by practical considerations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The notion of collective belief has been defended, among others, by Gilbert (1987, 1989, 1994, 1996, 2002) and Tollefsen (2002, 2015). For further discussion, see List (2005), List and Pettit (2011), Lackey (2016), and Kallestrup (2016).

  2. 2.

    See Parfit (2011), Scanlon (1998), and Raz (1975).

  3. 3.

    We also want to remain neutral about whether the constitution of a collective agent requires that its members adopt attitudes in the we-mode (Tuomela 2013; also Schmitz 2017) . In general, we wish to be as non-committal as possible about how the members of a group must interact in order for the group to behave as a collective agent (i.e. as a proficient player in normative practices of giving and asking for reasons) . It may well be that there is not a unique answer applying to all types of collective agent.

  4. 4.

    There are numerous mathematical proofs, in the judgment aggregation literature, showing that, given some reasonable assumptions, it is impossible to aggregate profiles of rational individual beliefs in a completely coherent way (see List and Pettit 2011).

  5. 5.

    For discussion of this idea and different ways of developing it, see among others Wedgwood (2002), Shah and Velleman (2005), Owens (2003), Steglich-Petersen (2006), Boghossian (2008), McHugh (2014b), and Whiting (2010).

  6. 6.

    This does not mean that we lack control over our beliefs. It can be argued that beliefs are under rational control, insofar as we form them in response to the reasons available to us (McHugh 2012, 2014a; Hieronymi 2008).

  7. 7.

    For proposals along these lines, see Shah and Velleman (2005) and Hieronymi (2008).

  8. 8.

    Take ‘p?’ as shorhand for a grammatically correct formulation of the question whether p. Indeed, as a matter of psychological fact, individuals hardly ever deliberate asking explicitly to themselves ‘Should I believe that p?’, rather than simply ‘p?’. The sort of transparency we are discussing would explain why this is the case.

  9. 9.

    Most of the main points we want to make could also be made in terms of weaker norms that do not require beliefs to be true, for instance the evidentialist norm that one ought to adjust one’s beliefs to the evidence available (see Conee and Feldman 2004). We will focus on truth-involving norms, for the sake of simplicity, and because of their plausibility.

  10. 10.

    For discussion on the notion of acceptance, see Cohen (1995) and van Fraassen (1980).

Bibliography

  • Boghossian, P. (2008). Content and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2000). Articulating reasons. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bykvist, K., & Hattiangadi, A. (2007). Does thought imply ought? Analysis, 67, 277–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. J. (1995). Essay on belief and acceptance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, S. (2013). Collectives’ duties and collectivization duties. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(2), 231–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, S. (2017). Duties of group agents and group members. Journal of Social Philosophy, 48(1), 38–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism: Essays in epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1987). Modelling collective belief. Synthese, 73(1), 185–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1994). Remarks on collective belief. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing epistemology: The social dimensions of knowledge (pp. 111–134). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1996). Living together: Rationality, sociality, and obligation. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2002). Belief and acceptance as features of groups. PRO, 16, 35–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M., & Pilchman, D. (2014). Belief, acceptance, and what happens in groups. In J. Lackey (Ed.), Essays in collective epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glüer, K., & Wikforss, Å. (2013). Against belief normativity. In T. Chan (Ed.), The aim of belief (pp. 80–99). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • González de Prado Salas, J., & Zamora-Bonilla, J. (2015). Collective actors without collective minds: An inferentialist approach. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 45, 3–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hakli, R. (2006). Group beliefs and the distinction between belief and acceptance. Cognitive Systems Research, 7(2–3), 286–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hieronymi, P. (2008). Responsibility for believing. Synthese, 161(3), 357–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kallestrup, J. (2016). Group virtue epistemology. Synthese, 1–19. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1225-7.

  • Kitcher, P. (1990). The division of cognitive labor. The Journal of Philosophy, 87(1), 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2016). What is justified group belief? Philosophical Review, 125(3), 341–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C. (2005). Group knowledge and group rationality: A judgment aggregation perspective. Episteme, 2(1), 25–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mathiesen, K. (2006). The epistemic features of group belief. Episteme, 2(3), 161–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, C. (2012). Epistemic deontology and voluntariness. Erkenntnis, 77(1), 65–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, C. (2014a). Exercising doxastic freedom. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, C. (2014b). Fitting belief. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 114, 167–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meijers, A. (2002). Collective agents and cognitive attitudes. ProtoSociology, 16, 70–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meijers, A. (2003). Why accept collective beliefs?: Reply to Gilbert. PRO, 18, 377–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2017). The enigma of reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Owens, D. (2003). Does belief have an aim? Philosophical Studies, 115, 283–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1975). Practical reason and norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitz, M. (2017). What is a mode account of collective intentionality? In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Social ontology and collective intentionality (pp. 37–70). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1(19), 253–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N. (2003). How Truth Governs Belief. Philosophical Review, 112(4), 447–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N., & Velleman, J. D. (2005). Doxastic deliberation. The Philosophical Review, 114(4), 497–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steglich-Petersen, A. (2006). No norm needed: On the aim of belief. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56, 499–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D. P. (2002). Challenging epistemic individualism. PRO, 16, 86–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D. P. (2015). Groups as agents. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2013). Social ontology: Collective intentionality and group agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wagenknecht, S. (2016). Social epistemology of research groups. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2002). The aim of belief. Noûs, 36, 267–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy of Science, 76(2), 225–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiting, D. (2010). Should I believe the truth? Dialectica, 64(2), 213–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1973). Problems of the self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. B. (2001). Collective belief and acceptance. Synthese, 129(3), 319–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. B. (2003). What really divides Gilbert and the rejectionists? PRO, 18, 363–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zamora-Bonilla, J. (2014). The nature of co-authorship: A note on recognition sharing and scientific argumentation. Synthese, 191, 97–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

González de Prado, J., Zamora-Bonilla, J. (2021). Rational Golems: Collective Agents as Players in the Reasoning Game. In: Koreň, L., Schmid, H.B., Stovall, P., Townsend, L. (eds) Groups, Norms and Practices. Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality, vol 13. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-49590-9_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics