Skip to main content

Philosophical Issues in Water Law

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ethical Water Stewardship

Part of the book series: Water Security in a New World ((WSEC))

  • 568 Accesses

Abstract

The use of law to regulate water raises many philosophical issues. This chapter examines the two principle moral justifications on which legal regulation rests: regulating water is important primarily because it ensures human access to it (the instrumental justification); regulating water is important because water is valuable in itself (the non-instrumental justification). The chapter will also explore the meaning of “law” by comparing various systems for regulating water, including non–stated-based systems (such as community, social, cultural, moral, or religious rules) and state-based systems (including international human rights law, domestic constitutional law, administrative and regulatory approaches, environmental stewardship, and traditional private law mechanisms). Throughout the chapter, we will also identify various critical perspectives that force us to consider whether the concept of law that supports legal regulation of water or whether specific laws and rules that societies have created treat marginalized groups such as women, the poor, racialized groups, and Indigenous peoples fairly.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    I have placed “regulation” in quotes because I will discuss moral and religious rules that some societies use to regulate water. Some people do not consider such rules to be regulations in the same way that laws enforced by the government are.

  2. 2.

    I use the word “state” in the international law sense to refer to polities that are recognized in international law. I restrict it to this use to make it clear that law exists outside of such states (hence the term “nons-state-based law”), for instance in the polities of Indigenous peoples and ethnic minorities, which have systems for regulating water that preexist or coexist with those created by officially recognized states.

  3. 3.

    For a discussion of the international law position in regard to what law applies to the Western Sahara, see the Western Sahara Case (1975: 12). Water is discussed in para 137.

  4. 4.

    For a good introduction to New Institutional Economics, see North (1995) and Ostrom (2008).

  5. 5.

    For a discussion on whether rules of an informal, spiritual, or moral nature constitute “law” in the sense used in European legal traditions, see the writings of those in the legal pluralist tradition such as MacDonald (2011) and Chiba (1998).

  6. 6.

    Two ancient Greek philosophers, Thales and Hippo, both held the view that water is a basic principle that explains the functioning of the natural world. See for instance Simplicius’ summary of their views in Urmson (1992: 23:21–29). Chinese philosophers had similar views: an example can be found in the Guanzi (管子; ch. 39). For an interpretation of the relevant passage, see Fung (1952: 166–67).

  7. 7.

    For examples of codes for the regulation of water from other regions, see Nanni (2007: ch. 2–3).

  8. 8.

    For an introduction to the topic by a contemporary Chinese philosopher, see Tu Wei-ming (1972).

  9. 9.

    For instance, see the Indigenous Peoples’ Earth Charter of 1992, in which Indigenous peoples describe their relationship to their territory in spiritual terms. Para 31 of the Charter states that “Indigenous Peoples were placed upon our Mother, the Earth, by the Creator. We belong to the land. We cannot be separated from our lands and territories.”

  10. 10.

    See also the Garma International Indigenous Water Declaration (2008) and Sanderson (2008).

  11. 11.

    For some ideas in this regard, see Assembly of First Nations: http://www.afn.ca/honoring-water

  12. 12.

    Friedrich Hölderlin (1770–1843), Novalis (1772–1801), Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775–1854) and Karl Wilhelm Friedrich Schlegel (1772–1829) are but a few examples. The themes of German Romanticism are also famously taken up by the poet Johann Wolfgang von Goethe (1749–1832).

  13. 13.

    As an example of such critique, see Heidegger (1977).

  14. 14.

    “‘La pensée paysagère’, qu’est-ce que cela veut dire?” (presented on December 9, 2017; on file with author), 12. See also “Existe-t-il un mode de pensée forestier?” (presented on January 28, 2017, at the University of Paris-Sorbonne; on file with author).

  15. 15.

    In regard to Japanese philosophy, Berque is particularly inspired by the work of Watsuji Tetsurō, especially his concept of aidagara (“betweenness”), which Berque translates as “médiance.” Watsuji’s notion of this term is described in works such as his three-volume Ethics (Rinrigaku), a portion of which is translated into English as Watsuji Tetsurō’s Rinrigaku: Ethics in Japan, trans. Yamamoto Seisaku and Robert E. Carter (New York: SUNY Press, 1996), and Climate and Culture: A Philosophical Study, trans. Geoffrey Bownas (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1988).

  16. 16.

    For a discussion of the importance of promoting human rights to protect these capacities, see Sen (1999).

  17. 17.

    See generally Alston (2013).

  18. 18.

    Alan Gewirth claims that human freedom is the fundamental value underlying human rights. See Gewirth (1982). For similar natural rights views, see Finnis (2011), Griffin (2008), and Perry (1998). Henry Shue (1996: 23) includes a right to unpolluted water as a “basic right.”

  19. 19.

    See, e.g., Finnis (2011: 205), citing Hart (1971: 200–1).

  20. 20.

    Joseph Raz (2010: 39) writes that according to traditional human rights theories, human rights are “universal because they are rights every human being has as a human being.”

  21. 21.

    Aristotle believed that to understand what it means to be human and to know how to act as a human, one must understand the “function” of humans (Nicomachean Ethics 1097b24). This function, Aristotle argues, is to act in accordance with our reason, which in turn requires that we act virtuously (NE 1098a15-17). It is in this sense that Nussbaum (1995: 118), like other philosophers, argues that what makes us truly human is our capacity for practical reason (moral reasoning). For a very good discussion of Aristotle’s argument and its critics, see Korsgaard (2009).

  22. 22.

    Nussbaum is developing the idea of Aristotle that the function of the state is to ensure that people have what they need in order to fulfil their function, which is to act in accordance with reason in the pursuit of virtue. She writes, “The job of [the future legislator] is to give to the people in his city the necessary conditions for choosing a flourishing human life. The city aims at making people capable of such choices. A life that is not even human at all is, a fortiori, not a good human life. And it is Aristotle’s claim that many conceivable political and economic arrangements do, either wholly or in part, remove the humanity from political life by removing choice from people – either in a single sphere or across the board” (1995: 118).

  23. 23.

    See also Hardt and Negri (2000).

  24. 24.

    For a discussion focused more on human rights, see Anghie (2013).

  25. 25.

    For a good modern development of Mill’s approach to human rights, see Talbott (2010).

  26. 26.

    I discussed Nussbaum’s work in the section on natural law theories because I believe her inspirations – the Stoics and Aristotle – fit into this paradigm. As an economist, Sen’s philosophical reasons for promoting the “capabilities approach” are slightly different than those of Nussbaum.

  27. 27.

    This is discussed in Hanemann (2006). The original distinction between private and public goods originates with Samuelson (1954: 387–389), elaborated in Samuelson (1955).

  28. 28.

    For an argument that water is a public good, see Barlow (2007).

  29. 29.

    For a discussion of how law and economics treats “common-pool” goods and various solutions for regulating them through institutions such as private property rights, see Trebilcock (1997: 138–141).

  30. 30.

    Such administrative rules and the law that regulates them are discussed in Loughlin (2010).

  31. 31.

    On the dialogue theory that explains the back and forth between courts and legislatures in the process of interpreting laws and the constitution, see Roach (2001).

  32. 32.

    Wood describe this approach as based on the assumption that environmental “agencies are neutral and objective agents of the public, constituted to carry out statutory objectives without regard to internal or external political agendas” (2009a: 59).

  33. 33.

    In the UK and its former colonies, “common law” is law made by judges; it is contrasted with law made by legislators such as elected officials. In other countries that are governed by civil law, the kinds of rules contained in the common law are often found in the country’s civil code.

  34. 34.

    For a good overview of research methods used by law and economics, see Trebilcock (1997: 124). For an application of law and economics analysis to environmental law, see Green (2006).

  35. 35.

    See, e.g., Brewer et al. (2007).

  36. 36.

    For a general description of feminist methods for studying law, see Bartlett (1990: 829). Similar questions are asked by non-lawyers, such as those interested international development. In this regard, see Beetham and Demetriades (2007). See also Harris et al. (2015).

  37. 37.

    For critical race approaches in general, see e.g. (Razack et al. 2010; Matsuda 1988; Crenshaw 1991; Harris 1990; Razack 1998). In regard to the environment, see Sturgeon (1997) and Moore et al. (2003).

References

  • Alston P (2013) International human rights: texts and materials. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Anghie A (2005) Imperialism, sovereignty, and the making of international law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anghie A (2013) Whose utopia? Human rights, development, and the third world. Qui Parle Crit Humanit Soc Sci 22(1):63–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakker K (2010) Privatizing water: governance failure and the world’s urban water crisis. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Barlow M (2007) Blue covenant: the global water crisis and the coming battle for the right to water. McClelland & Stewart, Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett KT (1990) Feminist legal methods. Harv Law Rev 103(4):829–888

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beetham G, Demetriades J (2007) Feminist research methodologies and development: overview and practical application. Gend Dev 15(2):199–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berque A (2008) La pensée paysagère. Archibooks, Bastia

    Google Scholar 

  • Bock FG (1990) The enthronement rites: the text of Engishiki, 927. Monum Nippon 45(3):307–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd DR (2012) The right to a healthy environment: revitalizing Canada’s constitution. UBC Press, Vancouver

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer J, Fleishman MA, Glennon R, Ker A, Libecap G (2007) Law and the new institutional economics: water markets and legal change in California, 1987–2005. Arizona legal studies discussion paper no. 07-35 (December). http://ssrn.com/abstract=1079685. Accessed 6 Apr 2020

  • Canada Water Act (1970) R.S.C. 1985, c. C-11

    Google Scholar 

  • Caney S (2005) Justice beyond borders: a global political theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chiba M (1998) Other phases of legal pluralism in the contemporary world. Ratio Juris 11(3):228–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ching J (1993) Chinese religions. Orbis, Maryknoll

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen F (1935) Transcendental nonsense and the functional approach. Columbia Law Rev 35(6):809–849

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crenshaw K (1991) Mapping the margins: intersectionality, identity politics, and violence against women of color. Stanford Law Rev 43(6):1241–1299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly J (1993) International human rights. Westview Press, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly J (2003) Universal human rights in theory and practice, 2nd edn. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (2000) Sovereign virtue: the theory and practice of equality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Felicia Gressit Bock, trans (1970) Engi-Shiki. Procedures of the Engi Era, Books I-IV. Sophia University, Tokyo

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (2011) Natural law and natural rights, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • First Nations in Ontario (2008) Resolution 08/87 passed at the 2008 Special Chiefs Assembly in Toronto. https://www.afn.ca/uploads/files/sca-res-08.pdf. Accessed 6 Apr 2020

  • Fox-Decent E (2012) Sovereignty’s promise: the state as fiduciary. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fung Yu-L (1952) A history of Chinese philosophy, vol 1 (trans: Bodde D). Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Garma International Indigenous Water Declaration (2008) www.afn.ca/uploads/files/env/garma-international.pdf. Accessed 6 Apr 2020

  • Getzler J (2006) A history of water rights at common law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth A (1982) Human rights: essays on justification and applications. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Green AJ (2006) You can’t pay them enough: subsidies, environmental law and social norms. Harvard Environ Law Rev 30(2):407–440

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (1986) Well-being: its meaning, measurement, and moral importance. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (2008) On human rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hanemann WM (2006) The economic conception of water. In: Rogers PP, Llamas MR, Martinez-Crotina L (eds) Water crisis: myth or reality? Taylor & Francis, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardt M, Negri A (2000) Empire. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris AP (1990) Race and essentialism in feminist legal theory. Stanford Law Rev 42(3):581–616

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris LM, Phartiyal J, Scott DN, Peloso M (2015) Women talking about water: feminist subjectivities and intersectional understandings. Can Women’s Stud J Les Cahiers de la Femme Spec Issue Women Water 30(2/3):15–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, HLA (1971 Oxford essays in jurisprudence: second series, Simpson AWB (ed). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1977) The question concerning technology and other essays (trans: Lovitt W). Harper and Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1993) Hölderlin’s Hymne ‘Der Ister’. In: Martin Heidegger Gesamtausgabe, vol 53. Vittorio Klostermann, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

  • Hölderlin F (1984) Hymns and fragments (trans: Sieburth R). Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes OW (1894) Harvard law review 1. Quoted in Weinrib. 1997. Tort law: cases and materials. Emond montgomery, Toronto, pp 15–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Indigenous Peoples’ Earth Charter (1992) Kari-oca, Brazil, May 25–30

    Google Scholar 

  • International River Improvements Act (1955) R.S.C. 1985, c. I-20

    Google Scholar 

  • International River Improvements Regulations (n.d.) C.R.C., c. 982, s. 10

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins W (ed) (2010) The spirit of sustainability. In: Encyclopedia of sustainability, vol 1. Gale, Farmington Hills

    Google Scholar 

  • Kavka G (1978) The futurity problem. In: Sikora RI, Barry B (eds) Obligations to future generations. Temple University Press, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard CM (2009) Aristotle’s function argument. In: Korsgaard (ed) The constitution of agency: essays on practical reason and moral psychology. Oxford University Press, Oxford. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199552733.003.0005

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka W (1989) Liberalism, community and culture. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka W (2002) Contemporary political philosophy: an introduction, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Loughlin M (2010) Foundations of public law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacDonald R (2011) Custom made: for a non-chirographic critical legal pluralism. Can J Law Soc 26(2):301–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maritain J (1951) Man and the state. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Matsuda M (1988) Affirmative action and legal knowledge: planting seeds in plowed-up ground. Harvard Womens Law J 11:1–17

    Google Scholar 

  • McCrudden C (ed) (2013) Understanding human dignity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mickelson K (2000) South, North, international environmental law, and international environmental lawyers. Yearbook Int Environ Law 11:52–81

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore DS, Kosek J, Pandian A (2003) Race, nature, and the politics of difference. Duke University Press, Durham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mutua M (2002) Human rights: a political and cultural critique. University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T (2005) The problem of global justice. Philos Public Aff 33(2):113–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanni M (2007) Principles of water law and administration, national and international, 2nd edn. Taylor & Francis, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Narveson J (1978) Future people and us. In: Sikora RI, Barry B (eds) Obligations to future generations. Temple University Press, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • North DC (1995) The new institutional economics and Third World development. In: Harriss J, Hunter J, Lewis CM (eds) The new institutional economics and third world development. Routledge, London, pp 17–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M (1995) Aristotle on human nature and the foundations of ethics. In: Altham JEJ, Harrison R (eds) World, mind, and ethics: essays on the ethical philosophy of Bernard Williams. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 86–131

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M (2000) Women and human development: the capabilities approach. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M (2002) Capabilities and human rights. In: de Greiff P, Cronin C (eds) Global justice and transnational politics: essays on the moral and political challenges of globalization. MIT Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M (2006) Frontiers of justice. Harvard University Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom E (2008) Doing institutional analysis: digging deeper than markets and hierarchies. In: Ménard C, Shirley MM (eds) Handbook of new institutional economics. Springer, New York, pp 819–848

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1976) On doing the best for our children. In: Bayles MD (ed) Ethics and population. Schenkman, Cambridge, MA, pp 110–115

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1982) Future generations: further problems. Philos Public Aff 11(2):113–172

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry M (1998) The idea of human rights: four inquiries. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner R (1980) A theory of primitive society, with special reference to law. J Law Econ 23(1):1–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (2010) Human rights in the emerging world order. Transl Leg Theory 1(1):31–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Razack S (1998) Looking white people in the eye: gender, race and culture in courtrooms and classrooms. University of Toronto Press, Toronto

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Razack S, Smith M, Thobani S (eds) (2010) States of race: critical race feminism for the twenty-first century. Between the Lines, Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Roach K (2001) The supreme court on trial: judicial activism or democratic dialogue. Irwin Law, Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Salman SMA, McInerney-Lankford S (2004) The human right to water: legal and policy dimensions. World Bank, Washington, DC

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson PA (1954) The pure theory of public expenditure. Rev Econ Stat 36(4):387–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson PA (1955) Diagrammatic exposition of a theory of public expenditure. Rev Econ Stat 37(4):350–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanderson CD (2008) Nipiy wasekimew/clear water: the meaning of water, from the words of the Elders: the interconnections of health, education, law and the environment. PhD thesis, Simon Fraser University. http://summit.sfu.ca/item/9050. Accessed 6 Apr 2020

  • Schwartz T (1978) Obligations to posterity. In: Sikora RI, Barry B (eds) Obligations to future generations. Temple University Press, Philadelphia, pp 3–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (1999) Development as freedom. Anchor Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Shue H (1996) Basic rights: subsistence, affluence and U.S. foreign policy, 2nd edn. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Species at Risk Act. S.C. 2002, c. 29

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon N (1997) Ecofeminist natures: race, gender, feminist theory and political action. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Talbott WJ (2010) Human rights and human well-being. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tasioulas J (2012) Towards a philosophy of human rights. Curr Leg Probl 65(1):1–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tasioulas J (2013) Human rights, legitimacy and international law. Am J Jurisprud 58:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trebilcock MJ (1993) The limits of freedom of contract. Harvard University Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Trebilcock MJ (1997) An introduction to law and economics. Monash Univ Law Rev 23(1):123–158

    Google Scholar 

  • Tu W-m (1972) Li as process of humanization. Philos East West 22(2):187–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • United Nations (2010) The human right to water and sanitation. GA Res. 64/292. UNGAOR, 64th Session. UN Doc A/RES/64/292

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nations (2011) The human right to safe drinking water and sanitation. Res 18/1. UNHRC, 18th Session, UN Doc A/HRC/RES/18/1

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nations Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights [UNCESCR] (2003) General comment no. 15: the right to water (Arts. 11 and 12 of the Covenant), January 20. E/C.12/2002/11

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nations General Assembly [UNGA] (1966) International covenant on civil and political rights, December 16. United Nations, Treaty series, vol 999

    Google Scholar 

  • Urmson JO (trans) (1992) Simplicius: corollaries on place and time (Ancient Commentators on Aristotle) 23:21–29. Bloomsbury Academic, London/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2015) Is dignity the foundation of human rights? In: Cruft R, Liao MS, Renzo M (eds) Philosophical foundations of human rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 117–137

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weinrib EJ (1995) The idea of private law. Harvard University Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiss EB (1990) Our rights and obligations to future generations for the environment. Am J Int Law 84(1):198–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Western Sahara Case. Advisory opinion of 16 October 1975, ICJ reports 1975

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson CF (1989) The headwaters of the public trust: some thoughts on the source and scope of the traditional doctrine. Environ Law 19(425):429

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood MC (2009a) Advancing the sovereign trust of government to safeguard the environment for present and future generations (Part I): ecological realism and the need for a paradigm shift. Environ Law 39(1):43–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood MC (2009b) Advancing the sovereign trust of government to safeguard the environment for present and future generations (Part II): instilling a fiduciary obligation in governance. Environ Law 39(1):91–139

    Google Scholar 

  • World Commission on Environment and Development [WCED] (1987) Our common future. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Graham Mayeda .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Mayeda, G. (2021). Philosophical Issues in Water Law. In: Stefanovic, I.L., Adeel, Z. (eds) Ethical Water Stewardship . Water Security in a New World. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-49540-4_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics