Skip to main content

Autonomy and Shared Citizenship: A ‘Neutral’ Justification for RE?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Religious Education in a Post-Secular Age

Abstract

Triggered by secularization, individualization and increasing religious pluralism, RE has undergone profound changes in Europe and elsewhere. One of the main changes has been the shift from confessional and denominational RE, to non-confessional and nondenominational RE. In spite of its merits, this shift has been criticized frequently, mainly by religious stakeholders who wrongly equate ‘neutrality’ with ‘anti-religiosity’ and ‘atheism’. In this chapter, I will counter this critique and explain what is meant by a ‘neutral’ or ‘reasonable’ justification for non-confessional RE. In order to do so, I will, from a political philosophical perspective, elaborate on the core principles of liberal democratic states and its implications for education in general and for RE in particular. It has been argued that, in these states, confessional RE should no longer be part of the regular school curriculum in state schools because this policy prioritizes religion over non-religion and is, accordingly, not neutral. Alternatively, students should learn about different religions and worldviews in an open and critical way. This way of organizing RE does not only fit with autonomy-based liberalism and its need for shared citizenship, but it also allows that religious as well as non-religious students become aware of the ‘semantic potential’ of religion in post-secular societies. In a final part, some common critiques concerning liberal education and its implications for RE will be addressed and critically evaluated. Until the 1960s, Christianity was the major religion in most European nation states and society was largely influenced by this religion. Today, this Christian dominance belongs to the past and most European nation states are characterized by secularization, but also by ethnic and religious diversity. Although the number of believers in western-Europe decreased substantially and even though the overall impact of religion on public life diminished, the famous secularization thesis (Berger 1967; Bruce 2002, 2011) does not persist in its original form. Rather than saying that religion will disappear, it seems to be more correct to say that religion transformed into a less institutionalized and more individualized and spiritual phenomenon (cf. Davie 1990; Heelas and Woodhead 2005; see also the concept of secularization as a “return of religion in society” in the introduction of this book, pp. 9–12). Besides, nation states worldwide are increasingly confronted with religious terrorism, which is often related to fundamentalist interpretations of Islam.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the difference between denominational and confessional RE, see Bråten 2013, 22–23.

  2. 2.

    Noteworthy exemptions in this classification are Finland, which has a combination of separative, non-denominational and ‘semi’-confessional RE; and the German states Hamburg and Bremen, where RE is integrative, denominational and inter-confessional.

  3. 3.

    Non-confessional RE is, like confessional RE, sometimes also criticized by ‘secular’ stakeholders (e.g. humanists), promoting a general ban of religion – and thus also of all kinds of RE – in public schools.

  4. 4.

    In Belgium, about 30% of the public schools are state schools or governmental schools, i.e. schools funded and established by the state. Most schools (70%) are public, non-governmental schools, i.e. schools funded by the state, but established by a private organization. 99% of these non-governmental schools are Catholic. They are funded on an equal basis as state schools and open for all the students, provided they/their parents agree with the school’s Catholic mission statement.

  5. 5.

    We will not go into further detail here, but it is obvious that my argument has also implications for faith-based schools, especially if they are recognized (and subsidized) by the state.

  6. 6.

    This policy is, for historical reasons, not applied in the region Alsace-Moselle and in the French transoceanic territories.

  7. 7.

    http://www.men.public.lu/fr/actualites/grands-dossiers/systeme-educatif/vie-societe/index.html (accessed 30 January 2020)

  8. 8.

    One example is the libertarian position of Chandran Kukathas. According to Kukathas (2001, 2003), a state’s policy should not be based on the principle of autonomy, but on freedom of conscience and freedom of association. As a consequence, there is no need for an educational system wherein the capacity to act and think in a critical way is developed. Moreover, because every educational system is based on a specific concept of the good life, Kukathas rejects all kinds of compulsory education: “[t]he last thing a liberal state should offer its subjects is education – even if that should be a liberal education” (Kukathas 2001, 323). However, since Kukathas also defends the right to exit, which is in practice impossible without liberal (autonomy-facilitating) autonomy, his view is considered inconsistent at this point.

  9. 9.

    Probably the most well-known court case in this regard is the Wisconsin v. Yoder Supreme Court case (1972, 406, US. 205), wherein the American Supreme Court decided, referring to the freedom of religion, that Amish-children can be exempted from compulsory education from the age of 14 onwards. However, one of the consequences of this decision is that Amish children may not be able to substantially develop the required capacities in order to make autonomous choices. A decision in the other direction – preferring the right to liberal education which gives children “the opportunity to participate in ‘normal’ society” over homeschooling in a ‘symbiotic’ family system – was made by the ECHR Great Chamber in 2019 in the case of Wunderlich v. Germany (appl.18925/15).

  10. 10.

    A common idea among liberal educational philosophers (e.g. Boucher, Callan, Levinson, MacMullen) is that faith-based schools should not and cannot be forbidden in liberal societies (since this would infringe with the core principle of liberty itself), but that state schools are, due to their ‘neutral’ and open character, to be preferred over faith-based schools.

  11. 11.

    For a discussion about Jewish orthodox schools and their refusal to teach in a ‘liberal’ way (e.g. by means of refusing ‘controversial issues’ and avoiding critical dialogue and reflection), see Franken & Levrau 2020 (forthcoming).

References

  • Allport, G. (1954 [1979]). The Nature of Prejudice. New York: Perseus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger, P. (1967). The Sacred Canopy: Elements of a Sociological Theory of Religion. New York: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boucher, F. (2018). Should Liberal States Subsidize Religious Schooling? Studies in Philosophy and Education, 37(2). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-018-9620-9.

  • Bråten, O. M. H. (2013). Towards a Methodology for Comparative Studies in Religious Education. A Study of England and Norway. Münster: Waxmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruce, S. (2002). God is Dead: Secularization in the West. New York: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruce, S. (2011). Secularization: In Defence of an Unfashionable Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callan, E. (1997). Creating Citizens. Political Education and Liberal Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davie, G. (1990). Believing without Belonging: Is This the Future of Religion in Britain? Social Compass, 37(4), 455–469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doyon, F. (2016). Les vertus antiphilosophiquess du cours ECR. In D. Baril & N. Baillargeon (Eds.), La face cachée du cours Ethique et culture religieuse (pp. 67–87). Montréal: Leméac.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C. (2008). Religious Education in Public Schools: An International Human Rights Perspective. Human Rights Law Review, 8(3), 449–473.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (2007). The Child’s Right to an Open Future. In W. Aiken & H. La Follette (Eds.), Whose Child? Children’s Rights, Parental Authority, and State Power (pp. 124–153). Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franken, L., & Levrau, F. (2020—forthcoming). Rejecting ‘Controversial’ Issues in Education: A Case Study of Ultra-orthodox Jewish Schools in Belgium. Religions 11(4), 214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franken, L. (2016). Liberal Neutrality and State Support for Religion. Zürich: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franken, L. (2017a). Coping with Diversity in Religious Education: An Overview. Journal of Beliefs and Values, 38(1), 105–120. https://doi.org/10.1080/13617672.2016.1270504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franken, L. (2017b). State Support for Religion in Belgium: A Critical Evaluation. Journal of Church and State, 59(1), 59–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franken, L. (2018). Religious Studies and Non-confessional RE: Countering the Debates. Religion & Education, 45(2), 155–172. https://doi.org/10.1080/15507394.2018.1452519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franken, L., & Loobuyck, P. (2013). The Future of Religious Education on the Flemish School Curriculum. A Plea for Integrative Religious Education for All. Religious Education, 108(5), 482–498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franken, L., & Loobuyck, P. (Eds.). (2017). Neutrality and Impartiality in RE: An Impossible Aim? Special Issue of British Journal of Religious Education, 39(1), 1–6. https://doi.org/10.1080/01416200.2016.1218219.

  • Gaudin, P. (2014). Neutrality and Impartiality in Public Education: The French Investment in Philosophy, Teaching about Religions, and Moral and Civic Education. British Journal of Religious Education, 39(1), 93–106. https://doi.org/10.1080/01416200.2016.1218221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, A. (1987). Democratic Education. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2002). Glauben und Wissen. Dialog, 1(1), 63–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2006). Religion in the Public Sphere. European Journal of Philosophy, 14(1), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2008). Secularism’s Crisis of Faith. New Perspectives Quarterly, 25(4), 16–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heelas, P., & Woodhead, L. (Eds.). (2005). The Spiritual Revolution: Why Religion is Giving Way to Spirituality. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, R. (Ed.). (2003). International Perspectives on Citizenship, Education and Religious Diversity. London: Routledge Falmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, R. (2004). Rethinking Religious Education and Plurality. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, R. (2014). Signposts—Policy and Practice for Teaching about Religions and Non-religious Worldviews in Intercultural Education. Strasbourg: Council of Europe Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, T. (2008). RS Based RE in Public Schools: A Must for a Secular State. Numen, 55(2–3), 123–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, T. (2011). Why Religion Education, as a Matter of Course, Ought to be Part of the Public School Curriculum. In L. Franken & P. Loobuyck (Eds.), Religious Education in a Plural, Secularised Society. A Paradigm Shift (pp. 131–149). Münster: Waxmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, P. (2002). Introduction: Between Culture and Equality. In P. Kelly (Ed.), Multiculturalism Reconsidered. Culture and Equality and its Critics (pp. 1–17). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukathas, C. (2001). Education and Citizenship in Diverse Societies. International Journal of Educational Research, 35, 319–330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukathas, C. (2003). The Liberal Archipelago. A Theory of Diversity and Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, W. (1995). Multicultural Citizenship. A Theory of Minority Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, M. (1999). The Demands of Liberal Education. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loobuyck, P., & Franken, L. (2011). Toward Integrative Religious Education in Belgium and Flanders. Challenges and Opportunities. British Journal of Religious Education, 33(1), 17–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacMullen, I. (2007). Faith in Schools. Autonomy, Citizenship and Religious Education. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCutcheon, R. T. (Ed.). (1999). The Insider/Outsider Problem in the Study of Religion. London/New York: Cassell.

    Google Scholar 

  • MELS. (2008). Ethics and Religious Culture Program, Secondary Education Cycles One and Two. Québec, QC, Canada: Gouvernement du Québec, Ministère de l’Éducation, du Loisir et du Sport. Retrieved January 30, 2020, from http://www.education.gouv.qc.ca/fileadmin/site_web/documents/dpse/formation_jeunes/ecr_secondary.pdf.

  • Miedema, S. (2012). Maximal Citizenship Education and Interreligious Education in Common Schools. In H. A. Alexander & A. A. Agbaria (Eds.), Religious Schooling in Liberal Democracies: Commitment, Character, and Citizenship (pp. 96–102). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miedema, S., & Bertram-Troost, G. (2008). Democratic Citizenship and Religious Education: Challenges and Perspectives for Schools in the Netherlands. British Journal of Religious Education, 30(2), 123–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1986). The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Grady, K. (2019). Religious Education as a Dialogue with Difference. Fostering Democratic Citizenship through the Study of Religions in Schools. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • OSCE. (2007). The Toledo Guiding Principles on Teaching about Religion or Belief. Warsaw: Office for Democratic Institutions and Human Rights [ODIHR].

    Google Scholar 

  • Pépin, L. (2009). Teaching about Religions in European School Systems. Policy Issues and Trends. London: Alliance Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollefeyt, D., & Lamberigts, M. (2015). De mythe van de neutraliteit. De Standaard, January 13. Retrieved from http://www.standaard.be/cnt/dmf20150317_01584537

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2005 [1993]). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothgangel, M., Jackson, R., & Jäggle, M. (Eds.). (2014b). Religious Education at Schools in Europe. Part 2: Western Europe. Vienna: Vienna University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothgangel, M., Jäggle, M., & Schlag, T. (Eds.). (2016). Religious Education at Schools in Europe. Part 1: Central Europe. Vienna: Vienna University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothgangel, M., Skeie, G., & Jäggle, M. (Eds.). (2014a). Religious Education at Schools in Europe. Part 3: Northern Europe. Vienna: Vienna University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, N. (1968). Secular Education and the Logic of Religion. London: Faber and Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Temperman, J. (2010). State–Religion Relationships and Human Rights Law: Toward a Right to Religiously Neutral Governance. Leiden/Boston: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torfs, R., Pollefeyt, D., & Lamberigts, M. (2015). Het lef om de andere echt te Ontmoeten. De Standaard, January 9. Retrieved March 2, 2018, from http://www.standaard.be/cnt/dmf20150118_01480480.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Leni Franken .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Franken, L. (2021). Autonomy and Shared Citizenship: A ‘Neutral’ Justification for RE?. In: Franck, O., Thalén, P. (eds) Religious Education in a Post-Secular Age. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-47503-1_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-47503-1_11

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-47502-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-47503-1

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics