Skip to main content

Relational Poverty, Domination and Social Esteem: Recognising the Poor’s Agency via a Deliberative Approach to Anti-Poverty Policies

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Poverty, Inequality and the Critical Theory of Recognition

Part of the book series: Philosophy and Poverty ((PPOV,volume 3))

  • 466 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, we provide a normative analysis of the relational dimension of poverty, that is, an account that is concerned with certain patterns of social and political relations amongst poor and non-poor individuals. While a relational dimension of poverty has been increasingly acknowledged in the literature, many share an underdeveloped notion of what exactly this means. One plausible way to develop it is by analysing the inferior social position held by poverty-stricken individuals in terms of an increased risk of being dominated by others and of a systematic lack of esteem. In this understanding, the agency of an impoverished individual is undermined at both the individual and institutional level, divesting those in poverty of the full capacity to make important decisions affecting their lives. In this vein, first, we will argue that this understanding hints at the possibility of recognising the agency of impoverished individuals by rethinking the way we design public policies to alleviate poverty. Second, that a deliberative strategy is a promising way for redressing the relational dimension of poverty by considering the poor as full citizens with power to make important decisions, capable of speaking by and for themselves and of making joint decisions with policy-makers on what should be done to alleviate poverty.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Whether poverty ought to be described in additional terms is an issue we will not be addressing here. We will preliminarily claim that both resourcist and relational elements should be part of an adequate conception of poverty.

  2. 2.

    Indeed, status inferiority or relational deprivation may also result from factors other than problematic social interactions, such as lack of resources. The two basic elements of our hybrid account (namely, lack of resources and relational deprivation) are interlocked in correlations and causal interactions. On the one hand, a person’s lack of resources in comparison with others affects her socio-political standing in a given society. On the other, a person’s lack of valuable socio-political relations in comparison with others impacts her access to resources (Sen 2009; Wolff 2015; Putnam forthcoming).

  3. 3.

    Whether this is true or not is of course an empirical matter. There remains a conceptual question related to the kinds of elements that should be part of an account of poverty. For instance, should an account include only causal elements or should it also include elements that may refer to the experience of the phenomenon without playing an actual causal role in it? Those who assume the latter could argue that even if relational elements had no proper causal role, they should nevertheless be part of an account of poverty.

  4. 4.

    In Laborde and Garrau’s words: “Vulnerability supposes the existence of a relationship of dependency between agents who have the power to act on one another, and potentially, to harm one another” (Laborde and Garrau 2015: 52).

  5. 5.

    Other examples are family configurations in which, due to the absence of equal rights protections, husbands can subjugate wives; or situations in which, given the scarcity of real opportunities to get well-paid and decent work, workers are led to accept unsafe working conditions and low wages imposed by their employers (Pettit 1997: 61).

  6. 6.

    See, for instance, I. M. Young’s account of structural injustice (2012). Structural injustice takes place “when social processes put large categories of persons under a systematic threat of domination or deprivation of the means to develop and exercise their capacities, at the same time as these processes enable others to dominate or have a wide range of opportunities for developing and exercising their capacities” (Young 2012).

  7. 7.

    This aspect is illustrated by Glenn Loury’s remark: in the context of racial discrimination, black people are haunted by “insidious habits of thought” (Loury 2002: 193).

  8. 8.

    In Schuppert’s definition, domination occurs: “if either an agent A (which can be an individual, a group or an institution) has the power to intentionally and arbitrarily interfere with an agent B (which can be an individual or a group) or if an individual’s, a group’s or an institution’s actions and practices structurally disadvantage (i.e., over a longer period of time through an identifiable mechanism), without due concern for her relevant fundamental interests, an agent B with regard to her status as a free and equal person” (Schuppert 2015a: 450). It is relevent to note that Schuppert’s definition relies on an intentional account of domination and differs, thus, from non-intentional ones.

  9. 9.

    One could distinguish between the wrong of the prejudices and stigmas and the harmful consequences that arise from them. Such well-known negative stigmas and prejudices are wrong per se and can be seen as a form of injustice, and very often entail a series of harmful consequences (such as restricting or precluding access to job opportunities) (Axelsen and Bidadanure 2018).

  10. 10.

    We are not taking a stance in the debate about whether mental states may be successfully reduced to behavioural dispositions or any other observable manifestation. Rather, we only wish to highlight the external manifestations of what might otherwise be seen as a private phenomenon.

  11. 11.

    This example is inspired by Anderson’s writings on stigmas and prejudices. On this issue, see: Anderson 2010: 53.

  12. 12.

    Indeed, the background norms governing how social esteem is assigned in this “meritocratic” fashion can be highly problematic. For one thing, judgments of “desert” may be socially and culturally biased or reflect dominant understandings that bear exclusionary and discriminatory consequences.

  13. 13.

    In proposing an institutional approach, we are not denying that individuals may eventually bear responsibility for transforming the social relations in which they are embedded. This is simply not the focus of our analysis here.

  14. 14.

    According to Sharon Krause, this notion of agency as non-sovereignty implies that the meaning of one’s action escapes individual intentionality and requires that others recognise one’s contribution in the public sphere (Krause 2013: 196). Sharon Krause is inspired by Hannah Arendt’s notion of agency as non-sovereignty, and she advances the idea that agency implies an interpersonal criterion. In her view, producing outcomes in the public sphere presupposes that others recognise and respond to one’s action.

  15. 15.

    Institutions (endorsed by the state) are part of the problem; but they may also be part of its solution. If they are given the right design, institutions can work as a means to challenge the inequalities of esteem and power that affect the poor; as having the potential to positively transform interactions amongst the poor and non-poor.

  16. 16.

    Wisor follows Chambers’s distinction. See Chambers, R. (2008). Revolutions in Development Inquiry. London: Earthscan (chapter 4).

  17. 17.

    Extractive and deliberative forms can appear in the same public policy, but in different steps. For instance, it is possible to hold consultations during a first stage, followed by deliberations later.

  18. 18.

    We would link to thank Andrew Walton for this formulation.

  19. 19.

    Axel Honneth’s (1996) theory can be a source of valuable insight into the lack of recognition or the forms of misrecogntion suffered by the poor. Although we take some inspiration from Honneth’s ‘recognition’ account and allude to concepts such as social esteem (one of the three basic forms of recognition in Honneth’s theory), our understanding of recognition in contexts of poverty goes beyond the author’s conception and is detached from the normative assumptions underpinning its value theory and social ontology. For one thing, when analysing the harms of domination and lack of social esteem in contexts of poverty, we are adopting here a broad social egalitarian framework that is independent from Honneth’s own understanding of the “grammar of social conflicts”.

  20. 20.

    First, we acknowledge that resourcist measures are also important. Second, a deliberative approach needs to be sensitive to contextual elements in order to respond more effectively to the problematic social interactions underlying the relational aspect of poverty.

  21. 21.

    We are especially grateful to Gottfried Schweiger for his thorough and very helpful comments and suggestions. Thanks as well to Andrew Walton and Mark Rogers for their reading. Earlier versions were presented at the Hoover Chair of Economic and Social Ethics (Louvain-la-Neuve) and at the workshop on Recognition and Poverty held at Salzburg.

References

  • Abers, Rebecca, et al. 2018. Porto Alegre: Participatory Budgeting and the Challenge of Sustaining Transformative Change. Washington, DC: World Resources Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amighetti, Sara, and Alasia Nuti. 2015. Towards a Shared Redress: Achieving Historical Justice through Democratic Deliberation. The Journal of Political Philosophy 23 (4): 385–405. https://doi.org/10.1111/jopp.12059.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 2010. The Imperative of Integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Avritzer, Leonardo. 2002. Democracy and the Public Space in Latin America. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelsen, David V., and Juliana Bidadanure. 2018. Unequally Egalitarian? Defending the Credentials of Social Egalitarianism. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 22 (3): 335–351. https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2018.1443398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, James. 2006. Deliberative Democracy and the Epistemic Benefits of Diversity. Episteme 3 (3): 175–191. https://doi.org/10.3366/epi.2006.3.3.175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callahan, Kathe. 2007. Citizen Participation: Models and Methods. International Journal of Public Administration 30 (11): 1179–1196. https://doi.org/10.1080/01900690701225366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castel, Robert. 1999. Les métamorphoses de la question sociale: Une chronique du salariat. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, Robert. 2008. Revolutions in Development Inquiry. London: Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Can We Know Better? Reflections for Development. London: Practical Action Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, Stephen L. 1992. Two Kinds of Respect. In Ethics and Moral Personality, ed. John Deigh, 65–78. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deveaux, Monique. 2016. Beyond the Redistributive Paradigm: What Philosophers can Learn from Poor-Led Politics. In Ethical Issues in Poverty Alleviation, ed. Helmut P. Gaisbauer et al., 225–245. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, Marc. 2007. Poverty as a form of oppression. In Freedom From Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor? ed. Thomas Pogge, 133–154. New York: Oxford University Press and UNESCO.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fourie, Carina. 2015. To Praise and to Scorn: The Problem of Inequalities of Esteem for Social Egalitarianism. In Social Equality: On What It Means to Be Equals, ed. Carina Fourie, Fabian Schuppert, and Ivo Wallimann-Helmer, 87–106. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, Nancy. 2010. Scales of justice: emerging political space in a globalisation world. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, Miranda. 2011. Epistemic Contribution as a Central Human Capability. In The Equal Society: Essays on Equality in Theory and Practice, ed. George Hull, 73–90. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fung, Archon. 2003. Survey Article: Recipes for Public Spheres: Eight Institutional Design Choices and Their Consequences. The Journal of Political Philosophy 11 (3): 338–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harding, Sandra. 2004. Introduction: Standpoint Theory as a Site of Political, Philosophic, and Scientific Debate. In The Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader: Intellectual and Political Controversies, ed. Sandra Herding, 1–15. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1996. The struggle for recognition: the moral grammar of social conflits. Cambridge, Massachussets: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel, and Nancy Fraser. 2003. Redistribution or Recognition?: A Political-Philosophical Exchange. New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khader, Serene. 2011. Adaptive Preferences and Women’s Empowerment. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klinenberg, Eric. 2018. Palaces for the People: How Social Infrastructure Can Help Fight Inequality, Polarization, and the Decline of Civic Life. New York: Crown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krause, Sharon R. 2013. Beyond Non-domination: Agency, Inequality and the Meaning of Freedom. Philosophy & Social Criticism 39 (2): 187–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laborde, Cécile and Marie Garrau. 2015. Relational Equality, Non-domination, and Vulnerability. In Social Equality: On What It Means to Be Equals, ed. Carina Fourie, Fabian Schuppert, and Ivo Wallimann-Helmer, 45–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, Hélène. 2013. Deliberation, Cognitive Diversity, and Democratic Inclusiveness: An Epistemic Argument for the Random Selection of Representatives. Synthese 190 (7): 1209–1231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lister, Ruth. 2004. Poverty. London: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loury, Glenn. 2002. The Anatomy of Racial Inequality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McBride, Cillian. 2009. Demanding Recognition: Equality, Respect and Esteem. European Journal of Political Theory 8 (1): 96–108. https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885108096962.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moles, Andres, and Tom Parr. 2018. Distributions and Relations: A Hybrid Account. Political Studies 67 (1): 132–148. https://doi.org/10.1177/0032321718755589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paugam, Serge. 2009. La disqualification sociale: Essai sur la nouvelle pauvreté. Paris: PUF.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 1997. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, Anne. 2003. Recognition and the struggle for political voice. In Recognition Struggles and Social Movements: Contested Identities, ed. B. Hobson, 263–273. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitasse Fragoso, Katarina. 2019. A Relational Egalitarian Account of Poverty: Towards a Deliberative Strategy. PhD dissertation, Catholic University of Louvain.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Daniel. Forthcoming. Poverty as a Social Relation. In Dimensions of Poverty, ed. Valentin Beck, Henning Hahn, and Robert Lepenies [page numbers TBA]. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rank, Mark R. 2005. One Nation, Underprivileged. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya. 2009. The idea of justice. Cambridge, Massachussets: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schuppert, Fabian. 2015a. Non-domination, Non-alienation and Social Equality: Towards a Republican Understanding of Equality. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 18 (4): 440–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015b. Being Equals: Analysing the Nature of Social Egalitarian Relationship. In Social Equality: On What It Means to Be Equals, ed. Carina Fourie, Fabian Schuppert, and Ivo Wallimann-Helmer, 107–126. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Adam. 1976/1776. An Inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations. London: Home University Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, J., et al. 2017. Deliberation across Deeply Divided Societies: Transformative Moments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wisor, Scott. 2012. After the MDGs: Citizen Deliberation and the Post-2015 Development Framework. Ethics & International Affairs 26 (1): 113–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, J., E. Lamb, and E. Szpiro. 2015. A philosophical review of poverty. London: Joseph Rowntree Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, Jonathan. 2019. Poverty, Social Expectations, and The Family. In In: Philosophy and Child Poverty, eds. Nicolás Brando and Gottfried Schweiger. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, J., Lamb, E., Szpiro, E. 2015. A philosophical review of poverty. London: Joseph Rowntree Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris M. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy. In Democracy and Difference, ed. Seyla Benhabib, 120–135. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Inclusion and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Situated Knowledge and Democratic Discussions. In The Politics of Inclusion and Empowerment, ed. John Andersen and Birte Siim, 19–35. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Responsibility for Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pitasse Fragoso, K., Lippmann, P. (2020). Relational Poverty, Domination and Social Esteem: Recognising the Poor’s Agency via a Deliberative Approach to Anti-Poverty Policies. In: Schweiger, G. (eds) Poverty, Inequality and the Critical Theory of Recognition. Philosophy and Poverty, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-45795-2_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics