Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences ((WHPS,volume 3))

  • 281 Accesses

Abstract

Arendt had little interest in the question of women in the philosophical canon. But her concept of natality and its links to reflections on difference, contestation, and multiplicity have struck a chord with many contemporary (and feminist) philosophers. Through her historical and theoretical examinations of the conditions for human life, political life, and ethical life—and for their transgressions—she has become a powerful intellectual figure. Her concept of natality, which focuses on the role of plurality, newness, and spontaneity for political life, offers distinctions and priorities that provide a necessary orientation for reflecting on the contemporary refugee crisis. In an Arendtian spirit, we must defend a conception of an open political sphere that is constantly renewed by newcomers, and that is not reducible to social or cultural identities, in order to protect refugees as obligated by both international conventions and moral relations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Her book on Rahel Varnhagen (Arendt 1957/1997) reflects her interest in exploring the questions of being a woman and a Jew in Germany.

  2. 2.

    Bonnie Honig rejects the standard view that this phrase refers to sexual difference. She claims, “La petite difference is an intra-sex/gender difference” which characterized Rosa Luxemburg’s difference from other women, “the refusal of membership, the choice of difference or distinction over a certain kind of equality (Honig 1995a, b, 151).”

  3. 3.

    This view of women’s issues aligns with her commitment to distinguish social questions from political questions, a view which she also maintained in her controversial 1959 essay on desegregation, “Reflections on Little Rock”.

  4. 4.

    Arendt thought there was nothing intrinsically masculine or feminine about the public realm; similarly, she would reject the view that thought places demands to think in a masculine or feminine way. In this respect, she would differ with Beauvoir’s view that in common usage as well as in scientific thought, “man represents both the positive and the neutral…whereas woman represents only the negative, defined by limiting criteria, without reciprocity” (Beauvoir 1952/1974, xviii).

  5. 5.

    The following four paragraphs are drawn from Schott (2010, 54–5).

  6. 6.

    The difficulty in communicating extreme pain is the subject of Elaine Scarry’s book, The Body in Pain Scarry 1985).

  7. 7.

    Arendt began to address the notion of beginnings in her doctoral dissertation, Love and Saint Augustine, which was published in German in 1929. She introduced the term natality in The Human Condition, published in 1958. When she set about revising her dissertation for English publication in the 1960s, she inserted the term natality in the earlier text to clarify her discussion of beginnings (Arendt 1996). In the first translation of this passage from her dissertation Arendt writes, “Because the world, and thus any created thing, must originate, its being is determined by its origin (fieri)—it becomes, it has a beginning.” In the revised version Arendt writes instead, “To put it differently, the decisive fact determining man as a conscious, remembering being is birth or ‘natality’, that is, the fact that we have entered the world through birth (Arendt 1996, 132–3).”

  8. 8.

    However, below I will argue that this distinction can be very important in reference to the protection of political rights of refugees.

  9. 9.

    In a similar vein, Foucault distinguishes Nietzsche’s genealogy from a search for “lofty origins.” Rather, genealogy follows descent: “it disturbs what was previously considered immobile; it fragments what was thought unified; it shows the heterogeneity of what was imagined consistent with itself (Foucault 1977, 143, 147).”

  10. 10.

    Which doom is also implied by the use of the hydrogen bomb, as Arendt points out.

  11. 11.

    In “Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason” Kant writes, “the human being is evil, cannot mean anything else than that he is conscious of the moral law and yet has incorporated into his maxim the (occasional) deviation from it.” (Kant 1793/2001, 9). And, “This evil is radical, since it corrupts the grounds of all maxims….” (Kant 1793/2001, 83).

  12. 12.

    Arendt reminds us that if one murders, then one has to live with a murderer for the rest of one’s life. This, however, might be more manageable than she fathomed. See, for example, Joshua Oppenheimer’s film, “the Act of Killing” on the mass murders in Indonesia in the 1960s, in which he asks perpetrators to re-stage their crimes.

  13. 13.

    Google search on July 6, 2016.

  14. 14.

    1350 migrants drowned during the course of just one week in April 2015.

  15. 15.

    If one established local areas from which people could seek asylum, it would also help correct for the gender imbalance that emerges when young, single men are more apt to take the dangerous journey.

  16. 16.

    Larking suggests this is a sad echo of the abdication of responsibility of governments in Western Europe during the inter-war period. It was the police who took over responsibility for refugees, and they were given license to act with impunity (Larking 2014. 133).

  17. 17.

    In January 2016, during a rampage against foreigners in the train station in Stockholm, a Swedish teenager was attacked because he had dark hair.

  18. 18.

    Since the civil wars in former Yugoslavia in the 1990s, it has been widely recognized that the imperative “Never Again” has not had the force to stop crimes against humanity and genocide. It may, however, retain force as a regulative ideal to guide moral and political experience.

References

  • Agamben, G. (1995/98). Homo sacer; sovereign power and bare life (D. Heller-Roazen, Trans.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1951/1973). The origins of totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1957/1997). Rahel Varnhagen; The life of a Jewess (L. Weissberg, Ed.; Richard & C. Winston, Trans.). Baltimore: John Hopkins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1958). The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1963/92). Eichmann in Jerusalem; A report on the banality of evil. New York and London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1963b). On revolution. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1996). Love and Saint Augustine (J. V. Scott & J. C. Stark, Ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (2003). Responsibility and judgment (J. Kohn, Ed.). New York: Schocken.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, Peter. (2002). Identifying the unprecedented: Hannah Arendt, totalitarianism, and the critique of sociology. American Sociological Review, 67(6), 804–831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beauvoir, S. de. (192/1974). The second sex. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (1996). The reluctant modernism of Hannah Arendt. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (2004). The rights of others; aliens, residents and citizens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Birmingham, P. (2006). Hannah Arendt and human rights. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Wendy. (1988). Manhood and politics. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Card, C. (1996). The unnatural lottery; character and moral luck. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dietz, M. G. (1991). Hannah Arendt and feminist politics. In C. Pateman & M. L. Shanley (Eds.), Feminist interpretations of political theory (pp. 232–252). Oxford: Polity Press in Association with Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dietz, M. G. (1995). Feminist receptions of Hannah Arendt. In B. Honig (Ed.), Feminist interpretations of Hannah Arendt (pp. 17–50). University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1977). Language, counter-memory, practice; selected essays and interviews (D. F. Bouchard & S. Simon, Trans.). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosz, E. (1990). Contemporary theories of power and objectivity. In S. Gunew (Ed.), Feminist knowledge; critique and construct (pp. 59–120). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honig, B. (1995a). Introduction: The Arendt question in feminism. In B. Honig (Ed.), Feminist interpretations of Hannah Arendt (pp. 1–16). University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honig, B. (1995b). Toward an agonistic feminism: Hannah Arendt and the politics of identity. In B. Honig (Ed.), Feminist interpretations of Hannah Arendt (pp. 135–166). University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1793/2001). Religion and rational theology (A. W. Wood & G. Di Giovanni, Trans., Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleist, N., & Sørensen, N. N. (2015, April). EU’s Løsning på Europas Flygtningskrise er Utilstrækkelig. DIIS impact. Retrieved February 1, 2016, from http://pure.diis.dk/ws/files/118718/diis_impact_drukneulykker_paa_middelhavet_WEB.pdf.

  • Larking, E. (2014). Refugees and the myth of human rights; life outside the pale of law. Farnham and Burlington: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucht, H. (2014, December 23). Cemetery in the Sea betrays Europe’s moral crisis. Retrieved June 12, 2015, from www.huffingtonpost.com.

  • Neiman, S. (2002). Evil in modern thought; an alternative history of philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabinow, P., & Rose, Nikolas. (2006). Biopower today. BioSocieties, 1, 195–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarry, E. (1985). The body in pain; the making and unmaking of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schott, R. M. (2003a). Beauvoir on the ambiguity of evil. In Claudia Card (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schott, R. M. (2003b). Discovering feminist philosophy; knowledge, ethics, politics. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schott, R. M. (2007). Evil, terrorism, and gender. In R. M. Schott (Ed.), Feminist philosophy and the problem of evil. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schott, R. M. (2009). Kant and Arendt on hospitality. In Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik; annual review of law and ethics (Vol. 17, pp. 183–94). Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schott, R. M. (2010). Natality and destruction. In R. M. Schott (Ed.), Birth, death, and femininity; philosophies of embodiment (pp. 49–69). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schott, R. M. (2011). War rape, natality, and genocide. Journal of Genocide Research, 13(1–2), 5–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schott, R. M., & Søndergaard, D. M. (Eds.). (2014). School bullying; new theories in context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tassinari, F. (2016, January 13). All for none, and none for all; life in a broken Europe. In Foreign affairs. Retrieved January 29, 2016, from https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/western-europe/2016-01-13/all-none-and-none-all.

  • Young-Bruehl, E. (1982). Hannah Arendt; for love of the world. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robin May Schott .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Schott, R.M. (2020). Arendt, Natality, and the Refugee Crisis. In: Thorgeirsdottir, S., Hagengruber, R. (eds) Methodological Reflections on Women’s Contribution and Influence in the History of Philosophy. Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-44421-1_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics