Skip to main content

The Nature of Scientific Models: Abstract Artifacts That Determine Fictional Systems

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Abstract Objects

Abstract

Cartwright (How the laws of physics lie. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1983) said: “A model is a work of fiction”. Since then a good deal of philosophical literature has advocated that scientific models are fictional objects. In this contribution we will try to show that Cartwright’s dictum is correct, but that scientific models are not fictional objects. We distinguish between models as abstract objects and the fictional systems that they determine, where the latter can be in partial correspondence with parcels of the world. We also contrast our view with other recent approaches for scientific models, among them Contessa’s dualist view as well as Frigg’s, Toon’s and Levy’s accounts based on Walton’s Pretence Theory.

This contribution has received financial support from FEDER/Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness under the project FFI2013-41415-P, and from FEDER/Spanish Ministry of Science, Innovation and Universities–State Research Agency under the project FFI2017-82534-P. This article also contributes to the project PICT-2014-1741 with financial support from ANPCyT, Argentina.

The order of the authors has no relevance. de Donato-Rodríguez, Xavier and Falguera, José L. have been contributed equally to the elaboration of this chapter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In a later work, Cartwright (1999, ch. 2) invites us to analyse SMs as fables.

  2. 2.

    See Godfrey-Smith (2009) for a study of the analogy between fictional systems and fictional characters and for a revision of recent contributions to the analysis of SMs.

  3. 3.

    Walton (1990) and Everett (2013), among others, provide some important fictionalist accounts on fictional discourse, such as that given by literary contexts. Besides fictionalist approaches on fictional characters, there are fictionalist views on putative abstract entities from mathematics, semantics and so on (e.g., numbers, concepts, propositions, etc.) that reject the existence of such entities. In the case of mathematical discourse, fictionalism has found contenders such as Field (1980), Balaguer (1998), Melia (2000), or Yablo (2001).

  4. 4.

    Obviously, this requires posing the problem of the semantic evaluation of sentences that contain expressions about such fictional entities. Let us postpone this question for something later; in Sect. 8.3 and 8.5 of this paper.

  5. 5.

    In fact, as far as abstract objects are concerned, Frigg (2010a, b) remains neutral about their existence, though he applies Walton’s fictionalist strategy to understand how SMs work; the same can be said of Frigg and Nguyen (2016).

  6. 6.

    In fact, Frigg (2010a, b) presents what he calls a model-system as a fictional object (or imaginary object). And although a model-system is, in some sense, an SM, he finally adopts an imaginative answer regarding what a scientific model is as he defends the idea that every component, and every combination of components, which he distinguishes in a general picture of scientific modeling (excluded the target-system), can be called the model.

  7. 7.

    Levy (2012) formerly endorsed a direct view too (according to him, there are no intermediate model systems), and he also articulated his view on how scientific modelling works by appealing to Walton’s make-believe theory. In a subsequent paper, Levy (2015) defends a fictionalist position as well, while attempting to improve it by appealing to Yablo’s notion of partial truth.

    Our arguments against Levy’s position do not differ greatly from those we have against Toon’s view.

  8. 8.

    Contessa speaks of an SM as an imaginary object solely for what he calls ‘fictional models’. See Sect. 8.3 below.

  9. 9.

    For Contessa, SM and fictional characters are, both, imaginary objects, and these must to be considered as abstract objects in order to account for the semantic assessment of sentences about these kind of entities (as we shall see below). The actual (or real) world is viewed as consisting of both concrete and abstract entities for someone adopting a realist approach regarding abstract entities.

  10. 10.

    Strictly, Contessa has proposed the dual ontological nature for the kind of SM that he calls “fictional models”.

  11. 11.

    Walton himself would not necessarily be antirealist in relation to numbers or propositions.

  12. 12.

    We omit Godfrey-Smith’s (2006) approach from consideration in this paper, as part of our criticism is also applicable to this perspective. According to his view, SMs are imaginary entities that would be concrete if they existed. On the other hand, and as Morrison (2015, 98) reminds us, even if we accepted that it could be possible for SMs to be concrete, this would not affect their condition of being idealisations of their targets.

  13. 13.

    We should recall that, in the direct approach, a model description, equation, or material entity helps to extract imaginings to represent aspects of the world (a real entity which is the purported target of our modelling). Only with difficulty can this approach account for the case in which purported targets do not exist.

  14. 14.

    Here we speak of the relation of determination in a semantic sense, in order to establish what an intensional object is directly about. So, in the case of a fictional content it is directly about a specific fictional object–i.e., a fictional character, a fictional place, a fictional kind, a fictional situation, etc.

  15. 15.

    In this sense, we should distinguish the case in which a novelist conceives some fictional scientist formulating a new SM–or postulating a new theoretical entity–(where the scientist and the SM construed by him–or the theoretical entity in question–are fictional in the sense that they exist thanks to the novel and its creation by the novelist) from the case in which an actual scientist construes a new SM–or postulates a new theoretical entity–to account for a certain (set of) phenomenon(a). The SM in the novel–let us suppose that it is even conveniently detailed–is not truly a SM, i.e. conceived for scientific purposes, but just because of the plot of the novel. Nevertheless, it will be easy to check that our approach can obviously account for these fictional cases as abstract artifacts, because the conceived SM in a novel is determined by that novel in a similar way to a character in a work of fiction (for instance, the Sherlock-Holmes-character of Doyle’s stories or the Hobbit-kind in Tolkien’s novels). Only in the case where a SM serves for actual scientific purposes and it has been construed by an actual scientist or group of scientists, we are facing an intensional entity that conveniently tries to satisfy scientific standards and that is construed with the purpose of understanding the real concrete world. This proposal is also accounting for cases in which scientists don’t believe that the SM stands for a real concrete system (or systems), as for example with the Bohr’s atom model nowadays. (The authors of this article want to thank an anonymous referee for his/her helpful comments at this point that lead us to clarify this issue.)

  16. 16.

    We assume that an SM can have more than an intended target system; for example, Bohr’s atomic model has many atoms (especially of hydrogen) as its target systems.

  17. 17.

    Here we use “fictional world” in an informal way, accepting that they can be incoherent or incomplete. According to Zalta (1983, 1988), it would be better to call them “fictional situations”, because, in his Abstract Object Theory a world is consistent and complete. Zalta himself (see Zalta 2000) makes a useful comparison between Walton’s Pretence Theory and his Axiomatic Abstract Objects Theory and considers the notion of story (in his technical sense) as analogous to the notion of a world of fiction (stories are kinds of situations–incomplete possible worlds–that are authored by concrete entities (the writer(s) or the author(s) of the story)).

  18. 18.

    These comments are inspired by Thomasson (1999), specifically her views on abstract artifacts and their dependences.

  19. 19.

    J. Díez (at the end of his contribution to this volume) says: “But, what abstract object can it be? Of course, the concept phlogiston exists, as the meaning of the word in the theory or model-description; but to claim that the piece in the model stands-for/determines the concept is odd.” And later he says: “But some accounts commit with stronger abstractionism, either accepting possible/fictional systems as abstract entities determined by the model as a whole (cf. Donato and Falguera, this volume), or abstract objects as entities stood for parts of the model that aim but “fail” to stand for the aimed concrete entity (caloric, ether, etc.), or both.” These comments are a little bit confusing. Attending to them, in the following we try to clarify our position.

    First, we consider that the complex intensional entity expressed by some (different) material support(s) for a scientific model exists, and that this entity is the scientific model. If Díez accepts that concepts as “PHLOGISTON” exists, it is difficult to understand that he doesn’t accept complex intensional entities as those expressed by material supports for scientific models. And if he were assuming those entities, why they are not part of his account of scientific modelling?

    Second, other researchers, advocating for the make-believe account for scientific models (see the contribution of Salis-Frigg-Nguyen in this volume), are assuming now the necessity to consider the content (or intension) of the model description, but they are more interested in the internal process of a human subject related to his imaginations than in the intersubjective content. Against them, we are not very interested in the subjective imaginations (though we don’t reject them), because it entails to recuperate the psychologist approach to epistemic–in fact, to ontoepistemosemantics–issues, superseded at the beginning of the twentieth century by several authors within the analytic philosophy (thanks to Frege, Carnap, and Popper, among others).

    Third, we do not say that the piece in the model stands for the concept (even accepting that the intensional entity which is expressed by that piece is a complex concept, something which we accept). Obviously, that claim is odd, but it is not our claim. It is odd because the verb “to stand for” seems to require the previous existence of the entity which is stood for a piece of material support (as representamen), but in the case of a scientific model–understood as an intensional entity–there is no such entity prior to the first piece of material support (as representamen) for the model which is created by its author(s). For us, the scientific model (as an intensional entity expressed by some piece of material support) determines a fictional system. This latter claim is not odd; it is the usual way to establish the relationship between a representamen (especially when it is a linguistic expression) and its content or intension. Only when a corresponding piece of material support expresses a scientific model with an existing target in our actual world it makes sense to speak of “standing for” in order to say that the piece of material support [that expresses a scientific model (as intensional entity)] stands for the corresponding target.

    Fourth, in any case, Díez gives a better characterization of our view in the footnote 12 of his contribution to this volume.

  20. 20.

    In any case, though we assume that these structures have notions as components, they do not necessarily have to be considered as Fregean propositions (or groups of Fregean propositions).

  21. 21.

    See for example Suppes (1960), van Fraassen (1980), Balzer et al. (1987).

  22. 22.

    This is something that could be captured by Zalta’s Abstract Objects Theory (ZAOT), in which an abstract object is determined by a group of properties, and these properties constitute the object in question. Abstract objects are introduced in Zalta’s theory by means of a comprehension axiom scheme which establishes that, for a given condition (or complex of conditions) φ, there is an abstract object that has (encodes) exactly those properties (see Zalta 1983 and 1988). In de Donato and Falguera (2016), we make use of ZAOT in order to present an account of scientific theories, ideal objects and the referents of theoretical terms as special kinds of abstract objects (or more particularly, making use also of Thomasson’s ideas, abstract artifacts).

  23. 23.

    See §3 for sentences (1) and (2).

  24. 24.

    Toon (2012) adopts a similar position in relation to fictional and metafictional statements.

  25. 25.

    In the case of intrafictional statements, the complete operator would be “it is fictional in the work (novel) that…”.

  26. 26.

    It should be kept in mind that an intrafictional statement could always be asserted as a true metafictional statement. Or, in other way, “p, when uttered as a metafictional claim, is true iff p is fictional when uttered as an intrafictional claim” (Frigg 2010a, 263).

  27. 27.

    They can also compare two fictional objects (from different works).

  28. 28.

    Remember that in a fictionalist approach, fictions are nothing; they do not have any kind of existence.

  29. 29.

    Allan Pinkerton (1819–1884) was the real detective who was reputed to have discovered a plot to murder A. Lincoln.

  30. 30.

    Contrast this with the comparison between Holmes and Pinkerton in terms of their relative cleverness, which is made in the story. It is far from obvious how a contender of the Pretence View can manage these cases and explain the difference between them. See about this the discussion in Zalta (2000, § 5).

  31. 31.

    A wider analysis for the problems of paraphrases to transfictional statements according to Pretence Theory can be found in Zalta (2000). See also Godfrey-Smith (2009) for the consideration of some critical comments on Frigg’s analysis of transfictional sentences.

  32. 32.

    The example is discussed by Toon (2012) and also by García-Carpintero (2010).

  33. 33.

    Walton’s theory is indeed antirealist regarding the issue of fictional entities, though he does not have the same problems with other alleged abstract objects (such as numbers or propositions). See Walton (1990, 390).

  34. 34.

    Recall here our note 4 above.

  35. 35.

    We leave the analysis and criticism of Levy’s (2015) new account in terms of Yablo’s partial truth for a future paper.

References

  • Baberousse, A., & Ludwig, P. (2009). Models as fictions. In M. Suárez (Ed.), Fictions in science. Philosophical essays in modeling and idealizations (pp. 56–73). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (1998). Platonism and anti-Platonism in mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W., Moulines, C. U., & Sneed, J. D. (1987). An architectonic for science: The structuralist program. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world. A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2010). Scientific models and fictional objects. Synthese, 172, 215–229, 2010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Donato-Rodríguez, X., & Falguera, J. L. (2016). On fictions, theoretical entities, and ideal objects: Applying Zalta’s abstract objects theory to scientific theories. In G. Borbone & K. Brzechczyn (Eds.), Idealization XIV: Models in science (pp. 13–42). Leiden/Boston: Brill/Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1914). La théorie physique son objet et sa structure (2nd ed.). Paris: Chevalier et Rivière.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett, A. (2013). The nonexistent. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1993). Fictionalism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XVIII, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010a). Models and fiction. Synthese, 172(2), 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010b). Fiction in science. In J. Woods (Ed.), Fictions and models: New essays (pp. 247–287). Munich: PhilosophiaVerlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2016). The fiction view of models reloaded. The Monist, 99, 225–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • García-Carpintero, M. (2010). Fictional entities, theoretical models and figurative truth. In R. Frigg & M. C. Hunter (Eds.), Beyond mimesis and convention. Representation in art and science (pp. 139–168). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 725–740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Models and fictions in science. Philosophical Studies, 143, 101–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2012). Models, fictions, and realism: Two packages. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 738–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2015). Modeling without models. Philosophical Studies, 172, 781–798.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2000). Weaseling away the indispensability argument. Mind, 109, 453–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2015). Reconstructing reality. Models, mathematics, and simulations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2009). Scientific fictions as rules of inference. In M. Suárez (Ed.), Fictions in science. Philosophical essays on modelling and idealisation (pp. 158–178). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1960). A comparison of the meaning and uses of models in mathematics and the empirical sciences. Synthese, 12, 287–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. L. (1999). Fiction and metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (2012). Models as make-believe. Imagination, fiction and scientific representation. New York: Palgrave/Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaihinger, H. (1911). Die Philosophie des Als Ob. Berlin: von Reuther & Reichard.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. L. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe. On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2001). Go figure: A path through fictionalism. In P. French & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy volume XXV: Figurative language (pp. 72–102). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (1983). Abstract objects. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (1988). Intensional logic and the metaphysics of intentionality. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (2000). The road between pretense theory and abstract object theory. In T. Hofweber & A. Everett (Eds.), Empty names, fiction, and the puzzles of non-existence (pp. 117–148). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to José L. Falguera .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

de Donato-Rodríguez, X., Falguera, J.L. (2020). The Nature of Scientific Models: Abstract Artifacts That Determine Fictional Systems. In: Falguera, J.L., Martínez-Vidal, C. (eds) Abstract Objects. Synthese Library, vol 422. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-38242-1_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics