Skip to main content

Law, Secularism, and the Evolution of the ‘Human’ in International Legal Discourse and Global Governance

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Why Religion? Towards a Critical Philosophy of Law, Peace and God

Part of the book series: Law and Religion in a Global Context ((LRGC,volume 2))

  • 256 Accesses

Abstract

Historical records establish that before 1700 the concept of ‘religion’ as separate from that of ‘society’ or ‘politics’ was non-existent. As such, a ‘religious’ foundation for political transformation or military intervention was inseparable from its social basis; the temporal intermingled with the divine. Separation of the church and state is a relatively modern invention, scholars argue, and the wars preceding it were fought with religious sentiments present and largely intact. In a world so designed, religion regulated war, designated who and what constituted a causus belli or a ‘just cause’ for waging war, and stipulated terms and conditions of engagement and ultimately of peace itself. When the Spanish and the Portuguese embarked on the conquistadorian missions in the New World, Pope Alexander VI, himself, saw to it that the plunder and extermination of the natives that followed be veiled in the ‘just war’ rhetoric. In the 14th century, however, with the balance of power shifting from Popes to Kings and, in the 17th century, with the inauguration of the concept of the state arranged according to a legal and constitutional order, the notion of the secular took a firm root in the European political consciousness issuing subsequently in a revolutionary turn away from naturalism toward positivism and social constructivism. The following paper traces the development of the concept of secularization and evolution of the juridico-political discourse and of the ‘human’ subject in international law along with its social ramifications, while also paying attention to the lessened influence—if not an altogether commanding decline—of the religious or divinely inspired laws, which emphasized harmony and peaceful cohabitation of all beings. In so doing, I shall seek to hint at a gradual humanization of international law and accompanying judicialization of politics, whereby customarily absolute sovereign prerogatives and incontrovertible ‘acts of state’ have become subjects of increased scrutiny, legal qualification, and accountability. Furthermore, I shall trace the historical evolution of the cosmopolitan sensibility and the conception of human subjectivity to which it gave rise under international law and, in so doing, delineate the evolving human-centered, as opposed to the traditionally state-centered, understanding of international law, international adjudication, and their cumulative impact on state behavior and global governance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    St. Augustine (1988), p. 633.

  2. 2.

    Taylor (2011).

  3. 3.

    See Footnote 2.

  4. 4.

    Calhoun, et al. (2010), p. 25.

  5. 5.

    Brown (2010), p. 89.

  6. 6.

    Koskennieni (2001).

  7. 7.

    Pinker (2011).

  8. 8.

    Blaise Pascal quoted in Pinker (2011).

  9. 9.

    See Footnote 7.

  10. 10.

    It might be worth reflecting here on Martin Heidegger’s idea of the “standing-reserve”. According to the philosopher, the citizen is to be treated instrumentally, as a means to an end, a “standing-reserve” ready to take up arms and shed blood in the name of the state’s short and long-term objectives.

  11. 11.

    Held (2005).

  12. 12.

    Brett (2012).

  13. 13.

    Kant (1978), p. 128.

  14. 14.

    Pinker (2011), p. 180.

  15. 15.

    See Footnote 14.

  16. 16.

    Pinker (2011), p. 181.

  17. 17.

    See Footnote 16.

  18. 18.

    Finnis (1980), pp. 83–84.

  19. 19.

    Bovarnick et al. (2011), p. 11.

  20. 20.

    Bovarnick et al. (2011), p. 22.

  21. 21.

    See Footnote 19.

  22. 22.

    Sharma (2008), p. 11.

  23. 23.

    Thomas Aquinas—Summa—IIaIIae 40, in Sharma (2008).

  24. 24.

    Sharma (2008), p. 14.

  25. 25.

    Vattel (1797), p. 586.

  26. 26.

    Hayman (2002), p. 3.

  27. 27.

    Hayman (2002), p. 4.

  28. 28.

    Locke (1998), p. 303.

  29. 29.

    Walzer (2000), p. 304.

  30. 30.

    Kolb and Hyde (2012), p. 22.

  31. 31.

    See Footnote 30.

  32. 32.

    See Footnote 30.

  33. 33.

    Kolb and Hyde (2012), p. 38.

  34. 34.

    Kolb and Hyde (2012), p. 41.

  35. 35.

    Bovarnick et al. (2011), p. 20.

  36. 36.

    See Footnote 33.

  37. 37.

    Detter De Lupis (1987), p. 123.

  38. 38.

    International Red Cross. The Geneva Conventions of 1949 and their Additional Protocols. http://www.icrc.org/eng/war-and-law/treaties-customary-law/geneva-conventions/overview-geneva-conventions.htm.

  39. 39.

    See Footnote 38.

  40. 40.

    Kolb and Hyde (2012), p. 41.

  41. 41.

    International Red Cross. Declaration Respecting Maritime Law. Paris, 16 April 1856. http://www.icrc.org/applic/ihl/ihl.nsf/Treaty.xsp?action=openDocument&documentId=10207465E7477D90C12563CD002D65A3.

  42. 42.

    Kolb and Hyde (2012), p. 53.

  43. 43.

    Starke (1963), p. 423.

  44. 44.

    Kolb and Hyde (2012), p. 54.

  45. 45.

    Bovarnick et al. (2011), p. 19.

  46. 46.

    Bovarnick et al. (2011), p. 20.

  47. 47.

    Kolb and Hyde (2012), p. 55.

  48. 48.

    Kolb and Hyde (2012), pp. 45–49.

  49. 49.

    Rolin in Koskenemmi (2001), p. 79.

  50. 50.

    Fiore in Koskenemmi (2001), pp. 54–55.

  51. 51.

    Meant in the Kantian sense as a state of cultivation of human faculties manifested in diplomacy and popular conscience.

  52. 52.

    Koskenemmi (2001), p. 56.

  53. 53.

    Koskenemmi (2001), p. 57.

  54. 54.

    Kelsen (1957), pp. 235–244.

  55. 55.

    Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (1969). http://legal.un.org/ilc/texts/instruments/english/conventions/1_1_1969.pdf.

  56. 56.

    The UN Declaration of Human Rights, Article 1. http://www.un.org/en/documents/udhr/.

  57. 57.

    Teitel (2011).

  58. 58.

    Pentassuglia (2009), p. 13.

  59. 59.

    Barnett (2011), p. 23.

  60. 60.

    See Footnote 59.

  61. 61.

    See Footnote 59.

  62. 62.

    Teitel (2011), p. 7.

  63. 63.

    An array of international and regional courts and tribunals exists for the purpose of administering justice in accordance with international law, such as: Central American Court of Justice; the Inter-American Court of Human Rights; Court of Justice of the Andean Community; Court of Justice of the EFTA; Benelux Court of Justice; Court of Justice of the EU; the European Court of Human Rights; the International Tribunal for the Law of the Sea; Eastern Caribbean Supreme Court; Caribbean Court of Justice, ECOWAS Community Court of Justice; COMESA Court of Justice; African Court of Human and People’s Rights; East African Court of Justice; International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda; Special Court for Sierra Leone; Special Tribunal for Lebanon; International Court of Justice; International Criminal Court; Permanent Court of Arbitration; International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia; Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia (Khmer Rouge Tribunal), to name a few.

  64. 64.

    Teitel (2011).

  65. 65.

    The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-law-ethics/.

  66. 66.

    Hart (1994), p. 113.

  67. 67.

    A view maintained by Ronald Dworkin.

  68. 68.

    Armour (2017).

  69. 69.

    Burke (1788).

  70. 70.

    See Footnote 69.

  71. 71.

    See Footnote 69.

  72. 72.

    Madison (1788).

  73. 73.

    See Footnote 72.

  74. 74.

    Friedman (1967), p. 154.

  75. 75.

    See Footnote 74.

  76. 76.

    See Footnote 74.

  77. 77.

    The philosophy of values posits that “values” are “real, objective and autonomous essences (Wesenheiten) which can be intuitively experienced and apprehended by man and therefore constitute a source of obligation”. See Friedman (1967), p. 197 (see also Aristotle, Hartmann, Pascal, Scheler).

  78. 78.

    Fuller (1964), p. 5.

  79. 79.

    Fuller (1964), p. 6.

  80. 80.

    Finnis (1980), p. 275.

  81. 81.

    See Footnote 80.

  82. 82.

    Legal Positivism. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://www.iep.utm.edu/legalpos/.

  83. 83.

    Natural law theory denies the doctrine of separation of law and morals. On this reading, laws, statutes, proclamations cannot be legally valid if they are morally illegitimate and if they should be so [invalidly] enacted, they cannot hold a legitimate sway or power over those subservient to them.

  84. 84.

    Fuller (1964), pp. 46–91.

  85. 85.

    Fuller (1964), p. 192.

  86. 86.

    Finnis (1980), p. 283.

  87. 87.

    Peterson (2017), p. 457.

  88. 88.

    See Footnote 87.

  89. 89.

    See Mullerson (2002), p. 7: “Law is never an end in itself. It is an instrument for achieving or preserving certain ends. If we take today’s international law, those ends encompass general purposes such as peace, economic development, a clean environment, the fight against terrorism and for human dignity, rational exploitation of renewable natural resources as well as quite concrete objectives such as building dams and guaranteeing access to the sea for landlocked states. This is the content or context of international law and neither is really formal”.

  90. 90.

    Chen (2015), p. 15.

  91. 91.

    Chen (2015), p. 16.

  92. 92.

    See Footnote 91.

  93. 93.

    See Footnote 91.

  94. 94.

    Murphy (2012), p. 15.

  95. 95.

    Trimble (1990), p. 818.

  96. 96.

    Kelsen (2002), p. xxi.

  97. 97.

    Kelsen (1967), p. 4.

  98. 98.

    Kelsen quoted in Beyleveld and Brownsword (1986), p. 240.

  99. 99.

    Ibid., p. 241.

  100. 100.

    Kelsen (1967), p. 59.

  101. 101.

    Kelsen (1967), p. 345.

  102. 102.

    Kelsen (1967), p. 346.

  103. 103.

    Kelsen (1967), p. 347.

  104. 104.

    See Footnote 103.

  105. 105.

    Beardsworth (2011).

  106. 106.

    It is important to note that dignity in legal and philosophical language remains a conceptually contested concept. Both, the utilitarian and deontological views compete for recognition and suggest themselves in different periods of the concept’s historical evolution.

  107. 107.

    McCrudden (2013), p. 2.

  108. 108.

    Reidy (2007), p. 58.

  109. 109.

    Quoted in Jacobson (1997), p. 107.

  110. 110.

    Jacobson (1997), p. 107.

  111. 111.

    Teitel (2011), p. 52.

  112. 112.

    Teitel (2011), p. 35.

  113. 113.

    Pentassuglia (2009), p. 39.

  114. 114.

    See Footnote 113.

References

  • Armour J (2017) Mechanization of law. https://www.law.ox.ac.uk/research-and-subject-groups/research-collection-law-and-technology/blog/2017/03/mechanisation-law

  • Barnett M (2011) Empire of humanity: a history of humanitarianism. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Beardsworth R (2011) Cosmopolitanism and international relations theory. Polity, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bovarnick JA et al (2011) Law of war deskbook. The United States Army Judge Advocate General’s Legal Center and School, Charlottesville

    Google Scholar 

  • Brett R (2012) Did the stoics invent human rights? Oxford studies in ancient philosophy, supplementary volume, Virtue and happiness: Essays in honour of Julia Annas, pp 149–169

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown W (2010) The sacred, the secular, and the profane: Charles Taylor and Karl Marx. In: Calhoun C et al (eds) Varieties of secularism in a secular age. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Beyleveld D, Brownsword R (1986) Law as a moral judgment. Sweet & Maxwell, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke E (1788) At the trial of warren hastings. http://www.bartleby.com/268/6/3.html

  • Calhoun C et al (eds) (2010) Varieties of secularism in a secular age. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen LC (2015) An introduction to contemporary international law: a policy-oriented perspective. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • de Vattel E (1797) The law of nations. Or, Principles of the law of nature, applied to the conduct and affairs of nations and sovereigns, with three early essays on the origin and nature of natural law and on luxury. Kapossy B, Whitmore R (eds), Liberty Fund, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Detter De Lupis I (1987) The law of war. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis J (1980) Natural law and natural rights. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman W (1967) Legal theory. Stevens & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller LL (1964) The morality of law. Yale University Press, New Haven and London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayman R et al (eds) (2002) Jurisprudence classical and contemporary: from natural law to postmodernism. West Group, St. Paul

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1994) The concept of law. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Held D (2005) Principles of cosmopolitan order. In: Bertram C et al (eds) The political philosophy of cosmopolitanism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hugo V (1888) The works of Victor Hugo: the man who laughs. Athenaeum Society, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1978) Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view. Feffer and Simmons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1957) What is justice? justice, law, and politics in the mirror of science: collected essays. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1967) Pure theory of law. University of California Press, Berkley

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (2002) Introduction to the problems of legal theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolb R, Hyde R (2012) An introduction to the international law of armed conflicts. Hart Publishing, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Koskenniemi M (2001) The gentle civilizer of nations: the rise and fall of international law 1870–1960. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson D (1997) Rights across borders. The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke J (1988) Two treatises of government. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Madison J (1788) The alleged tendency of the new plan to elevate the few at the expense of the many considered in connection with representation. Federalist 57, 19 Feb 19 1788. http://www.constitution.org/fed/federa57.htm

  • McCrudden C (2013) In pursuit of human dignity: an introduction to current debates. University of Michigan Public Law Research Paper No. 309. Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2218788

  • Mullerson R (2002) Reviews of Koskenniemi M (2001). Eur J Int Law 13: 727–735. http://www.ejil.org/pdfs/13/3/496.pdf

  • Murphy S (2012) Principles of international law. Thomson Reuters, St. Paul

    Google Scholar 

  • Pentassuglia G (2009) Minority rights, minority groups and judicial discourse in international law: a comparative perspective. Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Leiden

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson MJ (2017) Politics and law in international environmental governance. In: Sandholtz W, Whytock C (eds) Research handbook on the politics of international law. Edward Elgar, Northampton

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S (2011) The better angels of our nature. Viking Penguin Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Reidy D (2007) On the philosophy of law. Thomson Wadsworth, Belmont

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharma SK (2008) Reconsidering the jus ad bellum/jus in bello distinction. In: Stahn C, Kleffner JK (eds) Jus post bellum towards a law of transition from conflict to peace. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Starke JG (1963) An introduction to international law. Butterworths, London

    Google Scholar 

  • St. Augustine (1988) The city of God. In: Gochberg DS (ed) Classics of western thought: the ancient world, Harcourt, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor C (2011) Western secularity. In: Calhoun C et al (eds) Rethinking secularism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Teitel R (2011) Humanity’s law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Trimble P (1990) International law, world order, and critical legal studies. Stanf Law Rev 42(3):811–845

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer M (2000) Just and unjust wars. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joanna K. Rozpedowski .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Rozpedowski, J.K. (2020). Law, Secularism, and the Evolution of the ‘Human’ in International Legal Discourse and Global Governance. In: Bunikowski, D., Puppo, A. (eds) Why Religion? Towards a Critical Philosophy of Law, Peace and God. Law and Religion in a Global Context, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-35484-8_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-35484-8_11

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-35483-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-35484-8

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics