Skip to main content

On the Mathematical Constitution and Explanation of Physical Facts

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Quantum, Probability, Logic

Part of the book series: Jerusalem Studies in Philosophy and History of Science ((JSPS))

  • 673 Accesses

Abstract

The mathematical nature of modern physics suggests that mathematics is bound to play some role in explaining physical reality. Yet, there is an ongoing controversy about the prospects of mathematical explanations of physical facts and their nature. A common view has it that mathematics provides a rich and indispensable language for representing physical reality but that, ontologically, physical facts are not mathematical and, accordingly, mathematical facts cannot really explain physical facts. In what follows, I challenge this common view. I argue that, in modern natural science, mathematics is constitutive of the physical. Given the mathematical constitution of the physical, I propose an account of explanation in which mathematical frameworks, structures, and facts explain physical facts. In this account, mathematical explanations of physical facts are either species of physical explanations of physical facts in which the mathematical constitution of some physical facts in the explanans are highlighted, or simply explanations in which the mathematical constitution of physical facts are highlighted. In highlighting the mathematical constitution of physical facts, mathematical explanations of physical facts make the explained facts intelligible or deepen and expand the scope of our understanding of them. I argue that, unlike other accounts of mathematical explanations of physical facts, the proposed account is not subject to the objection that mathematics only represents the physical facts that actually do the explanation. I conclude by briefly considering the implications that the mathematical constitution of the physical has for the question of the unreasonable effectiveness of the use of mathematics in physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Steiner (1998, p. 9) argues that there are two problems with Wigner’s formulation of question of the “unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences.” First, Wigner ignores the cases in which “scientists fail to find appropriate mathematical descriptions of natural phenomena” and the “mathematical concepts that never have found an application.” Second, Wigner focuses on individual cases of successful applications of mathematical concepts, and these successes might have nothing to do with the fact that a mathematical concept was applied. Steiner seeks to formulate the question of the astonishing success of the applicability of mathematics in the natural sciences in a way that escapes these objections. He argues that in their discoveries of new theories, scientists relied on mathematical analogies. Often these analogies were ‘Pythagorean’, meaning that they were inexpressible in any other language but that of pure mathematics. That is, often the strategy that physicists pursued to guess the laws of nature was Pythagorean: “they used the relations between the structures and even the notations of mathematics to frame analogies and guess according to those analogies” (ibid., pp. 4–5). Steiner argues that although not every guess, or even a large percentage of the guesses, was correct, this global strategy was astonishingly successful.

    Steiner’s reasoning and examples are intriguing and deserve an in-depth study, which, for want of space, I need to postpone for another opportunity. I believe, though, that such a study will not change the main thrust of my analysis of the question of the mathematical constitution of the physical and its implications for the questions of mathematical explanations of physical facts and the “unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences”.

  2. 2.

    For a list of Pitowsky’s publications, see https://www.researchgate.net/scientific-contributions/72394418_Itamar_Pitowsky

  3. 3.

    Bolzano’s example is believed to have been produced in the 1830s but the manuscript was only discovered in 1922 (Kowalewski 1923) and published in 1930 (Bolzano 1930). Neuenschwander (1978) notes that Weierstrass presented a continuous nowhere differentiable function before the Royal Academy of Sciences in Berlin on 18 July 1872 and that it was published first, with his assent, in Bois-Reymond (1875) and later in Weierstrass (1895).

  4. 4.

    For the arrow paradox and its analysis, see for example Huggett (1999, 2019) and references therein.

  5. 5.

    Two comments: 1. The introduction of the calculus is often presented as a solution to Zeno’s arrow paradox. I believe that this presentation is somewhat misleading. The calculus does not really solve Zeno’s paradox. It just evades it by fiat, i. e. by redefining the concept of instantaneous velocity. 2. For a recent example of the role that the calculus plays in constituting physical facts, see Stemeroff’s (2018, Chap. 3) analysis of Norton’s Dome – the thought experiment that is purported to show that non-deterministic behaviour could exist within the scope of Newtonian mechanics. Stemeroff argues that: (i) this thought experiment overlooks the constraints that the calculus imposes on Newton’s theory; and that (ii) when these constraints are taken into account, Norton’s Dome is ruled out as impossible in Newtonian universes.

  6. 6.

    Clifton (1998) appropriates, with minor modifications, a definition of explanation given by Hughes (1993).

  7. 7.

    In Bohmian mechanics, a system’s momentum is not an intrinsic property. Rather, it is a relational property that is generally different from the system’s momentum ‘observable’. Thus, the momentum observable does not generally reflect the system’s momentum (Dürr et al. 2013, Chap. 7; Lazarovici et al. 2018).

  8. 8.

    Since graph theory did not exist at the time, this is obviously an anachronistic account of Euler’s reasoning. That is not a problem for the current discussion, as the aim is not to reconstruct Euler’s own analysis but rather to consider Pincock’s account of mathematical explanation of physical facts. For Euler’s reasoning, see Euler (1736/1956), and for a reconstruction of it, see, for example, Hopkins and Wilson (2004).

  9. 9.

    Vineberg (2018) suggests that the objection above does not apply to the structuralist understanding of mathematics. It is not clear, however, how an appeal to this conception of mathematics could help here. One may accept the structuralist rejection of mathematical objects yet argue that mathematical structures only represent the physical structures which actually do the explanation.

References

  • Aristotle. (1924). Metaphysics. A revised text with introduction and commentary by W. D. Ross (2 vols). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bachelard, G. (1965). L’ activité rationaliste de la physique contemporaine. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanations in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(3), 611–633.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2017). Mathematics and explanatory generality. Philosophia Mathematica, 25(2), 194–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bangu, S. (2008). Inference to the best explanation and mathematical explanation. Synthese, 160(1), 13–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S., Colyvan, M., & Ripley, D. (2017). How mathematics can make a difference. Philosophers’ Imprint, 17(3), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2002). Asymptotics and the role of minimal models. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53(1), 21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2010). On the explanatory role of mathematics in empirical science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(1), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2018). Autonomy of theories: An explanatory problem. Noûs, 52(4), 858–873.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R., & Rice, C. (2014). Minimal model explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81(3), 349–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2008a). Can classical structures explain quantum phenomena? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59(2), 217–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2008b). Reexamining the quantum-classical relation: Beyond reductionism and pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2011). How scientific models can explain. Synthese, 180(1), 33–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolzano, B. (1930). Functionenlehre. In K. Rychlik (Ed.) Spisy Bernarda Bolzana Vol. 1. Prague: Royal Bohemian Academy of Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (2012). Plantonism, naturalism, and mathematical knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & Colyvan, M. (2011). An inferential conception of the application of mathematics. Nous, 45(2), 345–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & French, S. (2011). How theories represent. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(4), 857–894.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & French, S. (2018). Applying mathematics: Immersion, inference, interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., French, S., & Ladyman, J. (2002). On representing the relationship between the mathematical and the empirical. Philosophy of Science, 69(3), 497–518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, E. (1910/1923). Substanzbegriff und funktionsbegriff. Untersuchungen über die Grundfragen der Erkenntniskritik. Berlin: Bruno Cassirer. Translated as Substance and function. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, E. (1912/2005). Herman Cohen and the renewal of Kantian philosophy (trans. By Lydia Patton). Angelaki, 10(1), 95–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clifton, R. (1998). Scientific explanation in quantum theory. PhilSci Archive. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/91/

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2002). Mathematics and aesthetic considerations in science. Mind, 111(441), 69–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daly, C., & Langford, S. (2009). Mathematical explanation and indispensability arguments. Philosophical Quarterly, 59(237), 641–658.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M., & Felline, L. (2011). Scientific explanation and scientific structuralism. In A. Bokulich & P. Bokulich (Eds.), Scientific structuralism (Boston studies in the philosophy of science) (pp. 161–177). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • du Bois-Reymond, P. (1875). Versuch einer classification der willkürlichen functionen reeller argumente nach ihren aenderungen in den kleinsten intervallen. Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 79, 21–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (2013). Quantum physics without quantum philosophy. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1933/1954). On the method of theoretical physics. In A. Einstein, Ideas and opinions (new translations and revisions by S. Bargmann), New York: Bonanza Books (1954), pp. 270–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Euler, L. (1736/1956). Solutio problematis ad geometriam situs pertinentis. Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae, 8, 128–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felline, L. (2018). Mechanisms meet structural explanations. Synthese, 195(1), 99–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferreirós, J. (2017). Wigner’s “unreasonable effectiveness” in context. Mathematical Intelligencer, 39(2), 64–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R., et al. (1963). The Feynman lectures in physics (Vol. 2). Reading: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Ladyman, J. (1998). A semantic perspective on idealization in quantum mechanics. In N. Shanks (Ed.), Idealization IX: Idealization in contemporary physics (Pozna’n Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities) (pp. 51–73). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2018). Scientific representation. The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition). In E. N. Zalta (Ed.). URL=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/scientific-representations/

  • Galileo, G. (1623/1960). The Assayer. In the controversy of the comets of 1618: Galileo Galilei, Horatio Grassi, Mario Guiducci, Johann Kepler (S. Drake, & C. D. O’Malley, Trans.) Philadelphia: The University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S. (2017). Bohmian mechanics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.). URL=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/qm-Bohm/

  • Hopkins, B., & Wilson, R. J. (2004). The truth about Königsberg. The College Mathematics Journal, 35(3), 198–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N. (Ed.). (1999). Space from Zeno to Einstein: Classic readings with a contemporary commentary. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N. (2019). Zeno paradoxes. The Stanford Encylopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.). URL= https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/paradox-zeno/

  • Hughes, R. I. G. (1993). Theoretical explanation. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XVIII, 132–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Islami, A. (2017). A match not made in heaven: On the applicability of mathematics in physics. Synthese, 194(12), 4839–4861.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansson, L., & Saatsi, J. (2019). Explanatory abstraction. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(3), 817–844.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, V. J. (2009). A history of mathematics: An introduction (3rd ed.). Reading: Addision-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koo, A. (2015). Mathematical explanation in science. PhD thesis, IHPST, University of Toronto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2012). Varieties of ontological dependence. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding: Understanding the structure of reality (pp. 186–213). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kowalewski, G. (1923). Über Bolzanos nichtdiffrenzierbare stetige funktion. Acta Mathematica, 44, 315–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2016). Because without cause: Non-causal explanations in science and mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2018). Reply to my critics: On explanations by constraint. Metascience, 27(1), 27–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazarovici, D., Oldofredi, A., & Esfeld, M. (2018). Observables and unobservables in quantum mechanics: How the no-hidden-variables theorems support the Bohmian particle ontology. Entropy, 20(5), 116–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leng, M. (2005). Mathematical explanation. In C. Cellucci & D. Gillies (Eds.), Mathematical reasoning and heuristics (pp. 167–189). London: King’s College Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévy-Leblond, J.-M. (1992). Why does physics need mathematics? In E. Ullmann-Margalit (Ed.), The scientific enterprise (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science) (Vol. 146, pp. 145–161). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lützen, J. (2011). The physical origin of physically useful mathematics. Interdisciplinary Science Reviews, 36(3), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, A. (2012). Mathematical explanations of empirical facts, and mathematical realism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(3), 559–578.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (2018). Explanation in Mathematics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.). URL=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/mathematics-explanation/

  • Mandelbrot, B. (1977). Fractals, form, chance and dimension. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2000). Weaseling away the indispensability argument. Mind, 109(435), 455–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2002). Response to Colyvan. Mind, 111(441), 75–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mundy, B. (1986). On the general theory of meaningful representation. Synthese, 67(3), 391–437.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neuenschwander, E. (1978). Riemann’s example of a continuous “nondifferentiable” function. Mathematical Intelligencer, 1, 40–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2004). A new perspective on the problem of applying mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 12(2), 135–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2007). A role for mathematics in the physical sciences. Noûs, 41(2), 253–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2011a). Abstract explanation and difference making. A colloquium presentation in the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, LMU, December 12, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2011b). Discussion note: Batterman’s “On the explanatory role of mathematics in empirical science”. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(1), 211–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematics and scientific representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2015). Abstract explanations in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(4), 857–882.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitowsky, I. (1992). Why does physics need mathematics? A comment. In E. Ullmann-Margalit (Ed.), The scientific enterprise (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science) (Vol. 146, pp. 163–167). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1913). La valeur de la science. Geneva: Editions du Cheval Ailé.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redhead, M. (2001). Quests of a realist: Review of Stathis Psillos’s Scientific Realism: How science tracks truth. Metascience, 10(3), 341–347.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M. D. (1997). Mathematics as a science of patterns. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2011). The enhanced indispensability argument: Representational versus explanatory role of mathematics in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(1), 143–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2016). On the “indispensable explanatory role” of mathematics. Mind, 125(500), 1045–1070.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2018). A pluralist account of non-causal explanations in science and mathematics: Review of M. Lange’s Because without cause: Non-causal explanation in science and mathematics. Metascience, 27(1), 3–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1978). Mathematical explanations. Philosophical Studies, 34(2), 135–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1998). The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stemeroff, N. (2018). Mathematics, structuralism, and the promise of realism: A study of the ontological and epistemological implications of mathematical representation in the physical sciences. A PhD thesis submitted to the University of Toronto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vineberg, S. (2018). Mathematical explanation and indispensability. Theoria, 33(2), 233–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weierstrass, K. (1895). Über continuirliche functionen eines reellen arguments, die für keinen werth des letzteren einen bestimmten differentialquotienten besitzen (read 1872). In Mathematische werke von Karl Weierstrass (Vol. 2, pp. 71–76). Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiener, N. (1923). Differential space. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 2, 131–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13(1), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I owe a great debt to Itamar Pitowsky. Itamar’s graduate course in the philosophy of probability stimulated my interest in the philosophical foundations of probability and quantum mechanics. Itamar supervised my course essay and MA thesis on the application of de Finetti’s theory of probability to the interpretation of quantum probabilities. During my work on this research project, I learned from Itamar a great deal about the curious nature of probabilities in quantum mechanics. Itamar was very generous with his time and the discussions with him were always enlightening. Our conversations continued for many years to come, and likewise they were always helpful in clarifying and developing my thoughts and ideas. Itamar’s untimely death has been a great loss. Whenever I have an idea I would like to test, I think of him and wish we could talk about it. I sorely miss the meetings with him and I wish I could discuss with him the questions and ideas considered above.

I am very grateful to the volume editors, Meir Hemmo and Orly Shenker, for inviting me to contribute, and to Meir for drawing my attention to Itamar’s commentary on the relationship between mathematics and physics. The main ideas of the proposed account of mathematical explanations of physical facts were first presented in the workshop on Mathematical and Geometrical Explanations at the Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (March 2012), and I thank Laura Felline for inviting me to participate in the workshop. Earlier versions of this paper were also presented in the 39th, 40th, 43rd, and 46th Dubrovnik Philosophy of Science conferences, IHPST, Paris, IHPST, University of Toronto, Philosophy, Università degli Studi Roma Tre, Philosophy, Università degli Studi di Firenze, CSHPS, Victoria, CPNSS, LSE, Philosophy, Leibniz Universität Hannover, ISHPS, Jerusalem, Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, LMU, Faculty of Sciences, Universidade de Lisboa. I would like to thank the audiences in these venues for their helpful comments. For discussions and comments on earlier drafts of the paper, I am very grateful to Jim Brown, Donald Gillies, Laura Felline, Craig Fraser, Aaron Kenna, Flavia Padovani, Noah Stemeroff, and an anonymous referee. The research for this paper was supported by SSHRC Insight and SIG grants as well as Victoria College travel grants.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph Berkovitz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Berkovitz, J. (2020). On the Mathematical Constitution and Explanation of Physical Facts. In: Hemmo, M., Shenker, O. (eds) Quantum, Probability, Logic. Jerusalem Studies in Philosophy and History of Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34316-3_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics