Skip to main content

Quantum Mechanics As a Theory of Observables and States (And, Thereby, As a Theory of Probability)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Quantum, Probability, Logic

Abstract

Itamar Pitowsky contends that quantum states are derived entities, bookkeeping devices for quantum probabilities, which he understands to reflect the odds rational agents would accept on the outcomes of quantum gambles. On his view, quantum probability is subjective, and so are quantum states. We disagree. We take quantum states, and the probabilities they encode, to be objective matters of physics. Our disagreement has both technical and conceptual aspects. We advocate an interpretation of Gleason’s theorem and its generalizations more nuanced—and less directly supportive of subjectivism—than Itamar’s. And we contend that taking quantum states to be physical makes available explanatory resources unavailable to subjectivists, explanatory resources that help make sense of quantum state preparation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See also Pitowsky (2003) and Bub and Pitowsky (2010).

  2. 2.

    For details of Pitowsky’s account of quantum gambles, see his (2003, Sec. 1).

  3. 3.

    A further technical quibble, readily addressed, is that the version Itamar discusses applies only to the special setting of non-relativistic QM; §4.2 extends his discussion.

  4. 4.

    Pitowsky (2003) and Bub and Pitowsky (2010) call it the “‘big’ measurement problem,” which they distinguish from the “small” measurement problem. More on this below.

  5. 5.

    For the relevant operator algebra theory the reader may consult Bratelli and Robinson (1987) and Kadison and Ringrose (1987).

  6. 6.

    This is not to say that T1∗ is uncontroversial among philosophers of physics. Bohmians would deny that T1∗ captures the fundamental event structure.

  7. 7.

    The sum of probabilities for a transfinite collection is understood as the sup of sums of finite subcollections. The sup exists because the sequence of sums over ever larger finite subcollections gives a non-decreasing bounded sequence of real numbers, and every such sequence has a least upper bound.

  8. 8.

    See Kadison and Ringrose (1987, Vol. 2, Theorem 7.1.12) and Bratelli and Robinson (1987, Theorem 2.4.21).

  9. 9.

    This Theorem requires proof techniques that are different from the one used for the original Gleason theorem; see Hamhalter (2003) and Maeda (1990) detailed treatments of this crucial theorem. A Type I2 summand is isomorphic to the algebra of bounded operators on a two-dimensional Hilbert space.

  10. 10.

    An awkwardness for Itamar’s account is the existence, in the case where \(\dim (\mathcal {H})=2\), of probability measures on \(\mathcal {P}(\mathfrak {B}(\mathcal {H}))\) that don’t extend to quantum states on \(\mathfrak {B}(\mathcal {H})\). In order to maintain that quantum states are just bookkeeping devices for the credences of rational agents contemplating bets on quantum event structures, it seems that Itamar must either deny that two dimensional Hilbert spaces afford quantum event structures, or articulate and motivate rationality constraints (in addition to the constraint of conformity to the axioms of the probability calculus!) that prevent agents from adopting “stateless” credences.

  11. 11.

    For a contrary viewpoint, see Feintzeig and Weatherall (2019).

  12. 12.

    Bayesian statisticians are divided on the issue of additivity requirements. Some versions of decision theory, such as that of Savage (1972), operate with mere finite additivity. Kadane et al. (1986) argue that various anomalies and paradoxes of Bayesian statistics can be resolved by the use of so-called improper priors and that such priors can be interpreted in terms of finitely additive probabilities. For more considerations in favor of mere finite additivity see Seidenfeld (2001).

  13. 13.

    von Neumann’s preferred version of the projection postulate differs from the version stated here in the case of observables with degenerate spectra. Preliminary experimental evidence seems to favor the Lüders version stated here; see Hegerfeldt and Mayato (2012) and Kumar et al. (2016).

  14. 14.

    This is a slight generalization of the result of Cassinelli and Zanghi (1983).

  15. 15.

    One of us (LR) has reservations about the interpretational morals being drawn from the BDL theorem; see Appendix 6.

  16. 16.

    Let \(\mathfrak {N}\) be a von Neumann algebra acting on \(\mathcal {H}\). A vector \(|\varOmega \rangle \in \mathcal {H}\) is cyclic iff \(\mathfrak {N}|\varOmega \rangle \) is dense in \(\mathcal {H}\). It is separating vector iff A|Ω〉 = 0 implies A = 0 for any \(A\in \mathfrak {N}\) such that \([A,\mathfrak {N}]=0\).

  17. 17.

    Or rather that is all there is supposed to be to what Pitowsky (2003) and Bub and Pitowsky (2010) call the ‘big’ measurement problem. They think that after the big problem is dissolved there still remains the ‘small’ measurement problem, viz. to explain the emergence of the classical world we observe.

  18. 18.

    This is hardly to deny that Bohmians are realists. They’re just realists about something else—the Bohm theory. Standard QM stands to the Bohm theory as an effective theory stands to a more fundamental theory whose coarse-grained implications it mimics. Thus realism about the Bohm theory induces something like “effective realism” about QM. The point is that this represents less realism about the theory than Itamar’s position. For more on effective realism, see Williams (2017).

References

  • Araki, H. (2009). Mathematical theory of quantum fields. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratelli, O., & Robinson, D. W. (1987). Operator algebras and quantum statistical mechanics I (2nd ed.). Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bub, J., & Pitowsky, I. (2010). Two dogmas of quantum mechanics. In S. Saunders, J. Barrett, A. Kent, & D. Wallace (Eds.), Many worlds? Everett, quantum theory, & reality (pp. 433–459). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Buchholz, D., & Wichmann, E. H. (1986). Causal independence and the energy-level density of states in local quantum field theory. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 106, 321–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchholz, D., Doplicher, S., & Longo, R. (1986). On Noether’s theorem in quantum field theory. Annals of Physics, 170, 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassinelli, G., & Zanghi, N. (1983). Conditional probabilities in quantum mechanics. Nuovo Cimento B, 73, 237–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti, B. (1972). Probability, induction and statistics. London: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti, B. (1974). Theory of probability (2 Vols). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drish, T. (1979). Generalizations of Gleason’s theorem. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 18, 239–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eilers, M., & Horst, E. (1975). Theorem of Gleason for nonseparable Hilbert spaces. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 13, 419–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feintzeig, B., & Weatherall, J. (2019). Why be regular? Part II. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 65, 133–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haag, R. (1992). Local quantum physics. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson, H. (2001). On the nature of continuous physical quantities in classical and quantum mechanics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 30, 27–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson, H. (2007). Algebraic quantum field theory. In J. Earman & J. Butterfield (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science, philosophy of physics part A (pp. 731–864). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamhalter, J. (2003). Quantum measure theory. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hegerfeldt, G. C., & Mayato, R. (2012). Discriminating between von Neumann and Lüders reduction rule. Physical Review A, 85, 032116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kadane, J. B, Schervish, M. J., & Seidenfeld, T. (1986). Statistical implications of finitely additive probability. In P. K. Goel & A. Zellner (Eds.), Bayesian inference and decision techniques (pp. 59–76). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadison, R. V., & Ringrose, J. R. (1987). Fundamentals of the theory of operator algebras (2 Vols). Providence: Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, C. S., Shukla, A., & Mahesh, T. S. (2016). Discriminating between Lüders and von Neumann measuring devices: An NMR investigation. Physics Letters A, 380, 3612–2616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2012). Two accounts of laws and time. Philosophical Studies, 160, 115–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maeda, S. (1990). Probability measures on projections in von Neumann algebras. Reviews in Mathematical Physics, 1, 235–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petz, D., & Rédei, M. (1995). John von Neumann and the theory of operator algebras. The Neumann Compendium, 163–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitowsky, I. (2003). Betting on the outcomes of measurements: A Bayesian theory of quantum probability. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 34, 395–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitowsky, I. (2006). Quantum mechanics as a theory of probability. In: W. Demopoulos & I. Pitowsky (Eds.), Physical theory and its implications; essays in honor of Jeffrey Bub (pp. 213–240). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raggio, G. A. (1988). A remark on Bell’s inequality and decomposable normal states. Letters in Mathematical Physics, 15, 27–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruetsche, L. (2011). Why be normal? Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 42, 107–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. J. (1972). Foundations of statistics (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seidenfeld, T. (2001). Remarks on the theory of conditional probability. In V. F. Hendricks, et al. (Eds.), Probability theory (pp. 167–178). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1992). Coherence, probability and induction. Philosophical Issues, 2, 215–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Srinvas, M. D. (1980). Collapse postulate for observables with continuous spectra. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 71, 131–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takesaki, M. (1972). Conditional expectations in von Neumann algebras. Journal of Functional Analysis, 9, 306–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, P. (2017). Scientific realism made effective. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70, 209–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work reflects a collaboration with the late Aristides Arageorgis extending over many years. We are indebted to him. And we thank Gordon Belot, Jeff Bub, and the editors of this volume for valuable guidance and feedback on earlier drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Laura Ruetsche .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Earman, J., Ruetsche, L. (2020). Quantum Mechanics As a Theory of Observables and States (And, Thereby, As a Theory of Probability). In: Hemmo, M., Shenker, O. (eds) Quantum, Probability, Logic. Jerusalem Studies in Philosophy and History of Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34316-3_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics