Skip to main content

Diagrams in Mathematics: On Visual Experience in Peirce

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Math Cognition

Part of the book series: Mathematics in Mind ((MATHMIN))

  • 911 Accesses

Abstract

Mathematicians use diagrams in their work all the time, whether they want to make use of Euclid’s fifth postulate, to prove Fermat’s principle, or to extract an algorithm that defines the seemingly chaotic movement of pigeons picking bread crumps from the ground. Using diagrams helps mathematicians identify patterns that solve particular mathematical problems by making the force of necessary reasoning visually given. A mathematical diagram, a paradigmatic use of which is exemplified in Euclid’s Elements, is an individual image that instantiates necessary relations. As an observable entity, it allows a mathematician to experiment upon it and to visually demonstrate the necessity of a given conclusion. At the same time, it represents an abstract mathematical object. We do not use diagrams simply to facilitate our reasoning and then translate those diagrams into a formal calculus in order to make inferences. Diagrams themselves are immediate visualizations of the deductive process as such. The necessary character of deductive arguments is thus internal to the diagrams mathematicians construct (Sloman 2002).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Abrahamsen, A. and Bechtel, W. (2015). Diagrams as tools for scientific reasoning Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6(1): 117–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bakker, A. and Hoffmann, M. (2005). Diagrammatic reasoning as the basis for developing concepts: A semiotic analysis of students’ learning about statistical distribution. Educational Studies in Mathematics 60: 333–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker-Plummer, D. (1997). The role of diagrams in mathematical proofs. Machine Graphics and Vision 6(1): 25–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, J. (2004). The generalization of the mathematical function: A speculative analysis. In: G. Debrock (ed.), Process pragmatism. Essays of a quiet philosophical revolution, pp. 71–86. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cajori, F. (1890). The teaching and history of mathematics in the United States. Washington, D.C.: The U.S Government Printing Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campos, D. (2009). Imagination, concentration, and generalization: Peirce on the reasoning abilities of the mathematician. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 45(2): 135–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danesi, M. (2016a). Language and mathematics. An interdisciplinary guide. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Danesi, M. (2016). Learning and teaching mathematics in the global village. Math education in the digital age. New York, NY: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1986). Cinema 1: The movement image (translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1992). A theory of semiotics. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegarty, M Kozhevnikov, M. (1999). Types of visual–spatial representations and mathematical problem solving. Journal of Educational Psychology, 91(4): 684–689.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisch, M. H. (n.d.) Chronological file, Institute for American Thought, School of Liberal Arts, IUPUI, Indianapolis, IN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann, M. (2004). Peirce’s “diagrammatic reasoning:” A solution of the learning paradox. In G. Debrock (ed.), Process pragmatism. Essays of a quiet philosophical revolution, pp. 121–144. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, K. (2017). The iconic Peirce: Geometry, spatial intuition, and visual imagination. In: K. Hull and R. Atkins (eds.), Peirce on Perception and Reasoning: From Icons to Logic (147–173). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Joswick, H. (1988). Peirce’s mathematical model of interpretation. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 24(1): 107–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulpa, Z. (2009). Main problems of diagrammatic reasoning. Part I: The generalization problem. Foundations of Science 14(1): 75–96.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1999). Philosophy in flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to Western thought. New York, NY: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. and Núñez, R. (2000). Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into being. New York, NY: Basic Books.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Legg, C. (2012). The Hardness of the Iconic Must: Can Peirce’s Existential Graphs Assist Modal Epistemology? Philosophia Mathematica 20, 1–24.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Legg, C. (2017). “Diagrammatic Teaching:” The role of iconic signs in meaningful pedagogy. In: I. Semetsky (ed.), Edusemiotics: A handbook, pp. 29–46. Singapore: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McLuhan, M. (1994). Understanding media: The extensions of man. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumma, J. (2010). Proofs, pictures, and Euclid. Synthèse 175(2): 255–287.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. (1992). How do scientists think? Capturing the dynamics of conceptual change in science. In: R. Giere (ed.), Cognitive models of science, pp. 5–22. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paavola, S. (2011). Diagrams, iconicity, and abductive discovery. Semiotica 186: 297–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paolucci, C. (2017). Semiotics, schemata, diagrams, and graphs: A new form of diagrammatic Kantism by Peirce. In: K. Hull and R. Atkins (eds.), Peirce on perception and reasoning: From icons to logic pp. 74–85. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, K. (2017). Foundations for semeiotic aesthetics: Mimesis and iconicity. In: K. Hull and R. Atkins (eds.), Peirce on perception and reasoning: From icons to logic, pp. 61–73. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1992–1998). The essential Peirce. Selected philosophical writings. Vols. 1-2. N. Houser and C. Kloesel (eds.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1982). Writings of Charles S. Peirce. A chronological edition. Vols. 1–6. M. H. Fisch, E. Moore, C. Kloesel, and Peirce Edition Project (eds.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1976). The new elements of mathematics. C. Eisele (ed.). Vol. 4. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931–1958). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Vols. 1–8. C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss, and A. Burks (eds.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (2009). Science and method (trans. by F. Maitland). New York: Cosimo Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prusak, N. (2012). From visual reasoning to logical necessity through argumentative design. Educational Studies in Mathematics 79(1): 19–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sherry, D. (2009). The role of diagrams in mathematical arguments Foundations of Science 14(1–2): 59–74.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, A. (2002). Diagrams in the mind? In: M. Anderson, B. Meyer and P. Olivier (eds.). Diagrammatic representation and reasoning, pp. 7–28. London: Springer-Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology: An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, E. (2017). Perception as inference. In K. Hull and R. Atkins (eds.), Peirce on perception and reasoning: From icons to logic. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, A. (2017). What do we perceive? How Peirce “expands our perception”. In K. Hull and R. Atkins (eds.), Peirce on perception and reasoning: From icons to logic, pp. 1–13. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vitaly Kiryushchenko .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kiryushchenko, V. (2019). Diagrams in Mathematics: On Visual Experience in Peirce. In: Danesi, M. (eds) Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Math Cognition. Mathematics in Mind. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-22537-7_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics