Skip to main content

Anti-abortion Laws and the Ethics of Abortion

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Controversies in Latin American Bioethics

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 79))

Abstract

In this paper, I begin by distinguishing between the moral evaluation of the law that criminalizes abortion and the moral evaluation of abortion itself. In the public debate on abortion, these are issues that we frequently find mixed up, and that must be analyzed separately. Regarding the moral evaluation of the law, there are at least two possible ways of assessing it: in terms of the consequences of the law and in terms of women’s rights. I argue that anti-abortion laws have negative consequences at different levels: for the women who are denied termination of their pregnancies when they do not want to go on with them, for unwanted children, and for society at large. These laws also infringe upon some of women’s most fundamental rights in a way no other law does, requiring them to sacrifice their freedom, autonomy, privacy, and future life, and putting their health and bodily integrity at risk. However, according to those with a conservative view on abortion, none of this justifies the intentional killing of an embryo, which they take as a person with a right to life. I argue that there are no good arguments in favor of considering an embryo to be a person since on all accounts, the ascription of personhood requires the presence of mental or psychological properties, which do not appear until the end of the second trimester of pregnancy. We cannot ascribe a right to life to the embryo, either. Therefore, there is no justification for all the negative consequences of anti-abortion laws and for the infringement of women’s rights.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Many people who favor the criminalization of abortion tend to use words indiscriminately, claiming that ‘abortion kills babies’ or ‘abortion kills children,’ making ‘embryo’ equivalent to ‘baby’ or ‘child,’ which is incorrect—in that case we would talk about infanticide, not about abortion. This is obviously intended to elicit a stronger negative emotional response from the audience against abortion. However, we should be careful with words: a zygote (a cell formed by the fertilization of two gametes) divides through mitosis and, by the fifth day, forms a blastocyst, which after further divisions may become implanted in the uterus. Although there is no universal agreement on when the embryo begins, ‘embryo’ is the term used to refer to this organism between the fourth week (after implantation has already occurred) and the eleventh week after fertilization. At the beginning of the twelfth week the embryo is termed a ‘fetus’ (Schoenwolf et al. 2015: 3–4). Only after birth it can properly be called a ‘baby’ or a ‘child.’ Since I focus mainly on abortion during the first trimester, I will mostly use the term ‘embryo’—although, as will be apparent, my arguments can be used to justify the permissibility of abortion during the second trimester, as well.

  2. 2.

    This information comes from Lerner and Guillaume (2007) and CRR (2017).

  3. 3.

    Finer et al. (2005); see also Johnston (2016), who argues that these cases represent less than 1% of all the reasons given for having abortions in the U.S.

  4. 4.

    In El Salvador, abortion was legal under some limited circumstances, but in 1998 a new law made abortion illegal under any circumstance. Nicaragua prohibited any type of abortion in 2007. Many states in Mexico amended state constitutions to protect life from the moment of conception, as a reaction to Mexico City’s law reform that decriminalized elective abortion for the first trimester in 2007. In Brazil, where evangelicals are becoming more powerful political actors, members of Congress have tried to toughen penalties for women who abort (Carless 2016).

  5. 5.

    In Latin America, due to restrictive abortion laws, the risk of dying from abortion is 32.9 deaths per 100,000 procedures (Khan et al. 2006: 1068). In Mexico, nationwide, it is around 40 deaths per 100,000 procedures, versus 0.0 deaths per 100,000 procedures in Mexico City, where elective abortion is legal (Schiavon et al. 2015). Thanks are due to Raffaela Schiavon for sharing the results of her research.

  6. 6.

    I realize that framing a reduction in numbers of abortions as a positive consequence of decriminalization is quite controversial within the reproductive rights movement. There are those that believe abortions should be “safe, legal and rare” [e.g. Hillary Clinton in her 2008 campaign (On the Issues 2008)] and those who believe equating rare and good heightens the stigma around abortion.

  7. 7.

    It is often said that adoption is a solution to the problem of abortion, but the disparity between the high number of abortions and the low number of adoptions in Latin America (and elsewhere) makes this option unrealistic. I have argued that adoption is not an answer to the problem of abortion, at least in the case of Mexico, in Ortiz Millán (2009).

  8. 8.

    There are economic analyses of the consequences of anti-abortion laws. Monea and Thomas (2011), for instance, estimate the annual costs of unintended pregnancies in the U.S., and how the prevention of such pregnancies could save taxpayers a significant amount of money.

  9. 9.

    Kost et al. (2008) analyze the results of the 2002 National Survey of Family Growth and conclude that “12.4% of all episodes of contraceptive use ended with a failure within 12 months after initiation of use.” Fertility-awareness-based methods, such as the “rhythm,” “periodic abstinence,” or “natural family planning” have the highest probability of failure (25%).

  10. 10.

    To be sure, decriminalization by itself does not make abortion safe. Conditions of poverty and ignorance, lack of sex education, lack of access to adequate health services and contraceptive methods, among others, contribute to making abortion unsafe. To assume that decriminalizing abortion would be enough to make abortion safe is an oversimplification of the problem. India, for instance, decriminalized abortion in 1971 through the Medical Termination of Pregnancy Act, but out of 6.4 million abortions, 3.6 million (56%) are unsafe (Sedgh et al. 2007). Decriminalization has to be accompanied by public policies that contribute to making abortion safe, such as family planning programs.

  11. 11.

    The case of the US is an example of how the state has infringed upon a woman’s right to health care “legally,” since the US legally denies women this type of health care.

  12. 12.

    Around 30% of Latin American married or in-union women of reproductive age do not use any contraceptive method, and among those who do, the dominant methods are those that are, so to speak, the responsibility of women (IUDs, pills, rhythm, implants, etc.), and less than 10% use male condoms (UN 2015). This suggests that men tend to leave contraception in the hands of women.

  13. 13.

    An alternative account of this kind of argumentative line is that of Thomson (1971). She grants, for the sake of the argument, that the fetus has a right to life and then argues that it does not trump the pregnant woman’s right to decide over her pregnancy, and that an intentional abortion is not morally impermissible.

  14. 14.

    For more on this line of argumentation, see Warren (1997).

  15. 15.

    There are other answers to the question about why abortion is immoral. Don Marquis has given one of the most prominent ones. According to Marquis, abortion is immoral since it deprives an embryo or fetus of a “future like ours” (1989: 191), and this is something of value to us. However, many have objected to Marquis’s argument. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (1999), for instance, argues that Marquis equivocates the meaning of “loss.” It either means the privation of a future to which the embryo has a moral right or the privation of a future to which it has no moral right. If this definition were accepted, Marquis would still have to explain how an embryo has a moral right to the means of realizing its future for his argument to be sound. For a deeper analysis of Marquis’s argument, see Boonin (2002).

  16. 16.

    Even if human embryos are not persons and have no right to life, they should be legally protected goods, just like parks, water, historic monuments, or the environment. Human embryos are valuable and must be protected by law. This point is important because it would be the basis for punishing, for example, someone who causes an abortion to a pregnant woman against her will.

References

  • Beckwith, F. 2007. Defending Life: A Moral and Legal Case Against Abortion Choice. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boonin, D. 2002. A Defense of Abortion. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, S.S., and Eisenberg, L. (eds.). 1995. The Best Intentions. Unintended Pregnancy and the Well-Being of Children and Families. Washington, DC: National Academy Press. Retrieved from https://www.nap.edu/read/4903/chapter/1.

  • Carless, W. 2016. A New Bill Aims to Make Brazil’s Abortion Law Even Tougher. Public Radio International. Retrieved from https://www.pri.org/stories/2016-03-26/new-bill-aims-make-brazils-abortion-law-even-tougher.

  • Cheng, D., E.B. Schwarz, E. Douglas, and I. Horon. 2009. Unintended Pregnancy and Associated Maternal Preconception, Prenatal and Postpartum Behaviors. Contraception 79: 194–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • CRR. 2017. The World’s Abortion Laws. Center for Reproductive Rights. Available at: http://worldabortionlaws.com/map/.

  • Cruz Sánchez, V. 2014. Guanajuato: joderse a las mujeres más pobres y más jodidas no beneficia a ninguna nación. In Aborto, Democracia y Empoderamiento, ed. G. Ortiz Millán, 115–134. Mexico City: Fontamara-ITAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • David, H.P. 2011. Born Unwanted: Mental Health Costs and Consequences. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry 81 (2): 184–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 1981. Conditions of Personhood. In The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty, 175–196. Berkeley-Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finer, L.B., L.F. Frohwirth, L.A. Dauphinee, S. Singh, and A.M. Moore. 2005. Reasons U.S. Women Have Abortions: Quantitative and Qualitative Perspectives. Perspectives on Sexual and Reproductive Health 37 (3): 110–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foote, C.L., and C.F. Goetz. 2008. The Impact of Legalized Abortion on Crime: Comment. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 123 (1): 407–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • François, A., R. Magni-Berton, and L. Weill. 2014. Abortion and Crime: Cross-Country Evidence from Europe. International Review of Law and Economics 40: 24–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • GIRE. 2005. Paulina. Five Years Later. Mexico City: Grupo de Información en Reproducción Elegida.

    Google Scholar 

  • GIRE. 2017. Perfil de las usuarias que han realizado la interrupción legal del embarazo en la Ciudad de México. Abril 2007–28 de febrero de 2017. Mexico City: Grupo de Información en Reproducción Elegida. Retrieved from: http://informe.gire.org.mx.

  • Greene Foster, D. 2016. Unmet Need for Abortion and Woman-Centered Contraceptive Care. The Lancet 388: 216–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gruber, J., P. Levine, and D. Staiger. 1999. Abortion Legalization and Child Living Circumstances: Who is the “Marginal Child”? Quarterly Journal of Economics 114 (1): 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guttmacher Institute. 2012. Facts on Abortion in Latin America and the Caribbean Available at: http://www.guttmacher.org/pubs/fb_IAW.pdf.

  • ICPD. 1994. International Conference on Population and Development. Programme of Action. New York: United Nations. Retrieved from http://www.unfpa.org/publications/international-conference-population-and-development-programme-action#sthash.tgttDGJZ.dpuf.

  • IPPF. 2006. Death and Denial: Unsafe Abortion and Poverty. London: International Planned Parenthood Federation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar, A. 2009. Abortion Rights and Gender Justice Worldwide: An Essay in Political Philosophy. In Abortion. Three Perspectives, ed. M. Tooley, C. Wolf-Devine, P.E. Devine, and A. Jaggar, 120–179. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • John Paul II. 1995. Evangelium Vitae. Retrieved from http://w2.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_25031995_evangelium-vitae.html.

  • Johnston, R. 2016. Reasons Given for Having Abortions in the United States. Available at: http://www.johnstonsarchive.net/policy/abortion/abreasons.html.

  • Khan, K.S., D. Wojdyla, L. Say, A.M. Gülmezoglu, and P.F.A. Van Look. 2006. WHO Analysis of Causes of Maternal Death: A Systematic Review. Lancet 367: 1066–1074.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kost, K., D.J. Landry, and J.E. Darroch. 1998. Predicting Maternal Behaviors During Pregnancy: Does Intention Status Matter? Family Planning Perspectives 30 (2): 79–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kost, K., S. Singh, B. Vaughan, J. Trussell, and A. Bankole. 2008. Estimates of Contraceptive Failure from the 2002 National Survey of Family Growth. Contraception 77 (1): 10–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, S., and A. Guillaume. 2007. Abortion in Latin America and the Caribbean. A Review of the Literature from 1990 to 2005. Mexico-Paris: Institut de Recherche pour le Développement-El Colegio de México. Retrieved from http://www.ceped.org/cdrom/avortement_ameriquelatine_2007/en/infos/introduction.html.

  • Levitt, S., and J. Donohue. 2001. The Impact of Legalized Abortion on Crime. Quarterly Journal of Economics 116 (2): 379–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mai, J.K., and K.W.S. Ashwell. 2004. Fetal Development of the Central Nervous System. In The Human Nervous System, ed. G. Paxinos and J.K. Mai, 49–94. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, D. 1989. Why Abortion is Immoral. The Journal of Philosophy 86 (4): 183–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ministerio della Salute. 2017. Relazione del Ministro della Salute sulla attuazione della legge contenente norme per la tutela sociale della maternità e per l’interruzione volontaria di gravidanza (Legge 194/78). Retrieved from http://www.salute.gov.it/imgs/C_17_pubblicazioni_2686_allegato.pdf.

  • Monea, J., and A. Thomas. 2011. Unintended Pregnancy and Taxpayer Spending. Perspectives on Sexual and Reproductive Health 43 (2): 88–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, F., and R. O’Rahilly. 2004. Embryonic Development of the Central Nervous System. In The Human Nervous System, ed. G. Paxinos and J.K. Mai, 22–48. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nino, C.S. 1989. Ética y derechos humanos, 2nd ed. Buenos Aires: Astrea.

    Google Scholar 

  • On the Issues. 2018. Hilary Clinton on Abortion. On the Issues. Retrieved from http://www.ontheissues.org/Celeb/Hillary_Clinton_Abortion.htm.

  • Ortiz Millán, G. 2009. La moralidad del aborto. Mexico City: Siglo XXI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raymond, E.G., and D.A. Grimes. 2012. The Comparative Safety of Legal Induced Abortion and Childbirth in the United States. Obstetrics and Gynecology 119 (2): 215–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roe v. Wade. 1973. Roe v. Wade: The 1973 Supreme Court Decision on State Abortion Laws. In The Ethics of Abortion: Pro-Life vs. Pro-Choice, 3rd ed., ed. R. M. Baird and S. E. Rosenbaum, 63–72. New York: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiavon, R., E. Troncoso, and G. Polo. 2015. Abortion Hospitalizations Trends in Mexico 2000–2013: Analysis of Complicated vs. Uncomplicated Cases Using the ICD-10 Classification. Paper presented at the XXI FIGO World Congress of Gynecology and Obstetrics, Vancouver, Canada, October 4–9, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoenwolf, G.C., S.B. Bleyl, P.R. Brauer, and P.H. Francis-West. 2015.. Larsen’s Human Embryology, 5th ed. Philadelphia: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • SCJN. 2008. Acción de inconstitucionalidad 146/2007 y su acumulada 147/2007. Mexico City: Suprema Corte de Justicia de la Nación. Available at: https://www.sitios.scjn.gob.mx/codhap/completo/despenalizacion_abortodf.

  • Sedgh, G., S. Henshaw, S. Singh, E. Åhman, and I.H. Shah. 2007. Induced Abortion: Estimated Rates and Trends Worldwide. Lancet 370: 1338–1345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sedgh, G., J. Bearak, S. Singh, A. Bankole, A. Popinchalk, B. Ganatra, C. Rossier, C. Gerdts, O. Tunçalp, B. Ronald Johnson Jr, H. Bart Johnston, and L. Alkema. 2016. Abortion Incidence between 1990 and 2014: Global, Regional, and Subregional Levels and Trends. Lancet 388: 258–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro-Mendoza, C., B.J. Selwyn, D.P. Smith, and M. Sanderson. 2005. Parental Pregnancy Intention and Early Childhood Stunting: Findings from Bolivia. International Journal of Epidemiology 34: 387–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. 1999. You Can’t Lose What You ain’t Never Had: A Reply to Marquis on Abortion. Philosophical Studies 96: 59–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 1959. Individuals. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stretton, D. 2008. Critical Notice: Defending Life: A Moral and Legal Case Against Abortion Choice by Francis J. Beckwith. Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (11): 793–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J.J. 1971. A Defense of Abortion. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1 (1): 47–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • UN. 2015. Trends in Contraceptive Use Worldwide 2015. New York: United Nations. Retrieved from http://www.un.org/en/development/desa/population/publications/pdf/family/trendsContraceptiveUse2015Report.pdf.

  • UNPD. 2002. Abortion Policies: A Global Review. United Nations Population Division. Retrieved from http://www.un.org/esa/population/publications/abortion/.

  • Van Dijk, M.G., L.G. Arellano Mendoza, A.G. Arangure Peraza, A.A. Toriz Prado, A. Krumholz, and E.A. Yam. 2011. Women’s Experiences with Legal Abortion in Mexico City: A Qualitative Study. Studies in Family Planning 42 (3): 167–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, M.A. 1997. Moral Status. Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, R. 1971. Understanding the Abortion Argument. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1 (1): 67–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • WHO. 2011. Unsafe Abortion: Global and Regional Estimates of the Incidence of Unsafe Abortion and Associated Mortality in 2008, 6th ed. Geneva: World Health Organization.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks are due to Jennifer Paine, Eduardo Rivera-López, Enrique Rodríguez, and to an anonymous reviewer for their many comments on an earlier version of this paper, and to Susana Lerner and Raffaela Schiavon for the information they gave me regarding their research on abortion. I am also grateful to the Dirección General de Asuntos del Personal Académico of the Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México (UNAM) for the financial support that allowed me to do this research as a visiting scholar at Duke University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gustavo Ortiz Millán .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ortiz Millán, G. (2019). Anti-abortion Laws and the Ethics of Abortion. In: Rivera-López, E., Hevia, M. (eds) Controversies in Latin American Bioethics. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 79. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-17963-2_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics