Skip to main content

Quantifiers and Conceptual Existence

  • Chapter
Mario Bunge: A Centenary Festschrift

Abstract

This chapter examines Bunge’s distinction between the logical concept of existence and the ontological one. We introduce a new conceptual existence predicate in an intensional environment that depends on the evaluation world. So that we can investigate restricted areas (worlds) where the different kinds of concepts might exist. We hope this new predicate would encompass Bunge’s philosophical position which he designates as conceptualist and fictional materialism. The basic hybridization (adding nominals and @ operators) acts as a bridge between intensions and extensions because @ works as a useful rigidifier. In hybrid logic, the accessibility relation and many properties this relation might have can be easily expressed in the formal language. The initial hypothesis is that hybridization and intensionality can serve as unifying tools in the areas involved in this research; namely, Logic, Philosophy of Science and Linguistics.

This research has been possible thanks to the research projects sustained by Ministerio de Economía y Competitividad of Spain with reference FFI2013-47126-P and FFI2017-82554-P.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Nowadays, to discriminate object language from metalanguage we make a distinction between predicates (of the object language) and properties of the metalanguage.

  2. 2.

    In spite of this conclusion, Kant allows existence to be a logical predicate for “anything we please can be made to serve as a logical predicate”(Kant 1787/1929, B626).

  3. 3.

    In the standard hierarchy, each \(\mathcal {D}_{\left \langle a,b\right \rangle } \) contains the whole \(\mathcal {D}_{a}^{\mathcal {D}_{b}}\) while in the general models, \(\mathcal {D}_{\left \langle a,b\right \rangle }\) is a subset of \(\mathcal {D}_{a}^{\mathcal {D}_{b}}\) closed under definability. General models were first introduced by Henkin (1950) to prove the completeness of type theory.

  4. 4.

    For a longer explanation, see section 1.2: “Paradoxes and their solution in4 type theory” in Manzano (1996, pp. 182–186).

  5. 5.

    The definition was first done by Henkin (1963) and improved by Andrews (1963).

  6. 6.

    This is our translation of the Spanish original: “Si x es un objeto, entonces:

    1. a]

      xexiste conceptualmente = df Algún conjunto no vac ío C de constructos es tal que EC(x);

    2. b]

      xexiste físicamente = df Algún conjunto no vac ío F de entes físicos es tal que EF(x).” (Bunge 1980, p. 62).

  7. 7.

    By a “rigid interpretation” we understand one that does not change from world to world.

  8. 8.

    “Tanto en ciencias formales como en ciencias fácticas las afirmaciones de existencia son responsables: se tiene algún motivo razonable y no se pierde el tiempo inventando postulados o conjeturas de existencia de objetos ociosos que no desempeñan función alguna tales como mundos posibles.” (Bunge 1980, p. 64).

  9. 9.

    “En este trabajo exploraremos una alternativa, que llamaremos materialismo conceptualista y ficcionista” (Bunge 1980, p. 54).

  10. 10.

    The example is based on Tichy (1979).

  11. 11.

    “In order to describe what the members of each type are to be, it will be convenient to introduce the term concept in a sense which is entirely different from that of Frege’s Begriff, but which corresponds approximately to the use of the word by Russell and others in the phrase ‘class concept’ and rather closely to the recent use of the word by Carnap, in Meaning and Necessity. Namely anything which is capable of being the sense of a name of x is called a concept of x.” (Church 1951, p. 11).

References

  • Andrews, P. (1963). A reduction of the axioms for the theory of propositional types. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 52, 345–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Areces, C., & Ten Cate, B. (2007). Hybrid logic. In Handbook of modal logic (pp. 821–868). New York: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Areces, C., Blackburn, P., Huertas, A., & Manzano, M. (2014). Completeness in hybrid type theory. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43(2–3), 209–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P. (2000). Representation, reasoning and relational structures: A hybrid logic manifesto. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 8, 339–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T. (2008). Adding intensional machinery to hybrid logic. Journal of Logic and Computation, 18(4), 631–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T. (2011). Hybrid logic and its proof-theory. Dordrecht/Heidelberg/London/New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1980). Epistemología. Barcelona: Ariel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1985). ¿Grados de existencia o de abstracción? Theoria. Segunda época, 2, 547–549.

    Google Scholar 

  • Church, A. (1940). A formulation of the simple theory of types. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 5, 56–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Church, A. (1951). A formulation of the logic of sense and denotation. In P. Henle, H. M. Kallen, & S. K. Langer (Eds.), Structure, method and meaning: Essays in honor of Henry M. Sheffer (pp. 3–24). New York: The Liberal Arts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farmer, W. M. (1990). A partial functions version of Church’s simple theory of types. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 55(3), 1269–1291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. (2002). Types, Tableaus, and Gödel’s God. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M., & Mendelsohn, R. L. (1998). First-order modal logic. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1884/1950). The foundations of arithmetic. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henkin, L. (1950). Completeness in the theory of types. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 15, 81–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henkin, L. (1955). The nominalistic interpretation of mathematical language. Bulletin de la Société Mathé matique de Belgique, 7, 137–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henkin, L. (1963). A theory of propositional types. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 52, 323–344. (Henkin, L. (1964). Errata. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 53, 119).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1787/1929). Critique of pure reason. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzano, M. (1985). Formalización en teoría de tipos del predicado de existencia de Mario Bunge. Theoria. Segunda época, 2, 513–534.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzano, M. (1996). Extensions of first order logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzano, M., Martins, M. A., & Huertas, A. (2014). A semantics for equational hybrid propositional type theory. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 43(3–4), 121–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1903). The principles of mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1908). Mathematical logic as based on the theory of types. American Journal of Mathematics, 30(3), 222–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tichý, P. (1979). Existence and god. The Journal of Philosophy, 76(8), 403–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

To Mario Bunge, with gratitude.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to María Manzano .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Manzano, M., Moreno, M.C. (2019). Quantifiers and Conceptual Existence. In: Matthews, M.R. (eds) Mario Bunge: A Centenary Festschrift. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-16673-1_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics