Skip to main content

Group Emotions and Group Epistemology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Value of Emotions for Knowledge

Abstract

In this paper, I provide an analysis of the connection between shared emotions and shared epistemic states and undertakings. In so-doing, I aim to answer the following questions: In what sense do shared emotions help or hinder our epistemic enterprises? How do they shape the way that groups engage in these epistemic undertakings? In my analysis, I stress emotions are correlated with far-reaching changes in cognitive processing. I suggest that we should understand emotions within group contexts as ways of thinking that can facilitate cooperation and create a joint epistemic outlook. Overall, my suggestion thus is that shared emotions should be seen as important for epistemic undertakings because they turn groups into unified epistemic subjects.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It should be noted that I do not wish to claim that this position is actually a dominant approach within the study on group emotions. Nevertheless, if one assumes that reflections on group emotions take their starting point in the study of individual emotions, this would be a natural place to begin the investigation.

  2. 2.

    Here, I pick up on suggestions I have made in past publications, see Berninger (2016, 2017).

  3. 3.

    For a recent study that analyses the role positive emotions have for a group’s cooperation with respect to certain epistemic projects, see Candiotto (2017).

  4. 4.

    Brady mentions two additional conditions to explain this claim somewhat further. He suggests that (frequently) shared emotions are the result of contagion (in the sense that one member of the groups catches the emotion from another). In other cases, emotions arise individually, but nevertheless there will be a connection between these individual emotional states in the sense that group members mutually endorse each other’s emotional state (Brady 2016). In other words, there needs to be some level of emotional conformity (over and above group members just happening to be in the same emotional state) for us to be able to speak of shared emotions. In settling for this relatively open position, I leave much of the current debate on these issues aside. For an instructive overview of some recent developments in this field, see Michael (2016).

  5. 5.

    I am assuming that we can do so (in part) by using a simple aggregation function. For a related (but more complex) position on group belief, see List and Pettit (2013).

  6. 6.

    There are different ways of spelling this out, of course, depending on one’s overall epistemic position and on the question of how one analyses the epistemic role of perception and the formation of beliefs in groups.

  7. 7.

    Of course, a full-blown analysis of the epistemic role of shared emotions would also need to take other positions into account. In this respect, Brady’s account would be extremely instructive (Brady2016). However, due to limitations in space, I cannot offer a thorough analysis of his view in the course of this paper.

  8. 8.

    In stressing the importance of these activities, I also take up ideas originally voiced by Seumas Miller. In a recent paper, he develops the idea of “joint epistemic action”. According to this view, an epistemic action is an action with an epistemic end (such as knowledge, but also understanding, etc.). Examples of groups engaged in such joint epistemic actions according to Miller are a group of detectives trying to establish the identity of Jack the Ripper or a group of scientists trying to find a cure for cancer (Miller 2014). In this paper, I use the somewhat vaguer notion of an epistemic activity or an epistemic undertaking. This is primarily because there is some debate as to whether the talk of action is sensibly applicable to the realm of the mental (Strawson 2003). More recently, the importance of looking at epistemic activities in group epistemology has also been stressed by Proust, see Proust (2018).

  9. 9.

    This section of the paper is largely based on my discussion in: Berninger (2016, 2017). Note, however, that in these reflections I do not take group emotions into account.

  10. 10.

    The central issue here is that many of the experiments conducted are concerned with trait and not state emotions. See Berninger (2016) for a more detailed assessment of this issue. For more on the role that Brady assigns to attention within his overall theory of emotion, see Brady (2016).

  11. 11.

    I take up this formulation here, though it should of course be stressed that these are not dilemmas in the strict philosophical sense of the term.

  12. 12.

    In my view these differences are overlooked by Salmela and Nagatsu who already point towards a position similar to the one I am advocating here. In a recent paper, they suggest that “collective emotions lubricate creative processes, speeding imagination and recombination of ideas, thus enabling group flow” (Salmela and Nagatsu 2016). I think, here we need to be more careful in the sense that not all shared emotions will lead to these results, while some emotions (such as shared joy) might indeed do so.

  13. 13.

    For fear this might e.g. be the case where the threat scenario we are facing is very complex in nature. Here, any solution might for instance demand high degrees of creative thinking, while fear fosters ways of thinking that do not exhibit the traits conducive to creative problem-solving.

References

  • Berninger, Anja. 2016. Thinking Sadly: In Favor of an Adverbial Theory of Emotions. Philosophical Psychology 29 (6): 799–812. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2016.1159294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Gefühle und Gedanken. Entwurf einer adverbialen Emotionstheorie. Münster: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady, Michael S. 2016. Group Emotions and Group Understanding. In The Epistemic Life of Groups, ed. Michael S. Brady and Miranda Fricker, 95–110. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Candiotto, Laura. 2017. Boosting Cooperation: The Beneficial Function of Positive Emotions in Dialogical Inquiry. Humana. Mente Journal of Philosophical Studies 33: 59–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derryberry, Douglas, and Don M. Tucker. 1994. Motivating the Focus of Attention. In The Heart’s Eye: Emotional Influence in Perception and Attention, ed. Paula M. Niedenthal and Shinobu Kitayama, 167–196. San Diego: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • de Sousa, Ronald. 1987. The Rationality of Emotion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Döring, Sabine A. 2007. Seeing What to Do: Affective Perception and Rational Motivation. Dialectica 6 (3): 363–394. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1746-8361.2007.01105.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreisbach, Gesine, and Thomas Goschke. 2004. How Positive Affect Modulates Cognitive Control: Reduced Perseveration at the Cost of Increased Distractibility. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 30 (2): 343–353. https://doi.org/10.1037/0278-7393.30.2.343.

  • Fredrickson, Barbara L., and Christine Branigan. 2005. Positive Emotions Broaden the Scope of Attention and Thought-Action Repertoires. Cognition and Emotion 19 (3): 313–332. https://doi.org/10.1080/02699930441000238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goschke, Thomas. 2013. Volition in Action: Intentions, Control Dilemmas, and the Dynamic Regulation of Cognitive Control. In Action Science, ed. Wolfgang Prinz, Miriam Beisert, and Arvid Herwig, 408–434. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huebner, Bryce. 2011. Genuinely Collective Emotions. European Journal for the Philosophy of Science 1 (1): 89–118. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-010-0006-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isen, Alice M., Kimberly A. Daubman, and Gary P. Nowicki. 1987. Positive Affect Facilitates Creative Problem Solving. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52 (6): 1122–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Kareem J., Christian E. Waugh, and Barbara L. Fredrickson. 2010. Smile to See the Forest: Facially Expressed Positive Emotions Broaden Cognition. Cognition and Emotion 24 (2): 299–321. https://doi.org/10.1080/02699930903384667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leith, K.P., and R.F. Baumeister. 1996. Why Do Bad Moods Increase Self-Defeating Behavior? Emotion, Risk Taking, and Self-Regulation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 71 (6): 1250–1267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, Christian, and Philip Pettit. 2013. Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathiesen, Kay. 2011. Can Groups Be Epistemic Agents? In Collective Epistemology, ed. Hans B. Schmid, Daniel Sirtes, and Marcel Weber, 23–44. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Michael, John. 2011. Shared Emotions and Joint Action. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2 (2): 355–373. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0055-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. What Are Shared Emotions (for)? Frontiers in Psychology 7: 412. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00412.

  • Miller, Seumas. 2014. Joint Epistemic Action and Collective Moral Responsibility. Social Epistemology 29 (3): 280–302. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2014.971908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, Jesse. 2004. Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pronin, Emily, and Elana Jacobs. 2008. Thought Speed, Mood and the Experience of Mental Motion. Perspectives on Psychological Science 3 (6): 461–485.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proust, Joëlle. 2018. Consensus as an Epistemic Norm of Group Acceptance. In Socially Extended Epistemology, ed. J. Adam Carter, Andy Clark, Jesper Kallestrup, S. Orestis Palermos, and Duncan Pritchard, 132–154. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, Robert C. 2003. Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmela, Mikko, and Michiru Nagatsu. 2016. Collective Emotions and Joint Action. Journal of Social Ontology 2 (1): 33–57. https://doi.org/10.1515/jso-2015-0020.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, Galen. 2003. Mental Ballistics or the Involuntariness of Spontaneity. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (1): 227–256. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0066-7372.2003.00071.x.

  • Tappolet, Christine. 2000. Emotions et Valeurs. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thonhauser, Gerhard. 2018. Shared Emotions: A Steinian Proposal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17 (5): 997–1015. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-018-9561-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anja Berninger .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Berninger, A. (2019). Group Emotions and Group Epistemology. In: Candiotto, L. (eds) The Value of Emotions for Knowledge. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15667-1_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics